Submission to the General Medical Council of the United Kingdom
Re: Personal beliefs and medical practice:
A draft for consultation (18 April-13 June, 2012)
3 June, 2012
Full Text
Introduction:
The Protection of Conscience Project is a non-profit, non-denominational
initiative that advocates for freedom of conscience in health care. The
Project does not take a position on the morality or desirability of
controversial procedures or services.
This submission comments on the draft consultation document,
Personal beliefs and medical practice.1 It presumes that the document pertains only
to conscientious objection arising from moral or ethical objections to a
treatment, not to situations in which physicians deem a treatment to be
medically contra-indicated, even if they also object to it for reasons of
conscience.
In order to avoid misunderstanding and to identify common ground, the
submission opens in Part I by identifying
and defining key terms, drawing attention, when appropriate, to differences
in terminology used by the draft consultation document. This is followed by
a summary of points of agreement in
Part II, not without an occasional caveat to ensure that the summary is
correctly understood.
Part III
summarizes some points that, if clarified or appropriately qualified,
might increase the scope of agreement. Points of disagreement are identified
and discussed in Part IV.
The submission closes with recommendations (Part
V) for modification of the guideline.
I.1 The consultation document states that "personal beliefs" include
"political, religious and moral beliefs," but also refers to "personal
views" and "personal values," terms that are not necessarily equivalent to
"personal beliefs." Nonetheless, the draft document seems to use all of these
interchangeably. In this submission, the terms "personal beliefs" and
"beliefs" mean moral, ethical or religious beliefs.
I.2 For the sake of brevity, treatments that are the subject of
conscientious objection are sometimes described here as "morally contested,"
and those who decline to provide morally contested treatments for ethical,
moral or religious reasons are referred to as "objecting physician(s)."
I.3 The distinction between "treatment" and "care" is important in
significant religious, moral and ethical traditions, but the distinction is
not made in the draft consultation document. Hence, its references to
"medical care" or "care" are ambiguous.
I.4 In this submission:
i) "care" means attention to and provision of basic
human needs: food, water, shelter, hygiene, warmth, respect, affection,
etc.;
ii) "treatment" means interventions, procedures or
services provided through or sought from physicians and other health care
providers.
I.5 Note the restricted sense of the term "treatment." The interventions,
procedures or services are not described in this submission as medical
because objecting physicians frequently deny that morally contested
procedures are legitimate aspects of the practice of medicine. However,
there is no dispute that morally contested treatments may be "provided
through or sought from physicians and other health care providers." (See
IV.26.)
Notice
II.1 It is reasonable to expect physicians to do their best to notify
patients and employers in advance of treatments to which they object for
reasons of conscience. It is common ground that conflicts should be avoided,
especially in circumstances of elevated tension, and that they often can be
avoided by timely notification of patients and employers, erring on the side
of sooner rather than later. This must not be understood to impose a duty to
anticipate every conceivable situation in which such an objection might
arise.
Post-procedural treatment or care
II.2 The Project agrees that it is normally unethical for a physician to
refuse to provide treatment or care to a patient on the grounds that she has
had an abortion or other morally contested treatment. Objecting physicians
do not become morally complicit in the prior acts of patients simply by
treating medical consequences that result from their conduct.2 The fact that
a patient's illness or injury is the result deliberate, negligent or even
criminal conduct has never been a reason to deny medical treatment.
Discussion of beliefs
II.3 It is agreed that disclosure by a physician of his beliefs is
acceptable only when the disclosure is solicited by a patient, or when it is
reasonable to believe that it would be welcomed by the patient. It is also
agreed that such disclosure and discussion ought to be limited to what is
relevant to the patient's care and treatment. This should not be interpreted
so strictly as to prevent a dialogue that is responsive to the needs of the
patient as a human person.3 It cannot be interpreted to exclude disclosure of
conscientious objection and conversation naturally arising from it, since
disclosure is required by the General Medical Council (GMC).4
"Unfair" discrimination
III.1 The draft document's reference to "unfair" discrimination
implicitly acknowledges that not all kinds of discrimination are unfair. The
draft itself discriminates between what is legal and illegal, for example.
