Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Saskatchewan
Re: Conscientious Refusal
5 March, 2015
Full Text
Abstract
The policy Conscientious Refusal requires all physicians who
object to a procedure for reasons of conscience to facilitate the procedure
by referring patients to a colleague who will provide it, even if it is
homicide or suicide. No evidence was provided to justify the policy. None of the arguments
provided to Council justify the policy, nor do the principles included in
the text.
Conscientious Refusal fails to recognize that the practice of
medicine is a moral enterprise, that morality is a human enterprise, and
that physicians, no less than patients, are moral agents.
The original text virtually copied by Conscientious Refusal was written
by believers: by people who believe that whatever is "legally permissible
and publicly-funded" is morally acceptable- including euthanasia, assisted
suicide and abortion. It is an assertion of those beliefs and an
authoritarian attempt to compel others to conform to them. It is a partisan
document that is profoundly disrespectful of the moral agency of physicians,
not a compromise.
Conscientious Refusal advances the dangerous idea that a learned
or privileged class, a profession or state institutions can legitimately
compel people to do what they believe to be wrong and punish them if they
refuse. This is not a limitation of fundamental freedoms, but a serious
violation of human dignity. It is also incoherent, because it posits the
existence of a moral or ethical duty to do what one believes to be wrong.
The Associate Registrar has made it clear that those who refuse to do
what the policy demands will be disciplined by the College or forced out of
the medical profession. This clashes seriously with the approach taken by
the Supreme Court of Canada, which has affirmed that public policy must make
room for physicians whose "concept of the good life" precludes their
participation in abortion, euthanasia, assisted suicide or other morally
contested procedures.
The burden of proof was on the Associate Registrar and the appointed
committee to prove beyond doubt that Conscientious Refusal is
justified and that no less authoritarian alternatives are available. They
failed to discharge that burden; neither has College Council discharged it.
The policy should be withdrawn.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
I. Origin of the draft policy, Conscientious Refusal
II. Content of the proposed policy
III. Focus of this submission
IV. Justification for the proposed policy
V. The issues
VI. Response to the issues
VII. Discussion
VIII. Conclusions
Appendix "A": Origin of the CPSS Draft Policy
Appendix "B": Development of the CPSS Draft Policy
Appendix "C": Interview of
CPSS Associate Registrar
Appendix "D": Ontario, Alberta, Manitoba and Saskatchewan College Policies
Appendix "E": College of
Physicians and Surgeons of Saskatchewan Re: Guideline:
Unplanned
Pregnancy
Appendix "F": Morally
Significant Participation
Appendix "G": Notes on Referral,
Abandonment and Fiduciary Duty
I. Origin of the draft policy,
Conscientious Refusal
I.1 The text of the draft policy, Conscientious
Refusal, originates in a model conscientious objection policy drafted by
members of the Conscience Research Group (CRG). The Group includes
euthanasia/assisted suicide and abortion activists who are determined to
force physicians who are unwilling to provide abortions, kill patients or help them
commit suicide to find a colleague willing to do so. Having been unable to
convince the Canadian Medical Association to adopt such a policy, they
decided to convince provincial regulatory authorities to impose it (Appendix
"A").
I.2 It appears that Saskatchewan
Associate Registrar Bryan Salten was among the participants at a meeting
convened by the Conscience Research
Group in 2013 to further this objective. The proposed CRG
policy was presented and discussed. Mr. Salte left the meeting with the text
agreed upon by meeting participants, almost an exact duplicate of what the
CRG published later in 2013 as its Model Conscientious Objection Policy
(MCOP). (Appendix "B", BII.)
I.3 Subsequently, Mr. Salte appears to have taken on
the project of convincing regulatory authorities to adopt what he called the
"draft policy statement developed by the Conscientious Objections Working
Group."
I.4 Mr. Salte appears to have led discussion of the
subject at a meeting of the Registrars of British Columbia, Alberta,
Saskatchewan, Manitoba and Ontario on 5 May, 2014. He said that there there
seemed to be a "consensus" among the Registrars that provincial Colleges should
consider adopting the policy (Appendix "B",
BIII). Two months later, he wrote
to all of the Registrars of Colleges of Physicians in Canada, providing them
with a copy of it and urging them to do just that. He advised them that
Saskatchewan’s College Council would be considering the policy at its
upcoming meeting (Appendix "B", BV).
The Council was not meeting until September, so it is not certain that, at
the time Mr. Salte wrote to the other Colleges, Council members were aware
of what he had in store for them.
I.5 Making explicit reference to the possibility of the
legalization of physician assisted suicide, and explicitly acknowledging
that the subject was potentially "very controversial," Mr. Salte urged all
Canadian Registrars to adopt a uniform policy - obviously, the one he was
proposing to them, or one much like it. He argued that this was necessary to
ensure that no College was placed in the difficult position of being an
"outlier" on such a controversial subject (Appendix "B",
BV).
I.6 Since the policy he was proposing would require
physicians unwilling to kill patients or help them commit suicide to help
find a colleague willing to do the killing, it seems
obvious that his intention was to make this the ethical standard for medical
practice throughout Canada. In the face of the historic opposition of the
Canadian Medical Association and the controversy attending demands for
compulsory referral, it is not surprising that Mr. Salte seems to have
adopted the CRG strategy of suppressing opposition by a unilateral and
monolithic exercise of regulatory power.
I.7 College Council discussed the memo provided by Mr.
Salte at its September, 2014 meeting. The memo included a draft policy
virtually identical to the CRG’s Model Conscientious Objection Policy.
(Appendix "B", Note 6)
I.8 It is significant that Mr. Salte took care to avoid
identifying the Conscience Research Group as the ultimate source of the
policy. Instead, he identified the participants in the meeting noted in
I.2 as "the Conscientious Objections Working Group" - "a
group that was formed with a grant to study and provide recommendations to
Canadian Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons" concerning physician
conscientious objection.1 This was at
least a misleading oversimplification, if not a misrepresentation.
I.9 The committee formed to study the question met
once, and no minutes were kept. The committee added a sentence to
Conscientious Refusal that warns physicians not to promote their moral or
religious beliefs, and deleted references to discipline and complaints they
considered superfluous. For the rest, the few textual differences that exist
between Conscientious Refusal and MCOP are not significant (Appendix
"A"). On 20 January, Council approved the policy in principle and
authorized external consultation.
II. Content of the proposed
policy
II.1 Conscientious Refusal is divided into
several sections. The two sections of concern are "Principles" and
"Obligations."
II.2 Under "Principles" one finds broad statements that are apparently
intended to provide the foundation for the obligations that follow.
However, some of the principles and some of the terminology used serves no
purpose apart from providing a rhetorical pretext for the coercive and
tendentious elements found later in the policy, and are, moreover,
misleading with respect to the obligations of physicians.
II.3 The Obligations include some commonplace duties that
are uncontroversial, others that require qualification if they are to be broadly
acceptable, and purported obligations that are advanced in order to force
objecting physicians to do what they believe to be wrong. These are disputed, and are
the focus of this submission.
III. Focus of this submission
III.1 This submission focuses on two passages in Conscientious Refusal:
5.3 Providing referrals for health
services
Physicians can decline to provide legally permissible and
publicly-funded health services if providing those services violates their freedom of conscience.
However, in such situations, they must make a timely referral to another
health care provider who is willing and able to accept the patient and
provide the service.
5.4 Treating patients
When a referral
to another health care provider is not possible without causing a delay that
would jeopardize the patient's health or well-being,
physicians must provide the
patient with all health services that are legally permissible and
publicly-funded and that are consented to by the patient or . . . substitute
decision maker. This obligations holds even in circumstances where the
provision of health services conflicts with physicians' deeply held and
considered moral or religious beliefs.
III.2 During an interview in February, 2015, Mr.
Salte confirmed that, if the policy is adopted, physicians will be expected
to do what they believe to be wrong, including referral
for assisted suicide(Appendix "C",
CIII.4). He
made it clear that, if the policy is approved, physicians unwilling to
comply could face discipline, including cancellation of their licenses to
practice, since refusing to arrange for a colleague to help a patient commit
suicide would be considered "unacceptable or unprofessional."(Appendix "C",
CV.I)
III.3 This is a dangerous and extraordinarily
authoritarian policy that is completely at odds with liberal democratic
aspirations and Canadian traditions. The burden of proof was on Mr. Salte
and the appointed committee to prove beyond doubt that it is justified and
that no reasonable alternatives to the policy are available.
IV. Justification for the proposed policy
IV.1 Taking note of controversial ethical issues like
abortion, contraception, assisted suicide, fetal sex selection and genetic
testing, Mr. Salte observed that strong views "from different perspectives"
had been expressed during a consultation underway in Ontario about
Physicians and the Human Rights Code. He then asserted that the draft
policy had the support of the Registrars of B.C., Alberta, Manitoba and
Ontario.
My perspective is that if there can be a consistent
position across Canada, it will greatly help in addressing this difficult
issue, which many people feel very strongly about.
