Protection of Conscience Project
Protection of Conscience Project
www.consciencelaws.org
Service, not Servitude

Service, not Servitude

Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan

Re: Conscientious Refusal (as revised)

5 June, 2015


Full Text
Download PDF
Abstract

Council has been given no evidence that anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been unable to access medical services or that the health of anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been adversely affected because a physician has declined to provide or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience.

The conclusion that objecting physicians "should not be obligated to provide a referral to a physician who will ultimately potentially provide the service" is entirely satisfactory. It is a tacit admission that such a policy would be an unacceptable assault on freedom of conscience.

Conscientious Refusal as revised attempts to nullify the alleged 'bias' of physicians who object to a procedure for reasons of conscience by requiring them to refer patients to a non-objecting colleague. This proposal is not sound, since, if it is to be applied fairly and consistently, the 'bias' of physicians who do not object to a procedure should be nullified in the same way. This would simply exchange one kind of alleged 'bias' for another, inconvenience patients and provide them with no better care.

The more sensible course is to require all physicians to provide patients with sufficient information to satisfy the requirements of informed medical decision making.  Physicians must advise patients at the earliest reasonable opportunity of services or procedures they decline to recommend or provide for reasons of conscience, advise affected patients that they may seek the services elsewhere, and ensure that they have sufficient information to approach other physicians, heath care workers or community organizations.  They must not promote their own moral or religious beliefs when interacting with a patient.

Physicians unwilling to abide by these requirements must promptly arrange for a patient to be seen by another physician or health care worker who is able to do so.

If the College is determined to enact a policy on conscientious refusal, it should ensure that the policy adopted is sufficiently flexible to accommodate physicians with respect to all procedures or services. Otherwise, Council should reject Conscientious Refusal as revised and postpone policy development until after the Carter decision comes into force in 2016.


TABLE OF CONTENTS

I.    Revision of draft policy - Conscientious Refusal

II.    Focus of this submission

III.    Section 5.3

IV.    Section 5.3: Suggested modification

V.    Section 2: Scope

VI.    Summary

Appendix "A" - Ontario College briefing materials

Appendix "B" - Providing Information

Appendix "C" - Conscientious Refusal and assisted suicide/euthanasia


I.    Revision of draft policy - Conscientious Refusal

I.1    The original text of Conscientious Refusal, approved in principle by College Council on 20 January, 2015 (hereinafter "CR No. 1"), was released for public consultation that generated "a very significant return" of over 4,400 responses, almost all of which opposed the policy.1 The first Protection of Conscience Project submission was made during this consultation.2

I.2    CR No. 1 was revised and re-submitted to Council on 20 March, 2015. This submission concerns the revised text (hereinafter "Conscientious Refusal as revised").3

I.3    The Project’s first submission noted that neither Mr. Salte nor the committee had provided any evidence

  •  that anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been unable to access medical services because a physician has declined to provide or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience; or
  • that the health of anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been adversely affected because a physician has declined to provide or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience.

I.4    Since Mr. Salte would surely have drawn Council’s attention to any evidence on either of these points produced by the consultation, it appears that the "very significant return" produced no evidence that such problems exist in Saskatchewan.

I.5    Council was provided with information from the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario concerning its new policy, Professional Obligations and Human Rights, including the briefing note provided to the Ontario College Council by its working group.4 Council is cautioned that the Ontario College briefing note is "deficient, erroneous and seriously misleading." (Appendix "A")

II.    Focus of this submission

II.1    The primary focus of this second submission is on three elements in Conscientious Refusal as revised:

Section 5.3

  • Deletion of the requirement to refer for a morally contested service
  •  Imposition of a requirement to refer patients for information

Section 2: Scope

  •  Non-applicability to assisted suicide and euthanasia

II.2    This submission notes that the deletion of the requirement to refer for a morally contested service is entirely satisfactory and warrants emphasis.

II.3    The imposition of a requirement to refer for information does not, strictly speaking, have a direct adverse effect on the fundamental freedoms of physicians, but it is problematic for other reasons relevant to the exercise of freedom of conscience and the expectations of the Supreme Court of Canada. For this reason, this submission treats this requirement at greater length and recommends an alternative approach to ensure that patients receive information necessary for medical decision making, without compromising physician freedom of conscience.