However, discrimination between what moral or immoral, ethical or unethical,
requires the application of an ethical or moral standard. Only to the extent
that there is agreement on the content of such a standard can all agree on
what counts as "unfair" discrimination. Within the context of the draft
document, it is not clear that there is agreement on the standard to be
applied.
"Likely" to cause distress
III.2 It is agreed that physicians must be careful not to "cause
distress" by an "inappropriate or insensitive expression" of their beliefs
to patients. However, a patient may be distressed merely because a physician
refuses to provide a service, no matter how carefully that refusal is
conveyed. Moreover, disgruntled patients or activists may fabricate claims
of distress in order to harass physicians through disciplinary proceedings.
Thus, "distress" in a patient - whether proved as a fact or advanced as a
claim - is not necessarily evidence of professional misconduct.
Implied judgement
III.3 The draft warns that physicians must not "imply any judgement" of
patients when disclosing conscientious objections. However, a physician
cannot make such an objection without first forming the judgement that the
treatment is immoral. It is reasonable to believe that the communication of
the objection, which the GMC requires,5 will cause patients to infer
(correctly) the beliefs of the physician concerning the treatment. Patients
may thus "feel judged" by the physician, even if the physician's judgement
pertains to the morality of the procedure rather than the personal
culpability of the patient. It would be unjust to require physicians to
disclose conscientious objections to patients and then discipline them
because a patient resents their beliefs.
Irrelevance of lifestyle
II.4 Many conditions treated by physicians are the result of patient
choices about diet and exercise, the use of alcohol, tobacco and illicit
drugs and other risk-taking behaviours: sometimes, even, of criminal
misconduct. Thus, the Project agrees that physicians "must not refuse to
treat the health consequences of lifestyle choices" with which they disagree
or to which they object. (Emphasis added. See II.2.) However, this must not
be understood to imply that objecting physicians are obliged to provide
morally contested treatments. For example: in some circumstances, pregnancy
and infertility may be considered to be "health consequences" of lifestyle
choices. It does not follow that objecting physicians must treat pregnancy
and infertility by abortion and artificial reproduction.
Non-obstruction
III.5 Objecting physicians act to preserve their own integrity, not to
control the conduct of patients. Thus, it is agreed that physicians who
refuse to provide a treatment for reasons of conscience are not entitled to
actively prevent patients from obtaining the treatment elsewhere. However,
physicians may also refuse to delegate or refer for a morally contested
treatment in order to preserve their personal integrity. That must be
distinguished from 'obstruction.' (See III.7.)
Pre-procedural treatment
III.6 As noted above, post-procedural treatment or care does not, of
itself, make objecting physicians morally complicit in the prior conduct of
patients. There is also no reason to deny pre-procedural treatment or care
that is unrelated to a morally contested treatment. However, physicians may
refuse to services or procedures that are meant to facilitate such
treatments in order to avoid morally unacceptable complicity in them. (See
III.7.)
Disclosure of options
III.7 Objecting physicians are required to disclose the availability of
treatments that they find objectionable, and to advise patients that they
may seek the advice of physicians willing to provide them. However, the
consultation document fails to recognize that physicians may be unwilling to
provide such information or advice if they believe that doing so makes them
complicit in a morally contested treatment, or if disclosure may be harmful
to the patient. This point becomes especially important in jurisdictions
where assisted suicide or euthanasia are legal, and a physician is concerned
that disclosing such options may have a disproportionate impact on a
vulnerable patient. The position of objecting physicians on this point is
the same as that of the GMC on providing information that supports the sale
of organs, or providing information or reports that could facilitate
assisted suicide. (See IV.21.)