As a member of the conscientious objections working
group which developed the recommendations I am not unbiased. However, I
think that a document which generally follows what is in the document would
be useful to establish expectations for physicians and guidance to the
College when it deals with physicians who have ethical or moral objections
to providing certain forms of care.2
IV.2 The argument was supported by a newspaper article
quoting an ethicist who claimed that objecting physicians are obliged to
refer for morally contested services (Appendix "B",
BVI.3) and a paper from a
professional journal reporting the results of a survey of opinions of 154
physicians in a Wisconsin faculty of medicine (Appendix "B",
BVI.4).
IV.3 Mr. Salte also provided the newspaper article
about the Calgary physician who was refusing to prescribe contraceptives,
apparently as evidence supporting the argument. The article did not
make clear that no patient had been denied contraception or had been unable
to obtain it, and concluded with a sentence erroneously implying that the
Alberta College of Physicians had a policy requiring objecting physicians to
refer for morally contested procedures (Appendix "B",
BIV).
IV.4 Attachments to the memo included policies of the
Ontario,3 Alberta4
and Manitoba5 Colleges of Physicians and
the Saskatchewan College policy on Unplanned Pregnancy.6
He extracted two sections of the Saskatchewan policy and highlighted them in
the memo:
Any physician who is unable to be involved in the
further care and management of any patient when termination of the pregnancy
might be contemplated should inform the patient and make and expeditious
referral to another available physician.
5) Will fully apprise the patient of the options she
may pursue and provide her with accurate information relating to community
agencies and services that may be of assistance to her in pursuing each
option.7
IV.5 The documents and quotes noted in IV.4 could
create the
impression that a policy of mandatory referral by objecting physicians
existed elsewhere and was already the policy of the College in Saskatachewan
with respect to abortion.
IV.6 Contrary to the impression that may have been
created by Mr. Salte's memo, the policies he provided do not require an
objecting physician to refer a patient to a colleague who will provide a
morally contested service (Appendix "D",
"E"). In this regard, it is
disturbing to find that Mr. Salter later publicly made this claim, which is
false (Appendix "C",
CIII.1,
CIII.1-note).
IV.7 Discounting the policies noted in
IV.4, the argument and evidence presented by Mr. Salte
can be summarized as follows.
Since
-
people have strongly held ethical or moral convictions
about killing developing infants in utero, helping
people to commit suicide, killing fetuses for reasons of sex, genetic testing
and provision of contraception; and
-
by virtue of their strong convictions, some physicians are unwilling to do such
things or to arrange for them to be done because they consider them evil, even
if legal; and
-
other people of equally strong convictions want physicians made to
provide these services or arrange for them because they are legal, and are upset
if they refuse; and
-
less than half of physicians surveyed in a
Wisconsin University believe that objecting physicians have an
obligation to refer for morally contested procedures, and a Canadian
ethicist agrees; and
-
participants in closed meetings held in 2013 and 2014
also think physicians unwilling to
provide morally contested services for reasons of conscience should be forced to
facilitate them by referral or other means; and
-
it is administratively prudent for regulators to adopt a uniform and consistent
policy across the country;
therefore,
-
physicians unwilling to kill developing infants
in utero, kill people or help them to commit suicide, kill
fetuses for reasons of sex, or unwilling to provide any other legal
service for reasons of conscience are ethically obliged help to arrange
for the services to be provided by someone else, and should be punished
if they refuse.
Hence, the policy Conscientious Refusal is
justified.
IV.8 As noted in II, the policy
includes principles that purport to justify the obligations
Conscientious Refusal would impose.
IV.9 There is no indication that the Council had before
it or asked for any other arguments, reasons or evidence before it when it
approved Conscientious Refusal in principle. However, Mr.
Salte subsequently claimed that the policy was a compromise (Appendix "C",
CV.4).
V. The issues
V.1 Does the proposed policy adversely affect freedom
of conscience or religion?
V.2 If the policy adversely affects freedom of
conscience or religion, is it, nonetheless, justified by
evidence provided to Council?
V.3 If the policy adversely affects freedom of
conscience or religion, is it, nonetheless, justified by
the arguments provided to Council?
V.4 If the policy adversely affects freedom of
conscience or religion, is it, nonetheless, justified by the principles
included in the policy?
V.5 Is the policy a compromise?
VI. Response to the issues
VI.1 Does the proposed policy adversely affect freedom
of conscience or religion?
VI.1.1 To the extent that the policy requires some physicians to do
what they believe to be wrong, the policy Conscientious
Refusal adversely affects freedom of conscience or religion.
VI.1.2 Killing patients, helping patients commit
suicide, and the killing of infants developing in utero are
understood to be the subject of significant moral and ethical disagreement,
both inside and outside the medical profession. While these procedures
generate the most notable disagreement, moral and ethical disputes are
entangled around other issues as well, such as contraception and eugenics.
Mr. Salte's memo explicitly adverts to this. The existence of
these controversies is one of the elements in his justification of the
policy.
VI.1.3 The policy Conscientious Refusal affects
physicians unwilling to kill patients or help them commit suicide for
reasons of conscience or religion. Indeed, Mr. Salte has explicitly
stated that the policy was developed with physician assisted suicide in mind
(I.5, III.2). In addition, the
policy is applicable to physicians who, for reasons of conscience or
religion, refuse to kill developing infants in utero or to provide
other legal, publicly-funded services.
VI.1.4 Conscientious Refusal requires all
such physicians to facilitate the services by referring patients to a
colleague who will provide them. This is widely recognized as a form
of morally significant participation (Appendix "F").
VI.1.5 The policy demands that physicians do what they
believe to be wrong - even gravely wrong - even arranging homicide or
suicide. Mr. Salte is clear that those who refuse to do what the
policy demands will be disciplined by the College or forced out of the
medical profession (Appendix "C",
CV.1).
VI.1.6 Conclusion: The policy
Conscientious Refusal adversely affects freedom of conscience and
religion.
VI.2 Is the policy justified by
evidence provided to Council?
VI.2.1 Given the obligations of the College, it might be reasonable
for Council to adopt
Conscientious Refusal if it were demonstrated that the policy is
necessary to ensure that medical practice in the province is safe,
competent, ethical and safeguards the health of patients.
Evidence not provided
VI.2.2 Neither Mr. Salte nor the committee provided
any evidence
-
that anyone in Saskatchewan has ever been unable
to access medical services because a physician has declined to provide
or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience; or
-
that the health of anyone in Saskatchewan has
ever been adversely affected because a physician has declined to provide
or refer for a procedure for reasons of conscience; or
-
that physicians who refuse to do what they
believe to be wrong are guilty of unethical practice.
The evidence provided
VI.2.3 The only evidence provided to Council concerned a
complaint by a woman about a Calgary physician who does not prescribe
contraceptives. The woman who complained does not appear to have been her patient. She was
simply angry because the physician was not prescribing
contraceptives. There is no evidence that she was refused a
prescription or that she or anyone else was unable to access contraceptives
because of the physician's practice (Appendix "B",
BIV).
VI.2.4 Conclusion:
No evidence was provided to justify the policy.
VI.3 Is the policy justified by the arguments provided
to Council?
VI.3.1 Given the obligations of the College, it might be reasonable
for Council to adopt
Conscientious Refusal if it were provided with arguments demonstrating
that the policy is necessary to ensure that medical practice in the province
is safe, competent, ethical and safeguards the health of patients.
Arguments not offered
VI.3.2 Neither Mr. Salte nor the committee argued
-
that
medical practice in Saskatchewan will be unsafe unless Conscientious Refusal
is adopted; or
-
that Conscientious Refusal is necessary to ensure the competence of medical
practice in Saskatchewan; or
-
that anyone in Saskatchewan will be unable to
access medical services if physicians decline to provide or refer for a
procedure for reasons of conscience; or
-
that the health of anyone in Saskatchewan will be
at risk if physicians decline to provide or refer for a procedure for
reasons of conscience; or
-
that physicians who refuse to do what they
believe to be wrong are guilty of unethical practice.
The argument offered
VI.3.3 The argument offered began with the reasonable
observation that there are markedly different ethical or moral beliefs
concerning legal and publicly funded (or soon to be legal and publicly
funded) controversial procedures like assisted suicide, euthanasia and
abortion, and conflicts are likely to arise between patients who want these
services and physicians unwilling to provide them.
VI.3.4 However, this observation alone was merely
descriptive of a present or anticipated state of affairs: a description of
an "is." The mere fact of disagreement was not sufficient to
justify the conclusion that objecting physicians ought to be forced to
provide or refer for the services. Something more was needed.
Mr. Salte offered something more in the form of appeals to authority, and
appeal to consensus, and a
claim that priority should be given to administrative convenience.
VI.3.5 Appeals to authority
VI.3.5.a Mr. Salte appealed to the authority of a single ethicist,
Arthur Schafer, who believes that objecting physicians are obliged to help
patients obtain the procedures to which they object by referral (Appendix
"B", BVI.3).
VI.3.5.b Mr. Salte appealed to the authority of the
collective opinion of less than half the faculty of Family Medicine at the
University of Wisconsin, as derived by a survey conducted in 2011. (Appendix "B",
BVI.4).