II.4    This submission argues that the disclaimer that Conscientious Refusal as revised will not apply to "physician assisted death" (i.e., physician administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide) is misleading and ill-advised. If the College is determined to enact a policy on conscientious refusal, it should ensure that the policy adopted is sufficiently flexible to accommodate physicians who are unwilling to do what they believe to be wrong, not excluding direct or indirect participation in killing patients or helping them commit suicide. If Council is uncertain how this can be done, it should reject Conscientious Refusal as revised and postpone policy development until after the Carter decision comes into force in 2016.

III.    Section 5.3
III.1    Deletion of requirement to refer for a morally contested service

III.1.1    The revised policy no longer requires that a physician unwilling to provide a service for reasons of conscience must facilitate the procedure by referral to a colleague who will.

III.1.2    The revision is consistent with the committee's conclusion that objecting physicians "should not be obligated to provide a referral to a physician who will ultimately potentially provide the service."5

III.1.3    This is a tacit admission that the original demand that objecting physicians must provide what the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario calls "effective referral" was an assault on freedom of conscience, not a compromise.

III.1.4    The deletion of the demand for referral is entirely satisfactory and the committee's conclusion is highly significant.

III.2    Imposition of requirement to refer patients for information

III.2.1    Instead of a demand to facilitate a morally contested service by referral, the revised policy imposes the following requirement when patients seek a service to which a physician objects for reasons of conscience:

. . . in such situations, [the physician] must make a timely referral to another physician or other health care provider who can meet the expectations of paragraph 5.2, who is willing and able to accept the patient, and if the patient decides to receive a clinically appropriate health service, that physician can either provide that treatment or refer the patient to another physician or health care provider who can provide that treatment.

III.2.    Paragraph 5.2, to which this passage refers, concerns the expectation that physicians will provide patients with the "full and balanced" (Section 4) information needed to make informed decisions about medical treatment. The accompanying memo to College Council included a practical example of what is intended by the revision:

A physician with an ethical objection to referring a patient for an abortion would not be obligated to refer a patient to an obstetrician who will perform an abortion. Rather, the physician would be obligated to refer the patient to another physician who can have an informed discussion with the patient about abortion and, if the patient after that discussion chooses to have a therapeutic abortion, refer the patient to an obstetrician willing to perform the abortion.6

III.2.3    The revision presumes that, by virtue of moral opposition to a service, a physician must be hopelessly prejudiced, duplicitous, disrespectful and incapable of providing full and balanced information. In light of Paragraph 5.2, the revision implies that physicians morally opposed to a service (like abortion) will

  • fail to advise a patient of its availability; and/or
  • fail to advise a patient of diagnosis, prognosis, and clinically appropriate treatment options; and/or
  • provide false, misleading, intentionally coercive or materially incomplete information; and/or
  • fail to communicate in a manner likely to be understood by a patient; and/or
  • communicate or otherwise behave in a manner that demeans the patient or the patient's beliefs, lifestyle, choices or values; and/or
  • promote their own religious beliefs.

III.2.4    This is not an attack on freedom of conscience. It is, however, an attack on the character and competence of objecting physicians. This confirms of one of the central points made in the Project's first submission to Council: medicine is an inescapably moral enterprise.

. . . [E]very decision concerning treatment is a moral decision, whether or not the physician specifically adverts to that fact. [VII.5.1]

 . . . Hence, the demand that physicians must not be allowed to act upon beliefs is unacceptable because it is impossible; one cannot act morally without reference to beliefs, and cannot practise medicine without reference to beliefs. . .[VII.5.4]

. . . Morality and ethics are actually intrinsic to [the practice of medicine]. Of course, some moral or ethical views may be erroneous, but that is a different matter that must be addressed by explaining why they are erroneous. It will not do to pretend, for example, that the claim that best medical practice in some circumstances means killing a patient does not involve at least implicit moral or ethical judgements.[VII.5.5]

III.2.5    Nor will it do to pretend that the claim that best medical practice means providing an abortion does not involve at least an implicit moral or ethical judgement. On the contrary: the revised policy is not an ethically or morally neutral statement. It demonstrates that committee members believe that abortion (for example) is morally or ethically acceptable and may be provided.  Recall one of the conclusions reached about the original policy in the Project's first submission:

Conscientious Refusal is not a compromise between opposite views about morally contested procedures or professional responsibilities. It is an assertion of a preference for one of the opposing views and an authoritarian attempt to compel others to conform to that preference, masked by the pretence of neutrality.[VI.5.9]

III.2.6    The revised policy does not compel objecting physicians to conform to the committee's ethical viewpoint, but, solely on the basis of their beliefs, it effectively prohibits them from communicating with their patients about morally contested procedures. This  demonstrates that the above conclusion was correct, and that the policy, even as revised, attempts to advance moral or ethical views masked by the pretence of neutrality.