Specious claims of discrimination
IV.1 The draft claims that physicians are obliged to
provide or facilitate 'gender reassignment,' and that they cannot refuse
contraceptives to unmarried women if they provide contraceptives to married
women. The basis for both claims is that only "a particular group of
patients" seek 'gender reassignment,' that "unmarried women" constitute
another "particular group," and that conscientious objection is prohibited
because objections in these cases are to "particular groups" of patients,
not to morally contested treatments.
IV.2 The GMC admits that current British statutes regulating abortion and
artificial reproduction prevent it from directly prohibiting conscientious
objection to such procedures. Nonetheless, the GMC's legal reasoning seems
to preclude conscientious objection to both. Only women - a "particular group of
patients" - request abortion. Again, only women
with multifetal pregnancies - another "particular group" - request selective
reduction.6
Only a "particular group" - those unable to
conceive naturally - seek artificial reproduction.
IV.3 At the very least, the GMC's reasoning with respect to contraception
leads to the conclusion that selective conscientious objection to abortion
is not permitted. Women over 14 weeks pregnant - just like "unmarried women"
- form a "particular group." It would seem, then, that the GMC considers
physicians are guilty of unfair discrimination if they provide abortions
only for women who are less than 14 weeks pregnant. Of course, the same
could be said of physicians willing to provide abortions in the second
trimester, but not in the third.7
IV.4 Similarly, it appears that at least selective
conscientious objection to artificial reproduction will be forbidden.
Applying the GMC's logic, a physician who provides or facilitates artificial
reproductive services for infertile couples would be forced to provide the
same services for everyone, including, for example, a man who has had sex
change surgery who wishes to use sperm frozen before surgery to conceive a
child, so that he can be both father and mother.
8
It is disingenuous to pretend that there is any moral or ethical consensus
on many of the issues involved with artificial reproduction,
9
and unacceptable for the GMC to use its disciplinary powers to impose its
moral views under the pretence that there is.
IV.5 If the GMC is concerned about access to abortion and contraception,
the draft consultation document is likely to reduce access, not increase it.
If physicians who provide earlier abortions are forbidden from
'discriminating' against women who are further along, those with moral
qualms about later procedures may prudently refrain from developing the
skills needed for them,10 or give up abortion practice altogether. Similarly,
physicians who now offer contraceptives only to married couples may cease
prescribing to anyone in order to avoid being forced to provide them to the
unmarried.
IV.6 The conflict between the GMC position and the statutory protection
of conscience provisions pertaining to abortion and artificial reproduction
complicate evaluation of the draft document. However, this complication does
not arise in the case of other legal but morally contested treatments sought
by "particular groups."
IV.7 Apotemnophiliacs, for example, request the amputation of healthy
limbs. In 1999, the GMC and professional bodies approved single leg
amputations on two apotemnophiliacs at the Falkirk & District Royal
Infirmary in Scotland.11 If one follows the reasoning of the draft
consultation document, all physicians must be willing to provide or
facilitate amputations of healthy limbs because refusal to do so would
amount to discrimination against a "particular group of patients."
IV.8 Only severely disabled children are candidates for "Ashley's
treatment" - surgical and pharmaceutical interventions to stunt their growth
and development.12 Again, the rationale offered by the document indicates that
refusal to provide or facilitate such treatments 'discriminates' against
this "particular group of patients,"so that conscientious objection should
be prohibited in such circumstances.
IV.9 One could, of course, go further. Only males seek ritual male
circumcision. Only conjoined twins are candidates for separative surgery.13
Only self-mutilators are likely to ask that knives and other implements be
provided as part of their care plans.14 Only certain "particular groups" might
seek prescription medication to help them conform to religious teachings
about sex.15 All of these are morally contested treatments, but, since they
are sought by "particular groups of patients," it would seem that all must
be provided or facilitated by physicians, since refusal to do so would be
'discriminatory.'
IV.10 This demonstrates the first problem with the GMC's reasoning.