VI.3.6 Appeal to consensus
VI.3.6.a Mr. Salte also appealed to the consensus of largely (and
sometimes purposefully) unidentified participants in closed meetings held in
2013 and 2014. He argued that the consensus arising from these meetings was
that objecting physicians should be forced to help patients obtain legal and
publicly-funded services (which will now include euthanasia and assisted
suicide) (Appendix "B", BII,
BIII).
VI.3.7 Claim of administrative convenience
VI.3.7.a The final reason offered by Mr. Salte to adopt
Conscientious Refusal was his concern that the failure to adopt a uniform
and consistent policy across the country would prove to be troublesome for
College administrators. In his view, "ethical standards for medical
practice should be very similar across Canada, and that it should be
possible for Canadian Colleges to adopt a common approach." (Appendix "B",
BV.)
Response to the argument
VI.3.8 Appeals to authority
VI.3.8.a An appeal to authority may be appropriate
within a defined community in which the authority is recognized. Within
Canada, a point of law may be settled by citing a ruling of the Supreme
Court of Canada, for example. However, an appeal to authority on points of
morality or ethics is not appropriate within a pluralist society composed of
people and groups with different and sometimes opposing concepts of good and
evil.
VI.3.8.b In this situation it is customary in Canada to
adopt the advice of Madame Justice Bertha Wilson of the Supreme Court of
Canada in R v. Morgentaler with respect to how the conscientious
judgement of an individual should stand against that of the state. Her
answer was that, in a free and democratic society, "the state will respect
choices made by individuals and, to the greatest extent possible, will avoid
subordinating these choices to any one conception of the good life," and
that the state should not endorse and enforce "one conscientiously-held view
at the expense of another." (VII.12)
VI.3.8.c With respect to Arthur Schafer's opinion,
other ethicists disagree with him. Mr. Salte did not explain why he chose to
ignore the opinions of ethicists who disagree with Mr. Schafer, nor did he
explain why the College should endorse and enforce Mr. Schafer's view at the
expense of those who disagree with him.
VI.3.8.d The same thing can be said with respect to the
opinions of faculty members at the University of Wisconsin. In addition, the
author of the paper provided by Mr. Salte cautioned that the research cannot
be used in the way Mr. Salte would have it used. (Appendix "B",
BVI.5).
VI.3.9 Appeal to consensus
VI.3.9.a Concerning the "consensus" of participants at
the meetings described by Mr. Salte, it is not difficult to arrive at a
consensus concerning a policy by excluding from discussion anyone likely to
disagree with it.
VI.3.9.b The first of these meetings appears to have
been organized and controlled by the CRG activists who meant to have their
Model Conscientious Objection Policy aadopted by the Colleges. Invitations
were probably sent to those known to be supportive or MCOP or those thought
likely to agree with it, while those known to disagree or likely to disagree
with it being deliberately excluded.(Appendix "B",
BII.).
VI.3.9.c The second meeting was limited to officials
from different Colleges (Appendix "B",
BIII.). Groups likely to be opposed
to a policy of mandatory referral were not present, even if the meeting was
not deliberately structured to exclude them.
VI.3.9.d Such a contrived "consensus" is certainly
useful for the purpose of advancing an ideological position at the expense
of the conscientiously-held views of others, and for subordinating them to
the conception of the good life favoured by CRG activists and College
administrators. However, a contrived and partisan consensus is not capable
of justifying the suppression of the fundamental freedoms.
VI.3.10 Administrative convenience
VI.3.10.a While a uniform policy would obviously be much
more convenient for administrators, Mr. Salte did not explain why either the
CRG's Model Conscientious Objection Policy or its virtual clone,
Conscientious Refusal, should be that policy.
VI.3.10.b Neither Mr. Salte nor the committee offered a
single ethical argument to support the claim that Conscientious Refusal
should be an 'ethical standard for medical practice.'
Summary
VI.3.11 Neither Mr. Salte nor the committee argued that
Conscientious Refusal is necessary to ensure that medical practice in the
province is safe, competent, ethical and is necessary to ensure that medical practice in the
province is safe, competent, ethical and safeguards the health of patients.
VI.3.12 Mr. Salte attempted to justify Conscientious
Refusal by appealing to the authority of opinion of half of a Wisconsin University faculty and the opinion of a single ethicist. However, the former
approach is invalid for empirical reasons, and the latter is unsatisfactory
in a pluralist society.
VI.3.13 Mr. Salte's appeal to a contrived and partisan
"consensus" is an unacceptable form of manipulation, not an adequate
justification of the policy.
VI.3.14 Even if it is administratively convenient for
Canadian regulators to adopt a common ethical standard for medical practice,
neither Mr. Salte nor the committee offered a single argument to prove that
Conscientious Refusal should be that standard.
VI.3.15 Conclusion:
No argument was provided to Council that demonstrates that Conscientious
Refusal is necessary to ensure that medical practice in the province is
safe, competent, ethical, or to safeguard the health of patients. No
argument was provided to prove that Conscientious Refusal
should be an ethical standard of medical practice.
VI.4 Is the policy justified by the principles
included in the policy?
VI.4.1 A number of the principles set out in
Conscientious Refusal might, at first glance, seem to justify the
conclusion that physicians should be made to do what they believe to be
wrong.
VI.4.2 "The College of Physicians and Surgeons
has an obligation to serve and protect the public
interest."
VI.4.2.a This obligation applies generally to every
government or state institution.
VI.4.2.b The College serves and protects the public
interest by attending to its statutory responsibilities. The
responsibilities are described on the College website:
- Licensing properly qualified medical practitioners;
- Developing and ensuring the standards of practice in all
fields of medicine;
- Investigating and disciplining of all doctors whose standards
of medical care, ethical or professional conduct are questioned.
VI.4.2.c Since the assertion of "an obligation to serve and protect
the public interest" applies to every government or state institution, and
the College fulfils that obligation by properly discharging its statutory
responsibilities, the reference to this principle either serves no purpose,
or has been included to provide rhetorical pretext for the coercive elements found in the policy.
VI.4.2.d In any case, the public interest is neither
served nor protected by the unjustified suppression of freedom of conscience
and religion.
VI.4.3 "The Canadian medical profession as a whole has an obligation to ensure that
people have access to the provision of legally
permissible and publicly-funded
health services."
VI.4.3.a Even if undisputed, it does not follow from
this principle that every physician is obliged to provide or facilitate access to
every legal, publicly-funded health service.
VI.4.4 "Physicians have an obligation not to interfere with or obstruct a patient's
right to access legally permissible and
publicly-funded health services."
VI.4.4.a Granted that physicians must not interfere
with or obstruct a patient's access to legally permissible services, it does
not follow that a physician is always legally or ethically obliged to facilitate
access.
VI.4.4.b Moreover, the unwillingness of a physician to provide a
service or facilitate
access to it does not constitute obstruction or interference.
Obstruction or interference both require some positive act. This point
was made recently in the submission of the Justice Centre for Constitutional
Freedoms to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario:
To obstruct or hinder a person connotes an active
intention.If a physician
explains to a patient that the physician has a moral, ethical, or religious
objection to a treatment or procedure, that physician is not "impeding" that
patient's access to such medical services.
Neither are those physicians who proactively take steps to notify potential
patients that they do not provide certain controversial services.
There is no active intention to obstruct or hinder the patient from
receiving such care, just an explanation that the physician cannot
participate in providing it.
As an analogous example, if a customer were to go to a
butcher to buy some pork chops and discover that the butcher is a devout
Muslim or Jew who refuses to sell pork, and even refuses to direct customers
to other butchers offering pork, that butcher is not "impeding" the
potential customer's access to pork.
Rather, the butcher is merely refusing to participate or facilitate
the potential customer’s purchase of pork.8
VI.4.5 "Physicians have an obligation not to
abandon their patients."
VI.4.5.a Writing in the New England Journal of
Medicine, two euthanasia advocates characterized refusal of physicians
to provide euthanasia as patient abandonment, a violation of medical ethics.9
VI.4.5.b Testifying during the trial in Carter v.
Canada as an expert witness in favour of
legalization of physician assisted suicide,
Professor Margaret Battin also linked refusal to provide such service as
patient abandonment.10 Professor Jocelyn
Downie of Dalhousie University helped the lawyers who called Professor
Battin to testify prepare their expert witnesses for the trial.11
VI.4.5.c Professor Downie was one of the ghost writers of Conscientious Refusal.
She and fellow ghost writer
Jaquelyn Shaw claim that a physician
who "terminates a relationship without referral in a conscientious conflict"
may be guilty of "patient abandonment."12
VI.4.5.d However, many will dispute the claim that a
physician who refuses to kill a patient in the circumstances contemplated by
the Supreme Court of Canada is guilty of "patient abandonment." A patient who
asks a physician for assisted suicide or euthanasia is not abandoned because
the physician offers effective remedial treatments or palliative care
instead of a lethal injection.
VI.4.5.e Similarly, a physician does not abandon a
patient because he offers treatment or care that the patient does not want.
A pregnant woman who comes to a physician seeking an abortion is not abandoned
because the physician declines to provide an abortion and offers obstetrical
care. A patient who asks a physician for birth control is not abandoned
because the physician offers assistance with Natural Family Planning rather than
a prescription for birth control.