III.2.7    While Project Advisor Jay Budziszewski calls this "bad faith authoritarianism,"7 it may be more appropriate, in this case, to describe it as merely unreflective authoritarianism. It is possible that committee members are so intent upon the 'bias' they perceive in those with whom they disagree that they are unaware that they are similarly 'biased' by their own moral/ethical viewpoint.

III.2.8    Nonetheless, suppose that College Council believes that it should nullify the 'bias' of physicians who object to a procedure for reasons of conscience by prohibiting them from communicating with their patients about morally contested procedures, requiring them, instead, to refer patients to a non-objecting colleague.

III.2.9    However, if this approach is sound, the College must go a step further. It must also nullify the 'bias' of physicians who do not object to a procedure. It must also prohibit physicians who do not object to abortion (for example) from communicating with their patients about it, and require them to refer patients to colleagues who do object to it.

III.2.10    As this exercise demonstrates, this approach is not sound. It does nothing more than 'protect' patients from one kind of alleged 'bias' by exposing them to another. Of course, this outcome could be avoided by allowing physicians who do not object to abortion (for example) to communicate with their patients about it, on the condition that they then refer the patient to a colleague who does object to abortion, and vice-versa. The respective physician 'biases' would then cancel each other out.

III.2.11    However, this is also unsatisfactory. It would, at a minimum, inconvenience patients, delay treatments, provide no better outcomes, double the costs of providing health care and antagonize physicians on all sides of any issue.

III.2.12    To repeat: this approach is not sound. The assumption underlying the recommendation is that a physician who has a moral viewpoint is incapable of properly communicating with a patient.  But all physicians have moral viewpoints.  Thus, if applied as now written, the policy would simply exchange one kind of 'bias' for another.  If applied fairly and consistently, the results would be ludicrous.

III.2.13    The committee's recommendation is not sound because medicine is a moral enterprise, yet the committee would have the College control for or eliminate the exercise of bona fide moral judgement. The College cannot do that fairly and consistently without grotesquely deforming medical practice. It can only do it unfairly and inconsistently by an authoritarian suppression of moral viewpoints selected arbitrarily, or selected on the basis of their unpopularity with those in positions of power and influence.

III.2.14    Such selective authoritarianism by medical regulators is a practice that squarely contradicts the repeated and eventually unanimous assertion of the full bench of the Supreme Court of Canada: that, in a free and democratic society, "the state will respect choices made by individuals and, to the greatest extent possible, will avoid subordinating these choices to any one conception of the good life."8

III.2.15    The recommended requirement to refer for information is offensive to objecting physicians for the same reasons that it would be offensive if it were applied to non-objecting physicians, but it does not, strictly speaking, immediately and adversely affect the exercise of freedom of conscience or religion.

III.2.16    However, the mindset perpetuated by such a policy is inimical to fundamental freedoms because its natural tendency is in the direction of oppression, as illustrated by developments in the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario between 2008 and 2015. It is also inconsistent with the expectations of the Supreme Court of Canada concerning the accommodation of different world views. For these reasons (in addition to those noted in III.2.10 to 13) , the Project recommends that the requirement for referral for information be modified.

IV.    Section 5.3: Suggested modification (See Appendix "B")

IV.1    Physicians must provide patients with sufficient information to make them aware of relevant treatment options so that they can make informed decisions about accepting or refusing medical treatment and care. The information must be communicated respectfully and in a way likely to be understood by the patient.9

IV.2    Physicians must disclose whether or not their religious, ethical or other conscientious convictions influence their recommendations or practice or prevent them from providing certain procedures or services.10 If medical judgement rather than moral/religious conviction is the primary consideration, it is still prudent to disclose pertinent religious or moral beliefs. The patient is also entitled to know whether or not the physician's medical opinion is consistent with the general view of the medical profession.11

IV.3    Physicians should inform patients of treatments or services that they will not provide for reasons of conscience, and notify them when their views change. Notice should be given as soon as it would be apparent to a reasonable and prudent person that a conflict is likely to arise concerning treatments or services the physician declines to provide, erring on the side of sooner rather than later. In many cases - but not all - this may be when a patient is accepted. The same holds true for notification of patients when a physician's views change significantly.