VI.4.5.f To characterize such situations as examples of
"patient abandonment" reflects wordsmithing that deforms accepted principles in
order to use them for a purpose for which they were never intended: to convince
physicians that they have an ethical and legal obligation to kill patients or
find someone who will, to justify the coercion of those who resist, and to
provide an
excuse to suppress freedom of conscience and religion in the medical profession.
VI.4.5.g Moving from ethics to law, in 2004, two
Canadian academics, Professors Rebecca Cook and Bernard Dickens, claimed
that failing to refer for abortion constitutes "negligence close to
abandonment." However, their claim was unsupported by their own legal
references (Appendix "G").
VI.4.6 ". . . legally permissible and
publicly-funded . . ."
VI.4.6.a Neither individual physicians nor the medical
profession as a whole have an obligation to ensure
that people have access to illegal health services. Any
actual obligation can refer only to legal services.
VI.4.6.b Many kinds of elective surgery are not
publicly funded. Diabetic supplies like insulin needles or pumps may
not be publicly funded or may be publicly funded only after payment of an
annual deductible. The fact that a health service is or is not
"publicly-funded" has nothing to do with whether or not individual
physicians or the medical profession as a whole have an obligation to ensure
that people have access to it.
VI.4.6.c Physicians may not interfere with or obstruct a
patient's right to access legally permissible services
whether or not they are health services and whether or not
they are publicly funded.
VI.4.6.d "Public funding" provides a benefit for a
patient, but it confers no privileged status on a procedure, nor does
"public funding" establish definitively that a procedure is morally or
ethically acceptable, any more than "public funding" can establish that a
war is justified.
VI.4.6.e The descriptors "legally permissible" and
"publicly-funded" serve no purpose in this document apart from providing a
rhetorical pretext for the coercive elements found in the policy.
VI.4.7 ". . . health services. . . health . . .
well-being. . ."
VI.4.7.a Following the legalization of abortion it
quickly became obvious that the meaning of "health" was so elastic as to be
meaningless for policy purposes unless more specifically defined; "well-being" is
more elastic still.
VI.4.7.b In his submission to the Supreme Court of
Canada in Carter v. Canada, counsel for the Canadian Medical
Association explained that the concept of "the best interests of the
patient" can be taken to mean that physicians should sometimes help patients
commit suicide or kill them, on the one hand, or, on the other, that they
should never do so. He told the Court that the medical profession is
divided between two positions, "each defensible on the basis of established
medical ethical considerations and compassion for the patient."13
VI.4.7.c The problem described by the CMA's lawyer
arises because the question of whether or not a service is a
health service or a procedure is a medical procedure is
determined by an underlying philosophy. Only to the extent that the
philosophy is actually shared can there be agreement on that point. It
is not determined by the legality of the service or the procedure, nor is it
determined by whether or not the service is publicly-funded.
VI.4.7.d For example, the
fact that the Supreme Court of Canada has decided that physicians should be
allowed to kill patients under certain circumstances does not oblige all
physicians to accept the view that killing patients is a "health service" or
"medical procedure," any more than they are obliged to accept the legal
fiction that an infant is not a human person until it has completely
proceeded, alive, from the body of its mother. It is precisely for
this reason that counsel for the CMA told the Court that "the law should
offer protection to those physicians who choose to participate in physician
assisted death if it is legalized, and those who do not."14
Summary
VI.4.8 Consistent with the ultimate origin of the
policy with the Conscience Research Group, the principles set out and
terminology used in Conscientious Refusal are apparently intended
to convince physicians that they have an ethical and legal obligation to do
what they believe to be wrong, to justify the coercion of those who resist,
and to provide an excuse to suppress freedom of conscience and religion in
the medical profession.
VI.4.9 However, the principles cannot be applied for
this purpose unless they are tendentiously interpreted in accordance with
the views of the Conscience Research Group and alternative philosophical or
ethical viewpoints are ignored or disallowed.
VI.4.10 Neither Mr. Salte nor the committee has
demonstrated that alternative philosophical or ethical viewpoints should be
ignored or disallowed.
VI.4.11 At this point one returns again to the words of Madame Justice Bertha Wilson in R v. Morgentaler.
In a free and democratic society, "the state will respect choices made by
individuals and, to the greatest extent possible, will avoid subordinating
these choices to any one conception of the good life," and that the state
should not endorse and enforce "one conscientiously-held view at the expense
of another."(VII.12)
VI.4.12 Conclusion:
Conscientious Refusal is not justified by the principles
included in the policy because there is no necessary connection between
the principles and a policy requiring physicians to do what they believe
to be wrong. Different philosophical or ethical approaches can be
applied to qualify or interpret the principles, leading to the opposite
conclusion.
VI.5 Is the policy a compromise?
VI.5.1 Interviewed after the draft policy was made
public, Mr. Salte offered a further justification for Conscientious
Refusal:
So there is a broad range of beliefs out there,
there's a broad range of perspectives out there, and what the draft policy
talks about is, in fact, a compromise between the extreme position, which
would be that physicians are compelled to provide this service, on the one
side, and the other extreme position which is physicians can simply refuse
to discuss with their patients what is going to become a legal procedure.
(Appendix "C", CV.4)
VI.5.2 This is a false characterization of the opposite
poles of the issue. Against the position that physicians are obliged to do
something they believe to be wrong is the opposite position that they are
not obliged to do so. Merely talking about killing the patient is a
different matter.
VI.5.3 However, for present purposes, consider the
claim that forcing an objecting physician to help to arrange the killing of
a patient by someone else is a compromise between two polar opposites: on
the one hand, that physicians are morally obliged to kill patients in the
circumstances defined by the Supreme Court, or, on the other, that
physicians are not morally obliged to kill patients in those circumstances.
VI.5.4 To claim that killing patients in accordance
with the Supreme Court ruling involves no moral judgement is absurd.
Clearly, the (unspoken) premise is that killing patients in those
circumstances is morally acceptable. If it is morally acceptable to kill
them, then it must be morally acceptable to assist with the killing - by
finding someone else to do it, for example. This is precisely the reasoning
used by the trial court judge in Carter. Beginning with the premise
that suicide can be morally acceptable, she agreed that it follows that
assisting with suicide can be morally acceptable.15
VI.5.5 However, objecting physicians typically reject
the premise that killing patients is morally acceptable even in the
circumstances defined by the Supreme Court. They insist, to the contrary,
that it is morally unacceptable. And, from the premise that it is morally
unacceptable, it follows that it must be morally unacceptable to assist with
it or arrange for it. This is entirely consistent with the reasoning of the
trial judge in Carter and with widespread understanding of morally
significant participation.
VI.5.6 To insist, despite this, that objecting
physicians are obliged to help to arrange the killing of a patient according
to the Carter protocol is not neutral with respect to the morality of
killing. On the contrary: the unspoken premise that lies behind such a
demand is that killing patients according to the Carter protocol is morally
acceptable and that anyone who refuses to accept that premise is mistaken.
To take the next step - to order an objecting physician to help to arrange a
killing - is not a compromise between two opposite moral views about killing
patients. It is a demand to conform to the opposite moral view.
VI.5.7 While the explanation offered here uses the
examples of physician assisted suicide and euthanasia, it applies equally to
other morally contested procedures, and it applies equally to disputes about
the content of professional obligations.
VI.5.8 To describe this demand for submission as a
"compromise" is, as Professor Jay Budziszewski says, "bad faith
authoritarianism . . . a dishonest way of advancing a moral view by
pretending to have no moral view."16
VI.5.9
Conclusion: Conscientious Refusal is not
a compromise between opposite views about morally contested procedures
or professional responsibilities. It is an assertion of a preference for
one of the opposing views and an authoritarian attempt to compel others
to conform to that preference, masked by the pretence of neutrality.
VII. Discussion
VII.1 One of the disturbing aspects of the story of
the origin and development of Conscientious Refusal is what appears to be a
pattern of concealment, selective disclosure, and false or misleading
statements that all serve the purpose of supporting the policy.
VII.2 Further, one also finds explicit statements that
the subject is controversial, which obviously imply the existence of
contrary opinions. However, at no point does one find even a half-hearted
effort to consider those opinions. For the purposes of policy development
by College officials, contrary views either do not exist or are not worth
examining.
VII.3 Finally, the documents considered in this
submission disclosed that, since some time in 2013, officials of Colleges of
Physicians in a number of provinces have been making plans behind closed
doors to suppress freedom of conscience in the medical profession by
enacting guidelines to force physicians to do what they believe to be wrong
- even if that means participating in homicide or suicide. Saskatchewan
physicians became aware of this only after the College Council had
approved Conscientious Refusal in principle.
VII.4 It is thus appropriate to offer here a number of
principles that have been ignored by those who urged College Council to
approve Conscientious Refusal, and by the ghost writers in the
Conscience Research Group who provided the original text for the policy.
VII.5 Medicine is a moral enterprise.