IV.4    Physicians must not promote their own moral or religious beliefs when interacting with a patient. Unless the patient questions the physician, asks for further explanation, or otherwise indicates a lack of understanding, a physician need not and probably should not expand upon the basis for his conscientious convictions.

IV.5    A physician who declines to recommend or provide services or procedures for reasons of conscience must advise affected patients that they may seek the services elsewhere, and ensure that they have sufficient information to approach other physicians, heath care workers or community organizations.

IV.6    Physicians who are unable or unwilling to comply with this section must promptly arrange for a patient to be seen by another physician or health care worker who can comply with this section.

V.    Section 2: Scope
V.1    Purported non-applicability of policy to assisted suicide and euthanasia

V.1.1    College Council has been asked to include a disclaimer in Conscientious Refusal as revised. The disclaimer states that the policy will not apply to "physician assisted death or physicians' conscientious objection related to a potential physician assisted death"12 (i.e., physician administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide).

V.1.2    The ostensible reason for this is "that this is currently an issue which is in a state of development and may be revisited by the College at a later time."13

V.1.3    Mr. Salte offered a more detailed explanation:

There is considerable uncertainty associated with physician-assisted death following the Carter decision. There may be legislation by the Federal or Provincial Government which addresses the issue before February 2016 when the Carter decision will come into effect if no new legislation is passed. The ethical implications of physician-assisted death have not been fully explored. 

The situation of physician-assisted death can be revisited later, when it is clearer whether there will be legislation that addresses the issue and, if there will be, what the legislation will state.14

V.1.4    Committee member Dr. Susan Hayton explicitly supported this, noting that "the boundaries of this whole area are very grey at the moment."15

V.1.5    However, this disclaimer is inconsistent with the origin of the policy and with previous statements by its proponents (V.2).  It is also inconsistent with previous arguments associating the provision of abortion/contraception with the provision of euthanasia/assisted suicide (V.3). Further, almost all of the principles introduced into the revised policy are as supportive of euthanasia and assisted suicide as they are of abortion and contraception (Appendix "C").

V.2    Disclaimer inconsistent with origin of policy and previous statements

V.2.1    The policy first proposed by Mr. Salte originated with the Conscience Research Group (CRG) and was virtually identical to it. The slightly modified text, approved in principle by College Council in January, 2015 as Conscientious Refusal (hereinafter "CR No.1") was also a nearly verbatim copy of the CRG policy.

V.2.2    The CRG includes two euthanasia activists. One of them - Professor Jocelyn Downie - co-wrote the CRG policy largely replicated in CR No. 1. They were and are of the view that health care workers unwilling to kill patients or help them kill themselves should be forced to find someone else willing to do so.16 Thus, the CRG policy is meant to apply to all "legally permissible and publicly funded health services" - which, beginning in 2016, will include euthanasia and assisted suicide.

V.2.3    Consistent with this, when, in 2014, Mr. Salte urged the registrars of all Canadian Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons to adopt a uniform coercive policy of the kind he and the CRG were proposing, he did not refer to abortion or contraception. Instead, he wrote, "Physician-assisted suicide, in particular, has the potential to challenge Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons to provide guidance to its members."17

V.2.4    Further, when - with a virtual clone of the CRG group’s text in his back pocket, so to speak - Mr. Salte proposed that the College adopt a policy on "ethical objection," he identified assisted suicide as one of a list of "issues which have resulted in controversy" - the others being abortion, birth control, fetal sex identification and genetic testing.18

V.2.5    After the Carter decision, anticipating the legalization of physician administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, Mr. Salte stated publicly that CR No. 1 was intended to apply "broadly,"not only to "birth control and abortion," but "all other areas," not excluding physician assisted suicide and euthanasia. He explicitly confirmed that doctors who disagree with assisted suicide could "end up being disciplined," and "could . . . lose their jobs."19

V.2.6    The statement is not surprising. Mr. Salte’s willingness to discipline and dismiss physicians who refuse to participate in killing patients or helping them to commit suicide reflects an attitude entirely faithful to the source of the policy. It is also consistent with his explicit association of assisted suicide with the policy from the very beginning, and his linking of assisted suicide with abortion and birth control. Mr. Salte has said nothing to indicate that his attitude will be any different once the Carter decision comes into effect.