VII.5.1 The practice of medicine is an inescapably moral enterprise
precisely because physicians are always seeking to do some kind of good and
avoid some kind of evil for their patients.17 However, the moral aspect of
practice as it relates to the conduct and moral responsibility of a
physician is usually implicit, not explicit. It is normally eclipsed by the
needs of the patient and exigencies of practice. But it is never absent;
every decision concerning treatment is a moral decision, whether or not the
physician specifically adverts to that fact.
VII.5.2 This point is frequently overlooked when a physician, for reasons
of conscience, declines to participate in or provide a service or procedure
that is routinely provided by his colleagues. They may be disturbed because
they assume that, in making a moral decision about treatment, he has done
something unusual, even improper. Seeing nothing wrong with the procedure,
they see no moral judgement involved in providing it. In their view, the
objector has brought morality into a situation where it doesn't belong, and,
worse, it is his morality.
VII.5.3 In point of fact, the moral issue was there all along, but they
didn't notice it because they have been unreflectively doing what they were
taught to do in medical school and residency, and what society expects them
to do. Nonetheless, in deciding to provide the procedure they also
implicitly concede its goodness; they would not provide it if they did not
think it was a good thing to do. What unsettles them is really not that the
objector has taken a moral position on the issue, but that he has made an
explicit moral judgement that differs from their implicit one.
VII.5.4 Hence, the demand that physicians must not be allowed to act upon
beliefs is unacceptable because it is impossible; one cannot act morally
without reference to beliefs, and cannot practise medicine without reference
to beliefs. Relevant here is a comment by Professor Margaret Somerville. "In
ethics," she writes,"impossible goals are not neutral; they cause harm."18
VII.5.5 Once medicine is understood to be a moral
enterprise, it becomes easier to understand why it is a mistake to think
that moral or ethical views are unwelcome intruders upon the
physician-patient relationship. Morality and ethics are actually intrinsic
to it. Of course, some moral or ethical views may be erroneous, but that is
a different matter that must be addressed by explaining why they are
erroneous. It will not do to pretend, for example, that the claim that best
medical practice in some circumstances means killing a patient does not
involve at least implicit moral or ethical judgements.
VII.5.6 It is not possible here to adequately address
the issues raised by Conscientious Refusal in relation to the practice of
medicine, particularly since the policy is fixated on the provision of
"legally permissible publicly-funded services" to the complete exclusion of
any reference to the philosophy of medicine or ethical medical practice. It
does not seem to recognize that providing palliative care is not
functionally or morally equivalent to providing automotive repairs covered
by Saskatchewan Government Insurance.
VII.6 Consider
first the well being of the patient.
VII.6.1 Consistent with the practice of medicine understood as a
moral enterprise, a physician first considers the well-being of the patient.19 What
constitutes or contributes to the "well-being" of a patient is largely
determined by a competent patient, not by a physician, though a physician
may well contribute to the patient's decision. However, it does not follow
that a physician is always obliged to agree with the patient's decision or
to give effect to it. What happens in the case of such disagreements is
largely dependent upon patient and physician concerned and their respective
evaluations of what is at stake. More relevant here is the obligation of the
physician to offer the patient his best medical judgement about a
recommended course of treatment or action, and, in so doing, select
treatments that avoid or minimize health risks or adverse side effects.
VII.6.2 Sound medical judgement begins with and remains focussed on the
patient and is exercised respectfully. It must be informed by correct
science, avoiding or minimizing foreseeable risks or harm. It must seek a
reasonably effective response to the needs of the patient, the anticipated
benefits of which outweigh potential risks or harms. Medical judgement
requires the reasonable exercise of discretion, which is shaped and refined
by clinical wisdom born of experience. More could be added, but these
elements are essential.
VII.6.3 Physicians are expected to provide patients with accurate
information about all legal options available to them, the effectiveness of
the methods, adverse effects or risks associated with each, benefits
associated with each, and other information that someone in the position of
a patient would reasonably want to know. In some cases the physician might
have to provide a great deal of information; in others, it may simply be a
matter of filling in some gaps in what the patient knows.20 In all cases, the
physician must take care to present the information in a form comprehensible
to the patient.21
VII.6.4 The physician must disclose whether or not he has religious,
ethical or other conscientious convictions that generally preclude him from
providing some services or treatments, even if medical judgement is central
to his practice.22 The reason for this is that the patient is entitled to be
apprised of non-medical factors that may influence a physician's medical
judgement and recommendations. The patient is also entitled to know whether
or not the physician's medical evaluation of the treatment in question is
consistent with the general view of the medical profession.23
VII.6.5 The physician should invite questions from the patient at
different stages in the consultation to ensure that he has been correctly
understood.24 The goal is to ensure that the patient has sufficient
information and understanding to make an informed decision about what kind
of treatment she will accept. With respect to any reference to his
conscientious convictions, unless the patient questions him, asks for
further explanation, or otherwise indicates that she does not understand his
position, the physician need not and probably should not expand upon the
basis for his own position. To do so would likely invite the accusation that
he is "preaching."
VII.6.6 Patient-centred medical practice is directed to ensuring good
medical care, but good medical care is not provided by automatons. Medical
schools do not manufacture made-to-order products that perform according to
factory default settings, or finely machined cogs that keep health care
delivery apparatus running smoothly. Medicine is a moral enterprise,
morality is a human enterprise, and physicians, no less than patients, are
moral agents. Conscientious Refusal was written from a very
different perspective, and it has not been shown to be a morally or
ethically superior perspective.
VII.7 Morality is a human
enterprise.
VII.7.1 All public behaviour - how one treats other people, how one treats
animals, how one treats the environment - is determined by what one
believes. All beliefs influence public behaviour. Some of these beliefs are
religious, some not, but all are beliefs. This applies no less to "secular"
ethics than to religious ethics. A secular ethic may be independent of
religion,25 but it is not faith-free, nor is it beyond the influence of faith.
On the contrary: a secular ethic, like any ethic, is faith-based. That human
dignity exists - or that it does not - or that human life is worthy of
unconditional reverence - or merely conditional respect - and notions of
beneficence, justice and equality are not the product of scientific enquiry,
but rest upon faith: upon beliefs about human nature, the meaning and
purpose of life, the existence of good and evil.
VII.7.2 That everyone is a believer reflects the fact that the practice of
morality is a human enterprise,26 but it is not a scientific enterprise. The
classic ethical question, "How ought I to live?" is not a scientific
question and cannot be answered by any of the disciplines of natural
science, though natural science can provide raw material needed for adequate
answers.
VII.7.3 Answers to the question, "How ought I to live?" reflect two
fundamental moral norms; do good, avoid evil. These basics have
traditionally been undisputed; the disputes begin with identifying or
defining good and evil and what constitutes "doing" and "avoiding." Such
explorations are the province of philosophy, ethics, theology and religion.
Internationally, religion continues to be the principal means by which
concepts of good and evil and right and wrong conduct are sustained and
transmitted.
VII.7.4 Nonetheless, since the practice of morality is a human enterprise,
reflections about morality and the development and transmission of ideas
about right and wrong also occurs within culture and society outside the
framework of identifiable academic disciplines and religions. In
consequence, the secular public square is populated by people with any
number of moral viewpoints, some religious, some not: some tied to
particular philosophical or ethical systems, some not: but all of them
believers. There is no reason to deny the freedom to act upon religious
belief because it is religious: no reason, that is, apart from
anti-religious bigotry.
VII.7.5 Further, since morality is a human enterprise,
moral judgement is an essential activity of every human person, moral
judgement necessarily involves some kind of individual or personal
conviction, and maintaining one's personal moral integrity is the aspiration
of anyone who wishes to live rightly. Thus, beliefs are "personal," in
the sense that one personally accepts them and is committed to them.
VII.7.6 However, this does not mean that they are
parochial, insignificant or erroneous. Christian, Jewish and Muslim beliefs,
for example, are shared by hundreds of millions of people. They "personally"
adhere to their beliefs, just as non-religious believers "personally" adhere
to their non-religious beliefs. In neither case does the fact of this
"personal" commitment provide grounds to set beliefs aside. Thus, it is
important to recognize that pejorative or suspicious references to
"personal" beliefs or "personal" values frequently reflect underlying and
perhaps unexamined prejudice against them.
VII.7.7 Conscientious Refusal was written by
believers: by people who believe that whatever is "legally permissible and
publicly-funded" is morally acceptable, who believe that those who think
differently are mistaken, and who believe that others should be compelled to
conform to their faith in the moral infallibility of the law and ministers
of finance. The policy is profoundly disrespectful of the moral agency of
physicians.
VII.8 A
secular public square includes religious belief.
VII.8.1 It is for this reason that the Supreme Court of Canada has
recognized that, in Canadian law, "secular" must be understood to include
religious belief. In his paper, Seeing Through the Secular Illusion,27 Dr.