V.2.7    The Canadian Medical Protective Association (CMPA) took note of the CR No. 1 requirement that objecting physicians actually provide "all health services that are legally available and publicly funded" if referral were not possible or would cause a delay jeopardizing a patient’s "health or well being." The CMPA understood this would include providing euthanasia and assisted suicide once Carter came into effect.20

V.3    Disclaimer inconsistent with association of abortion/birth control and euthanasia/assisted suicide

V.3.1    It has been noted that the policy first proposed by Mr. Salte and CR No.1 are nearly verbatim copies of the CRG policy, produced by a group including two euthanasia activists, one of whom co-wrote the CRG policy. They argue that health care workers unwilling to kill patients or help them kill themselves should be forced to find someone else willing to do so because (they claim) it is agreed that health care workers who refuse to provide abortion and birth control can and should be compelled to refer patients to someone who will.21

V.3.2    It should be obvious that this claim is sharply contested, but it demonstrates clearly that arguments supporting a policy of coerced participation in abortion and birth control also support a policy of coerced participation in euthanasia and assisted suicide.

V.3.3    Consistent with this, when Mr. Salte proposed that the College adopt a policy on "ethical objection," he explicitly associated assisted suicide with abortion, birth control, fetal sex identification and genetic testing when indicating the potential scope of the policy (V.2.4). After the Carter decision, he again explicitly associated abortion and birth control with euthanasia and physician assisted suicide (V.2.5).

V.4    Dissecting the disclaimer

V.4.1    The reasons offered to support the disclaimer are unsatisfactory.

V.4.2    In the first place, almost every one of the principles that has been added to Section 1 of the revised policy has already been used to support demands that physicians should be forced to facilitate euthanasia and assisted suicide (Appendix "C"). Certainly, arguments based on those principles are disputed. However, one would have to be hopelessly naive, boundlessly optimistic or simply disingenuous to suggest that the principles cannot or will not be used to support coerced involvement in euthanasia and assisted suicide.

V.4.3    Second, when Mr. Salte proposed the coercive policy in July, 2014, it was well known that the Supreme Court of Canada might well legalize physician assisted suicide and euthanasia. That possibility had become a widespread prediction by the time the committee returned CR No. 1 to Council for approval in principle in January, 2015, but there was no reference to the "very grey" areas later discovered by Dr. Hayton. And Mr. Salte continued to advocate for the coercive policy even after the ruling in Carter.

V.4.4    Recall that, when Mr. Salte urged the registrars of all Canadian Colleges to adopt a policy forcing objecting physicians to refer for morally contested procedures, he specifically noted its importance in relation to physician-assisted suicide (V.2.3). He did not then express concern that "the ethical implications of physician assisted dying [had] not been fully explored." Why not?

V.4.5    Again, when Mr. Salte proposed that the College adopt a policy on "ethical objection," he included assisted suicide among the list of controversial services (V.2.4). He did not then suggest that the College wait to see "whether there will be legislation that addresses the issue and, if there will be, what the legislation will state." Why not?

V.4.6    After the Supreme Court of Canada ordered the legalization of euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, Mr. Salte stated publicly that CR No. 1 was intended to apply "broadly," to all areas of practice, not excluding physician assisted suicide and euthanasia. He did not then worry that there was "considerable uncertainty associated with physician-assisted death." He did not then say, "This is currently an issue which is in a state of development." On the contrary, he defended the proposition that physicians should be disciplined or fired if they refuse to at least help to find someone willing to kill patients or help them commit suicide (V.2.5, V.2.6). Why so bold then, so cautious now?

V.5    Explaining the disclaimer

V.5.1    The timing of the shift in attitude suggests an answer. All of the concerns about "ethical implications," "grey areas," "considerable uncertainty," and lack of legislation  arose suddenly in March, 2015 - that is, just after Mr. Salte and the committee were confronted by overwhelming opposition to CR No. 1.

V.5.2    The introduction of the disclaimer could be seen as a mere tactical withdrawal: an attempt to secure passage of the policy, at least in some form, by defusing opposition that has been amplified by the pending legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia. Supporters of CR No. 1 may simply be prepared to wait, expecting to have an easier time imposing a policy that will force physicians to do what they believe to be wrong once physicians and the public have become as comfortable with assisted suicide and euthanasia as they are with abortion and contraception.

V.5.3    On the other hand, a less Machiavellian explanation is available. The disclaimer may indicate that committee members have begun to realize that if the College can force physicians to do what they believe to be wrong with respect to abortion and contraception, there would seem to be no reason why the College should not also be able to force physicians to do what they believe to be wrong with respect to killing patients and helping them commit suicide. That would explain Mr. Salte’s suggestion that the Council "may wish to consider whether there is something different about physician assisted death that should result in it being addressed differently than other issues of conscientious objection."22

V.6    Disposing of the disclaimer

V.6.1    Mr. Salte appears to be inviting College Council to declare that objecting physicians need not facilitate euthanasia and physician assisted suicide because killing patients is morally contentious, but objecting physician must facilitate abortion, contraception, fetal sex selection (and perhaps other procedures) because they are morally acceptable and contrary views are erroneous.

V.6.2    Council should decline the invitation because declarations of that kind are beyond its competence, and enacting policies that give effect to such dogmatic positions would be an abuse of its authority.  For the same reasons, it would be unacceptable to propose a policy to limit the exercise of freedom of conscience with respect to some procedures or services and not others.

V.6.3    In view of V.2, V.3. V.4 and Appendix "B," it is unrealistic to believe that Conscientious Refusal as revised will not be applied to physician administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, either directly, after a certain length of time, or indirectly, as a paradigm for further policy development.

V.6.4    Including the disclaimer in the policy is thus misleading and ill-advised. If the College is determined to enact a policy on conscientious refusal, it should ensure that the policy adopted is sufficiently flexible to accommodate physicians who are unwilling to do what they believe to be wrong, not excluding direct or indirect participation in killing patients or helping them commit suicide. If Council is uncertain how this can be done, it should reject Conscientious Refusal as revised and postpone policy development until after the Carter decision comes into force in 2016.

VI.    Summary

VI.1    A public consultation that produced a very significant return" produced no evidence that anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been unable to access medical services because a physician has declined to provide or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience, or that the health of anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been adversely affected because a physician has declined to provide or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience.

VI.2    The revised policy has withdrawn the demand that physicians unwilling to provide a service for reasons of conscience must facilitate the procedure by referral to a colleague who will. This is entirely satisfactory. It is also a tacit and significant admission that compelling physicians to facilitate services to which they object for reasons of conscience is an unacceptable assault on freedom of conscience. The statement, "Objecting physicians should not be obligated to provide a referral to a physician who will ultimately potentially provide the service" should be included in the text of the policy itself.

VI.3    Conscientious Refusal as revised effectively prohibits objecting physicians from communicating with their patients about morally contested procedures. It presumes that, by virtue of moral opposition to a service, a physician must be hopelessly prejudiced, duplicitous, disrespectful and incapable of providing full and balanced information. The suggested revision provides clear and convincing evidence that the College committee continues to advance moral and ethical views masked by the pretence of neutrality.

VI.4    The committee’s recommendation would have the College control for or eliminate the exercise of bona fide moral judgement. The College can only do that unfairly and inconsistently by an authoritarian suppression of moral viewpoints selected arbitrarily, or because they are unpopular. Such selective authoritarianism contradicts direction from the Supreme Court of Canada that requires accommodation of different world views.

VI.5    Physicians who, for reasons of conscience, are unable or unwilling to provide patients with sufficient information to satisfy the requirements of informed medical decision making must promptly arrange for a patient to be seen by another physician or health care worker who is able to do so.

VI.6    Physicians should inform patients of treatments or services that they will not provide for reasons of conscience as soon as it appears that a conflict is likely to arise. The same holds true for notification of patients when a physician’s views change significantly.

VI.7    A physician who declines to recommend or provide services or procedures for reasons of conscience must advise affected patients that they may, if they wish, approach other physicians, heath care workers or community organizations to obtain the services, and ensure that they have sufficient information to do so.

VI.8    It is unrealistic to believe that a policy concerning the exercise of freedom of conscience will not be applied to euthanasia and assisted suicide.  If the College is determined to enact a policy on conscientious refusal, it should ensure that the policy adopted is sufficiently flexible to accommodate physicians with respect to all procedures or services. Otherwise, Council should reject Conscientious Refusal as revised and postpone policy development until after the Carter decision comes into force in 2016.


Notes

1.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Policy on Conscientious Objection, 9 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 38/15) p. 3.

2.  Protection of Conscience Project, Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan Re: Conscientious Refusal, 5 March, 2015

3.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy- Conscientious Objection, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15) p. 10-17.

4.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy- Conscientious Objection, 23 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 75/15) p. 4-11.