Iain Benson emphasizes this by referring to an explanation supported by the
full bench of the Court:
In my view, Saunders J. below erred in her assumption
that 'secular' effectively meant 'non-religious'. This is incorrect since
nothing in the Charter, political or democratic theory, or a proper
understanding of pluralism demands that atheistically based moral positions
trump religiously based moral positions on matters of public policy. I note
that the preamble to the Charter itself establishes that '... Canada is
founded upon principles that recognize the supremacy of God and the rule of
law'. According to the reasoning espoused by Saunders J., if one's moral
view manifests from a religiously grounded faith, it is not to be heard in
the public square, but if it does not, then it is publicly acceptable. The
problem with this approach is that everyone has 'belief' or 'faith' in
something, be it atheistic, agnostic or religious. To construe the 'secular'
as the realm of the 'unbelief' is therefore erroneous. Given this, why,
then, should the religiously informed conscience be placed at a public
disadvantage or disqualification? To do so would be to distort liberal
principles in an illiberal fashion and would provide only a feeble notion of
pluralism. The key is that people will disagree about important issues, and
such disagreement, where it does not imperil community living, must be
capable of being accommodated at the core of a modern pluralism.28
VII.8.2 Thus, the Supreme Court of Canada has acknowledged that
secularists, atheists and agnostics are believers, no less than Christians,
Muslims, Jews and persons of other faiths. Neither a secular state nor a
secular health care system (tax-paid or not) must be purged of the
expression of religious belief. Whether or not they are state employees in
law or as a matter of public policy, physicians may act upon religious
beliefs when practising medicine. The Court has
insisted that rational democratic pluralism must make room for all of
them.
VII.8.3 This undercuts the reasoning sometimes offered by those who
would suppress freedom of conscience and religion in the medical
profession. Identifying physicians as "providers of secular public services"(emphasis added),29
they erroneously presume that what is
"secular" excludes religious belief. The public perpetuation of this
error contributes significantly to anti-religious sentiments
and a climate of religious intolerance.
VII.8.4 Further, the approach taken by the Supreme Court of Canada on
this issue contradicts the position taken by those who argue that "moral
beliefs" are not protected: that only specifically religious beliefs and
practices are protected by law.30 This reasoning would place atheists and agnostics "at a public
disadvantage or disqualification" vis-à-vis religious believers, surely not
an outcome consistent with the thinking of the Supreme Court.
VII.8.5 While the Supreme Court of Canada has
recognized that religious believers and religious communities are part of
the warp and woof of the Canadian social fabric, Conscientious Refusal
is written as if this is inconsequential, inasmuch as it demands that
physicians must participate in morally significant ways in procedures known
to be contrary to the teaching of major religious groups. Thus, the policy
is inimical to the presence of members of those groups in medical practice.
VII.9 Avoid authoritarian
solutions.
VII.9.1 Making room in the public square for people motivated by different
and sometimes opposing beliefs can lead to conflict, as the present
consultation demonstrates. The Supreme Court of Canada has warned that to
single out and exclude religious belief in order to prevent or minimize such
conflict would "distort liberal principles in an illiberal fashion."31
VII.9.2 It is also dangerous. It overlooks the possibility that some
secularists - like some religious believers - can be uncritical and narrowly
dogmatic in the development of their ethical thinking, and intolerant of
anyone who disagrees with them. They might see them as heretics who must be
driven from the professions, from the public square, perhaps from the
country: sent to live across the sea with their "own kind." University
of Victoria law professor Mary Anne Waldron provides a reminder and a
warning:
Conflict in belief is an endemic part of human society
and likely always will be. What has changed, I think, is the resurrection of
the idea that we can and should compel belief through legal and
administrative processes, or, if not compel the belief itself, at least
force conformity. Unfortunately, that begins the cycle of repression that,
if we are to maintain a democracy, we must break.32
VII.9.3 On this point, it is essential to note that a secular ethic is
not morally neutral.33 The claim that a secular ethic is morally neutral - or
that one can practise medicine in a morally "neutral" fashion- is not merely
fiction. It is another example of "bad faith authoritarianism” identified by
Professor J. Budziszewski.16
VII.9.4 Conscientious Refusal illustrates
another of the most common examples of "bad faith authoritarianism": the
pretence that referral is an acceptable compromise that balances the
respective "interests" of physicians and patients. While that may be the
case for many physicians in many situations, it clearly is not the case when
it is understood that referral or other forms of facilitation make a
physician complicit in wrongdoing.34
VII.10 There is no duty to do what is believed to be wrong.
VII.10.1 If it is legitimate to compel religious believers to do what they
believe to be wrong, then it is equally legitimate to compel non-religious
believers to do what they think is wrong. It would, in principle, establish
a duty to do what is believed to be wrong for everyone.
VII.10.2 For Andrei Marmor, "a duty to do what is wrong is surely an
oxymoron,"35 and most people would agree, as did Dr. John Williams, then
Director of Ethics for the Canadian Medical Association. Speaking in 2002 of
physicians who decline to provide or refer for contraceptives for religious
reasons, he said, "[They're] under no obligation to do something that they
feel is wrong."36
VII.10.3 When discussion about difficulties associated with the exercise of
freedom of conscience in health care is repeatedly characterized as "the
problem of conscientious objection,"37 it becomes clear that the underlying
premise is that people and institutions ought to do what they believe to be
wrong, and that refusal to do what one believes to be wrong requires special
justification. This is exactly the opposite of what one would expect. Most
people believe that we should not do what we believe to be wrong, and that
refusing to do what we believe to be wrong is the norm. It is wrongdoing
that needs special justification or excuse, not refusing to do wrong.
VII.10.4 The inversion is troubling, since "a duty to do what is wrong" is
being advanced by those who support the "war on terror." They argue that
there is, indeed, a duty to do what is wrong, and that this includes a duty
to kill non-combatants and to torture terrorist suspects.38 The claim is
sharply contested,39 but it does indicate how far a duty to do what is wrong
might be pushed. In Quebec, it is now being pushed as far as requiring
physicians to participate in killing patients, even if they believe it is
wrong: even if they believe that it is first degree murder.40
VII.10.5 This, perhaps, was what was troubling a member of the Council of
the College of Physicians of Ontario when, in September, 2008, the Council
was considering the final draft of Physicians and the Human Rights Code. He
drew his colleagues' attention to a chilling New England Journal of Medicine
article by Holocaust survivor, Elie Wiesel: "Without conscience."41 It
was about the crucial role played by German physicians in supporting Nazi
horrors. "How can we explain their betrayal?" Wiesel asked. "What gagged
their conscience? What happened to their humanity?"42
VII.10. 6 This reminder is a warning that the community
must be protected against the temptation to give credence to the dangerous
idea that is advanced by Conscientious Refusal: that a learned or
privileged class, a profession or state institutions can legitimately compel
people to do what they believe to be wrong - even gravely wrong - and punish
them if they refuse.
VII.10. 7 Finally, Conscientious Refusal is
incoherent because it purports to include a duty to do what one believes to
be wrong in a code of ethics or ethical guidelines, the very purpose of
which is to encourage physicians to act ethically and avoid wrongdoing.
VII.11 Forcing someone to do wrong is violation, not limitation.
VII.11.1 Attempts to suppress freedom of conscience
and religion in the medical profession are often defended using a statement of the Supreme
Court of Canada: "the freedom to hold beliefs is broader than the freedom to
act on them."43
VII.11.2 The statement is certainly correct, and precedents can be
cited for applying it. Oliver Cromwell applied the distinction to
justify his suppression of the practice of Catholicism in Ireland.44 However,
it is doubtful that the Supreme Court of Canada intended its comment to be
put to such use in a liberal democracy.
VII.11.3 The mantra, "the freedom to hold beliefs is broader than the
freedom to act on them" is not wrong, but it is inadequate. It is simply not
responsive to many of the questions about the exercise of freedom of
conscience that arise in a society characterized by a plurality of moral and
political viewpoints and conflicting demands. More refined distinctions are
required. One of them is the distinction between perfective and preservative
freedom of conscience, which reflects the two ways in which freedom of
conscience is exercised: by pursuing apparent goods and avoiding apparent
evils.45
VII.11.4 It is generally agreed that the state may limit the exercise of
perfective freedom of conscience if it is objectively harmful, or if the
limitation serves the common good. Although there may be disagreement about
how to apply these principles, and restrictions may go too far, no polity
could long exist without restrictions of some sort on human acts, so some
limitation of perfective freedom of conscience is not unexpected.
VII.11.5 If the state can legitimately limit perfective freedom of
conscience by preventing
people from doing what they believe to be good, it
does not follow that it is equally free to suppress preservative freedom of
conscience by forcing them to do what they believe to be wrong. There is a
significant difference between preventing someone from doing the good that
he wishes to do and forcing him to do the evil that he abhors.
VII.11.6 We have noted the danger inherent in the notion of a "duty to do
what is wrong." Here we add that, as a general rule, it is fundamentally
unjust and offensive to suppress preservative freedom of conscience by
forcing people to support, facilitate or participate in what they perceive
to be wrongful acts; the more serious the wrongdoing, the graver the
injustice and offence. It is a policy fundamentally opposed to civic
friendship, which grounds and sustains political community and provides the
strongest motive for justice. It is inconsistent with the best traditions
and aspirations of liberal democracy, since it instills attitudes more
suited to totalitarian regimes than to the demands of responsible freedom.