5.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy- Conscientious Objection, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15) p. 5.

6.  Salte BE.  Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy- Conscientious Objection, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15) p. 7

7.  "The question of neutrality has been profoundly obscured by the mistake of confusing neutrality with objectivity... neutrality and objectivity are not the same... objectivity is possible but neutrality is not. To be neutral, if that were possible, would be to have no presuppositions whatsoever. To be objective is to have certain presuppositions, along with the manners that allow us to keep faith with them." Budziszewski J., "Handling Issues of Conscience." The Newman Rambler, Vol. 3, No. 2, Spring/Summer 1999, P. 4.

8.  R. v. Morgentaler  (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 166. (Accessed 2015-02-26); R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654, Québec (Curateur public) c. Syndicat national des employés de l'Hôpital St-Ferdinand, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 211 (Accessed 2015-03-05).

9.  Canadian Medical Association Code of Ethics (2004): "22. Make every reasonable effort to communicate with your patients in such a way that information exchanged is understood." (Accessed 2014-02-22)

10.  Canadian Medical Association Code of Ethics (2004): "12. Inform your patient when your personal values would influence the recommendation or practice of any medical procedure that the patient needs or wants." (Accessed 2014-02-22)

11.  Canadian Medical Association Code of Ethics (2004): "45. Recognize a responsibility to give generally held opinions of the profession when interpreting scientific knowledge to the public; when presenting an opinion that is contrary to the generally held opinion of the profession, so indicate." (Accessed 2014-02-22)

12.  Policy: Conscientious Refusal-2: Scope. In Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy, Conscientious Objection, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15) , p. 10-11,14-15.

13.   Policy: Conscientious Refusal-2: Scope. In Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy, Conscientious Objection, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15) , p. 10-11,14-15.

14.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Draft Policy, Conscientious Objection,, 20 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 73/15), p. 5.

15.   Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Policy on Conscientious Objection, 9 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 38/15) p. 12.

16.  Professor Jocelyn Downie and Professor Daniel Weinstock are members of the faculty of the "Conscience Research Group"  (CRG), the ulitmate source of the policy first proposed by Mr. Salte (See Protection of Conscience Project, Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan Re: Conscientious Refusal, Appendices "A" and "B."  With Udo Schuklenk and others, they were members of a Royal Society of Canada panel of "experts" who recommended that health care workers unwilling to provide euthanasia or assisted suicide should be compelled to refer patients to someone who would do so. See Schuklenk U, van Delden J.J.M, Downie J, McLean S, Upshur R, Weinstock D. Report of the Royal Society of Canada Expert Panel on End-of-Life Decision Making (November, 2011) p. 101 (Accessed 2014-02-23).  Referring to the Supreme Court of Canada hearing in Carter, Shcuklenk noted the Project's joint intervention asking the Court to "direct parliament to ensure that health care professionals would not be forced to assist in dying if they had conscientious objections."  He commented, "I am not a fan of conscientious objection rights anyway, so I hope the Court will ignore this." Schuklenk U.  "Supreme Court of Canada heard arguments in Charter challenge to assisted dying criminalisation." Udo Schuklenk's Ethx Blog, T, Thursday, October 16, 2014 (Accessed 2015-02-22)

17.  Letter from Bryan Salte to the Registrars of Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons in Canada. Redacted in Document 200/14, College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan, Report to Council from the Registrar, 31 July, 2014, p. 8.

18.  Salte B. Memorandum to Council re: Possible Policy or Guideline - Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical services, 31 July, 2014 (CPSS No. 200/14).

19.  "Saskatchewan doctors could face discipline over assisted suicide." Global News, 13 February, 2015 (Accessed 2015-05-30). Annotated transcription at Protection of Conscience Project, Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan, Re: Conscientious Refusal, Appendix "C": Interview of Associate Registrar, College of Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan Re: CPSS Draft Policy Conscientious Refusal, CI.2, CI.3; CIII.2 to CIII.4, CIV.1, CV.1

20.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Policy on Conscientious Objection, 9 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 38/15) p. 9-10.

21.  Schuklenk U, van Delden J.J.M, Downie J, McLean S, Upshur R, Weinstock D. Report of the Royal Society of Canada Expert Panel on End-of-Life Decision Making (November, 2011) p. 62 (Accessed 2014-02-23).

22.  Salte BE. Memorandum to Council re: Policy on Conscientious Objection, 9 March, 2015 (CPSS No. 38/15) p. 1.

 | Next