VII.11.7 This does not mean that no limit can ever be placed on
preservative freedom of conscience. It does mean, however, that even the
strict approach taken to limiting other fundamental rights and freedoms is
not sufficiently refined to be safely applied to limit freedom of conscience
in its preservative form. Like the use of potentially deadly force, if the
restriction of preservative freedom of conscience can be justified at all,
it will only be as a last resort and only in the most exceptional
circumstances.
VII.11.8 What is proposed by Conscientious Refusal
is not a justified limitation of fundamental freedoms, but a serious
violation of human dignity that remains unjustified by any evidence or
argument advanced to support it.
VII.12 Accommodate different conceptions of
"the good life."
VII.12.1 Madame
Justice Bertha Wilson of the Supreme Court of Canada addressed the issue of
freedom of conscience in the landmark 1988 case R v. Morgentaler. Madame
Justice Wilson argued that "an emphasis on individual conscience and individual
judgment . . . lies at the heart of our democratic political tradition."46
Wilson held that it was indisputable that the decision to have an abortion "is
essentially a moral decision, a matter of conscience."
The question is: whose conscience? Is the conscience of the woman to be
paramount or the conscience of the state? I believe. . . that in a free and
democratic society it must be the conscience of the individual. Indeed, s.
2(a) makes it clear that this freedom belongs to "everyone", i.e., to each
of us individually.47
VII.12.2 "Everyone" includes every physician. But, at this point
in the judgement, Wilson was not discussing whether or not the conscience of a
woman should prevail over that of an objecting physician, but how the
conscientious judgement of an individual should stand against that of the state.
Her answer was that, in a free and democratic society, "the state will respect
choices made by individuals and, to the greatest extent possible, will avoid
subordinating these choices to any one conception of the good life."48
This statement was affirmed unanimously in 1991 by a panel of five judges,
and by the full bench of the Court in1996.49
VII.12.3 Wilson approved the principle that a human person must never be treated as a
means to an end - especially an end chosen by someone else, or by the state.
Wilson rejected the idea that, in questions of morality, the state should
endorse and enforce "one conscientiously-held view at the expense of another,"
for that is "to deny freedom of conscience to some, to treat them as means to an
end, to deprive them . . .of their 'essential humanity'."50
VII.12.4 Freedom of conscience was also mentioned by
Justices Beetz and Estey in Morgentaler when considering the
appointment of therapeutic abortion committees.
Given that therapeutic abortions can only be performed
in eligible hospitals and that the committee certifying the abortion must
come from that hospital, this effectively contributes to the inaccessibility
of the treatment. Nothing in the Criminal Code
obliges the board of an eligible hospital to appoint therapeutic abortion
committees. Indeed, a board is entitled to refuse to appoint a therapeutic
abortion committee in a hospital that would otherwise qualify to perform
abortions and boards often do so in Canada.
Given that the decision to appoint a committee is, in part, one of conscience and, in some cases, one which affects religious beliefs, a law cannot force a board to
appoint a committee any more than it could force a physician to perform an
abortion. The defect in the law is not that it does not
force boards to appoint committees, but that it grants exclusive authority
to those boards to make such appointments. (Emphasis added)51
VII.12.5 Most recently, in Carter v. Canada,
the full bench of the Court, affirming the words of Mr. Justice Beetz,
stated, "a physician’s decision to participate in assisted dying is a matter
of conscience and, in some cases, of religious belief."
52
VII.12.6 The plan to suppress freedom of conscience and
drive dissenting physicians from the medical profession demonstrates that
Conscientious Refusal clashes seriously with the approach taken in
Morgentaler and affirmed in Carter. Public policy must make room for both
hospitals and physicians whose "a concept of the good life" precludes their
participation in abortion, euthanasia, assisted suicide or other morally
contested procedures for reasons of conscience or religion.
VIII. Conclusions
VIII.1 Conscientious Refusal requires all
physicians who object to a procedure for reasons of conscience to facilitate
the procedure by referring patients to a colleague who will provide it, even
if it is homicide or suicide. This is widely recognized as a form of
morally significant participation. Moreover, since this is known to be
contrary to the teaching of major religious groups, the policy is inimical
to the presence of members of those groups in medical practice. Thus, the
policy adversely affects freedom of conscience and religion.
VIII.2 No evidence was provided to justify the policy.
No argument was offered to demonstrate that Conscientious Refusal is
necessary to ensure that medical practice in the province is safe,
competent, ethical, or to safeguard the health of patients. None of the
arguments provided to Council justify the policy, nor do the principles
included in the text.
VIII.3 Conscientious Refusal fails to
recognize that the practice of medicine is a moral enterprise, morality is a
human enterprise, and physicians, no less than patients, are moral agents.
VIII.4 The original text virtually copied by Conscientious Refusal
was written by believers: by people who believe that whatever is
"legally permissible and publicly-funded" is morally acceptable- including
euthanasia, assisted suicide and abortion. It is an assertion of those
beliefs and an authoritarian attempt to compel others to conform to them. It
is a partisan document that is profoundly disrespectful of the moral agency
of physicians, not a compromise.
VIII.5 Conscientious Refusal advances the dangerous idea that a
learned or privileged class or profession or state institutions can
legitimately compel people to do what they believe to be wrong - even
gravely wrong - and punish them if they refuse. This is not a limitation of
fundamental freedoms, but a serious violation of human dignity that remains
unjustified by any evidence or argument advanced to support it. It is also
incoherent, because it purports to include a duty to do what one believes to
be wrong in a code of ethics or ethical guidelines, the very purpose of
which is to encourage physicians to act ethically and avoid wrongdoing.
VIII.6 The Associate Registrar has made it clear that those who refuse to do
what the policy demands will be disciplined by the College or forced out of
the medical profession. This clashes seriously with the approach taken by
the Supreme Court of Canada, which has affirmed that public policy must make
room for physicians whose "concept of the good life" precludes their
participation in abortion, euthanasia, assisted suicide or other morally
contested procedures.
VIII.7 The burden of proof was on the Associate
Registrar and the
appointed committee to prove beyond doubt that Conscientious Refusal is
justified and that no less authoritarian alternatives are available. They
failed to discharge that burden; neither has College Council discharged it.
The policy should be withdrawn.
Notes
1. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and
Surgeons of Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 3.
2. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and
Surgeons of Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 4.
3. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 10-13. (Physicians
and the Ontario Human Rights Code)
4. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 14. (Moral
or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care)
5. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 15.(Members
Moral or Religious Beliefs Not to Affect Medical Care)
6. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 16-18. (Guideline:
Unplanned Pregnancy)
7. Document 200/14, College of Physicians and
Surgeons of Saskatchewan,
Memo from Bryan
Salte to Council dated 31 July, 2014 Re: Possible Policy or Guideline -
Physicians who have an ethical objection to provide certain forms of medical
services, p. 2.
8.
In Defence of Charter Freedoms: A legal analysis of the constitutionality of
the draft policy "Professional Obligations and Human Rights." & Justice
Centre for Constitutional Freedoms, February, 2015, p. 6 (Accessed
2015-03-02)
9. Angell M., Lowenstein E.
Letter re: Redefining Physicians' Role in Assisted Dying.
N Engl J Med 2013; 368:485-486 January 31, 2013 DOI: 10.1056/NEJMc1209798
(Accessed 2015-03-03)
10.
Carter v. Canada (Attorney General) 2012 BCSC 886, para. 239
(Accessed 2015-02-28)
11.
Carter v. Canada (Attorney General) 2012 BCSC 886, para. 124
(Accessed 2015-02-28)
12. Shaw, J. and Downie, J. "Welcome to the
Wild, Wild North: Conscientious Objection Policies Governing Canada's
Medical, Nursing, Pharmacy, and Dental Professions." Bioethics.
doi: 10.1111/bioe.12057
13. Re: Joint intervention in Carter v.
Canada: Selections from oral submissions. Supreme Court
of Canada, 15 October, 2014.
Harry Underwood (Counsel for the Canadian Medical
Association)[227:29/491:20] to [229:29/491:20]
14. Re: Joint intervention in Carter v.
Canada: Selections from oral submissions. Supreme Court
of Canada, 15 October, 2014.
Harry Underwood (Counsel for the Canadian Medical
Association)[229:29/491:20]
15.
Carter v. Canada (Attorney General)
2012 BCSC 886. Supreme Court of British Columbia, 15 June, 2012. Vancouver,
British Columbia. (Hereinafter "Carter v. Canada") para. 339
(Accessed 2014-11-24) The judge uses the term "ethical," not "moral," and
more frequently employs the former, but she treats them as synonyms when
addressing the question, "Does the law attempt to uphold a conception of
morality inconsistent with the consensus in Canadian society?" (para.
340-358) Moreover, witnesses on both sides do not typically distinguish
between ethical and moral issues. See, for example, Dr. Shoichet
(plaintiffs) at para. 75, Prof. Sumner (plaintiffs) at para. 237, Dr. Bereza
(defendants) at para. 248, Dr. Preston (plaintiffs) at para. 262. The judge
defines ethics as "a discipline consisting of rational inquiry into
questions of right and wrong" and frames the question accordingly: " whether
it is right, or wrong, to assist persons who request assistance in ending
their lives and, if it is right to do so, in what circumstances." Carter
v. Canada, para. 164. Most would see in this passage no way to
distinguish between ethics and moral philosophy.
16. "The question of neutrality has been profoundly
obscured by the mistake of confusing neutrality with objectivity...
neutrality and objectivity are not the same... objectivity is possible but
neutrality is not. To be neutral, if that were possible, would be to have no
presuppositions whatsoever. To be objective is to have certain
presuppositions, along with the manners that allow us to keep faith with
them." Budziszewski J., "Handling Issues
of Conscience." The Newman Rambler, Vol. 3, No. 2,
Spring/Summer 1999, P. 4.
17. Maddock J.W.
"Humanizing health care services. The practice of medicine as a moral
enterprise." J Natl Med Assoc. 1973 November; 65(6):
501–passim. PMCID: PMC2609038 (Accessed 2014-02-18)
18. Somerville M.
"Why are they throwing brickbats at God?" MercatorNet, 1 June,
2007 (Accessed 2014-08-03)
19. Canadian Medical Association,
Code
of Ethics (2004): Fundamental Responsibilities No. 1.
(Accessed 2014-02-15)
20. Canadian Medical Association
Code
of Ethics (2004):
"21. Provide your patients with the information they need to make informed
decisions about their medical care, and answer their questions to the best
of your ability." (Accessed 2014-02-22)
21. Murray B.
"Informed Consent: What Must a Physician Disclose to a Patient?" American Medical Association Journal of
Ethics, Virtual Mentor. July 2012, Volume 14, Number 7: 563-566.
(Accessed
2014-02-22)
22. Canadian Medical Association
Code
of Ethics (2004): "12. Inform your patient when your personal values would influence
the recommendation or practice of any medical procedure that the patient
needs or wants." (Accessed 2014-02-22)
23. Canadian Medical Association
Code
of Ethics (2004): "45. Recognize a responsibility to give generally held opinions of
the profession when interpreting scientific knowledge to the public; when
presenting an opinion that is contrary to the generally held opinion of the
profession, so indicate."
(Accessed
2014-02-22)
24. Canadian Medical Association
Code
of Ethics (2004): "22. Make every reasonable effort to communicate with your patients
in such a way that information exchanged is understood."
(Accessed
2014-02-22)
25. Singer P. Practical Ethics (2nd Ed.).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, p. 3; Kreeft P.
Fundamentals of the Faith. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1988, p.
74-80. On line (Chapter 11) as
"The Uniqueness of Christianity." (Accessed 2015-03-05)
26.
This presumption obviously underlies standard
bioethics texts. See, for example, Beauchamp TL, Childress JF,
Principles of Biomedical Ethics (7th ed) New York: Oxford University
Press, 2013
27.
Benson, I.T., "Seeing
Through the Secular Illusion" (July 29, 2013). NGTT Deel 54
Supplementum 4, 2013. (Accessed 2014-02-18)
28.
Chamberlain v. Surrey School District No. 36 [2002] 4 S.C.R.
710 (SCC), para. 137 (Accessed 2014-08-03). Dr. Benson adds: "Madam Justice
McLachlin, who wrote the decision of the majority, accepted the reasoning of
Mr. Justice Gonthier on this point thus making his the reasoning of all nine
judges in relation to the interpretation of ‘secular.’" Benson I.T., "Seeing
Through the Secular Illusion" (July 29, 2013). NGTT Deel 54
Supplementum 4, 2013. (Accessed 2014-02-18)
29.
Submission of the Ontario Human Rights Commission to the College of
Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario Regarding the draft policy, "Physicians
and the Ontario Human Rights Code." 15 August, 2008. (Accessed
2014-03-11), citing Norton K.C.
"Letter to Ontario's Attorney General expressing concern about allowing
public officials to refuse to marry same-sex couples." (Accessed
2014-03-11)
30.
Submission of the Ontario Human Rights Commission to the College of
Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario Regarding the draft policy, "Physicians
and the Ontario Human Rights Code." 15 August, 2008. (Accessed
2014-03-11)
31. ". . . if, despite being a belief system,
secularism is not excluded from the public square, then religious voices
should not be excluded on that basis. The mistake is in taking a disjunctive
(either secularism or religion) approach to a situation that requires a
conjunctive (both this and that, secularism and religion) approach. We need
all voices to be heard in the democratic public square." Somerville M.
"Should religion be evicted from the public square?" The Warrane
Lecture 2011. Kensington, NSW Australia: Warrane College, August, 2011,
p. 12. (Accessed 2014-08-02)
32. Waldron, MA, "Campuses, Courts and Culture
Wars." Convivium, February/March 2014, p. 33
33. The distinction between ethics and morality is
mainly a matter of usage. Recent trends identify ethics as the application
of morality to a specific discipline, like medicine or law. In a broader and
older sense, ethics is concerned with how man ought to live, while the study
of morality focuses on ethical obligations. See the entry on "Ethics and
Morality" in Honderich T. (Ed.) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy
(2nd Ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
34. Murphy S.
"Redefining the Practice of Medicine- Euthanasia in Quebec, Part 6:
Participation in Killing." Protection of Conscience Project,
July, 2014.
35. Marmor A. Law in the Age of Pluralism.
New York: Oxford University Press, 2007, p. 218
36. Mackay B.
"Sign in office ends
clash between MD's beliefs, patients' requests." CMAJ January
7, 2003 vol. 168 no. 1 (Accessed 2014-02-16 )
37. Cannold L.
"The questionable ethics of unregulated conscientious refusal." ABC
Religion and Ethics, 25 March, 2011. (Accessed 2013-08-11)
Human Rights Council, Twentieth session, Agenda items 2 and 3:
Annual Report of the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for
Human Rights- Technical guidance on the application of a human rights based
approach to the implementation of policies and programmes to reduce
preventable maternal morbidity and mortality (2 July, 20012) para.
61, 30 (Accessed 2013-08-11)
O'Rourke A, De Crespigny L, and Pyman A.
"Abortion and Conscientious
Objection: The New Battleground" (July 10, 2012). Monash Law Review
(2012) Vol 38(3): 87-119. (Accessed 2013-08-18)
Finer L., Fine JB.,
"Abortion Law Around the World: Progress and Pushback." American
Journal of Public Health, Apr 2013, Vol. 103 Issue 4, p. 585. (Accessed
2013-08-18)
Human Rights Council, 23nd Session - June 3, 2013. Agenda Item 3:
Presentation of Reports by the Special Rapporteur on Violence against Women.
"Oral
Statement: Center for Reproductive Rights." (Accessed 20-13-08-11)
38. Gardner J. "Complicity and Causality," 1
Crim. Law & Phil. 127, 129 (2007). Cited in Haque, A.A.
"Torture, Terror, and the
Inversion of Moral Principle." New Criminal Law Review, Vol.
10, No. 4, pp. 613-657, 2007; Workshop: Criminal Law, Terrorism, and the
State of Emergency, May 2007. (Accessed 2014-02-19)
39. Haque, A.A.
"Torture, Terror, and the
Inversion of Moral Principle." New Criminal Law Review, Vol.
10, No. 4, pp. 613-657, 2007; Workshop: Criminal Law, Terrorism, and the
State of Emergency, May 2007. (Accessed 2014-02-19)
40. Murphy S.
"Redefining the Practice of
Medicine- Euthanasia in Quebec, Part 9: Codes of Ethics and Killing."
Protection of Conscience Project, July, 2014.
41. Email to the Administrator, Protection of
Conscience Project, from P__ H__ (present at College Council meeting 18
September, 2008) (2014-02-11, 10:10 am)
42.
Wiesel E. "Without
Conscience." N Engl J Med 352;15 april14, 2005 (Accessed
2014-02-24)
43.
Trinity Western University v. College of Teachers, [2001] 1
S.C.R. 772, 2001 SCC 31 (Accessed 2014-07-29)
44. Cromwell, Oliver, "Declaration of the Lord
Lieutenant of Ireland." (January, 1649) Carlyle, Thomas, Oliver Cromwell’s
Letters and Speeches, with elucidations. Boston: Estes and Lauriat, 1886,
Vol. I, Part 5, p. 18.
45. This section of the paper draws from an
extended discussion of the subject in Murphy S, Geunis S.J.
"Freedom
of Conscience in Health Care: Distinctions and Limits." J Bioeth
Inq. 2013 Oct; 10(3): 347-54
46.
R.
v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 165. Accessed
2015-02-26.
47.
R.
v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 176. Accessed
2015-02-26.
48.
R.
v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 166. Accessed
2015-02-26.
49. R.
v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654;
Québec (Curateur public) c. Syndicat national des employés
de l'Hôpital St-Ferdinand, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 211 (Accessed
2015-03-05).
50.
R.
v. Morgentaler
(1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 179. Accessed
2015-02-26.
51.
R.
v. Morgentaler
(1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) p. 95-96. Accessed
2015-02-26.
52.
Carter v. Canada (Attorney General), 2015 SCC 5, para. 132.
(Accessed 2015-02-25)
| Next