"Particular group" is so elastic a notion that it can be applied to
innumerable sub-groups of patients or stretched to include all of them as a
subset of the population: "those seeking the service of a physician." The
term is useful for fabricating specious claims of illicit discrimination,
but for this very reason it fails to provide an acceptable standard by which
to evaluate the conduct of objecting physicians.
IV.11 Certainly, it would be improper for a physician to refuse to
provide services or treatment to someone because of
hisr race, ethnic origin, religious beliefs, etc.
But conscientious objectors are concerned to avoid
moral complicity in wrongdoing, not with the sex, marital status or "group status" of
the patient. Objections, if they arise, are to abortion, even though only
women can have abortions: to premarital sex, even though only unmarried
persons can have premarital sex: to the amputation of healthy body parts,
even though only apotemnophiliacs request such surgery.
IV.12 Further, personal characteristics may be
relevant to moral judgement. For example: a 20 year old man may not be
faulted morally or legally for having sexual intercourse, and a friend may
have no objection to making his apartment available for that purpose.
However, the friend might well refuse the favour if the prospective bedmate
were a nine year old girl rather than a nineteen year old woman, or if the
would-be Lothario were cheating on his wife. Age and marital status may both
be important factors in the friend's moral evaluation of the act and his
decision to avoid complicity in it, even though age and marital status are
"personal characteristics."
IV.13 Objecting
physicians should not be threatened with discipline for exercising this kind
of rationally comprehensive moral reasoning. It is absurd and profoundly offensive to assert that physicians who
refuse to be complicit in adultery, premarital sex, the mutilation or
amputation of healthy body parts or the killing of human embryos or fetuses
are acting like bigots.
Mandatory referral and delegation
IV.14 The draft insists that physicians who object to a
treatment may decline to provide it themselves, but must provide the patient
with "enough information" to arrange to see a non-objecting colleague who
will provide it, and, if need be, assist the patient in making arrangements
to have it provided by another physician.
IV.15 The reasoning of the draft consultation document is based on
unstated faith-assumptions of the GMC about moral complicity and
culpability. The Council appears to believe that someone who merely arranges
for an act is absolved of moral responsibility, because only someone who
actually does an act is morally responsible for it. Alternatively, the GMC
may admit that some moral responsibility is incurred by referral or by
otherwise facilitating a procedure, but that the degree of responsibility is
sufficiently diminished in such cases that it is of no real significance.
IV.16 Many physicians are willing to refer for morally contested
treatments because their evaluation of moral complicity is consistent
with
that of the GMC. The draft document fails to recognize that reasonable
physicians who work from different moral premises reach different moral
conclusions about moral complicity. Many people recognize the principle of
vicarious moral responsibility, by which an accomplice or facilitator can be
held responsible for acts done by someone else.
IV.17 The GMC can find the simplest illustration of this in provisions of
criminal law concerning parties to offences and accessories after the fact,
by which one may be convicted for indirect facilitation of criminal
offences. The Medical Defence Union cautioned physicians about this in
advice offered late last year.16
IV.18 The draft document fails to consider evidence taken in 2004 and
2005 by the British House of Lords Select Committee on Assisted Dying for
the Terminally Ill, and the conclusions of the Committee concerning a bill
to legalize euthanasia. The bill, in its original form, included a
requirement that objecting physicians refer patients for euthanasia.
Numerous submissions protested this provision because it made objecting
physicians a moral party to the procedure,17and the Joint Committee on Human
Rights concluded that the demand was probably a violation of the European
Convention on Human Rights.18 The bill's sponsor, Lord Joffe, promised to
delete the provision in his next draft of the bill.19
IV.19 The GMC also appears to be unfamiliar with
the moral reasoning of those concerned about the complicity of health care
workers through even indirect participation in torture and abusive
interrogations. The World Medical Association (WMA) Declaration of Tokyo states that physicians are
"ethically prohibited from conducting any evaluation, or providing
information or treatment, that may facilitate the future or further conduct
of torture."20 More recently, the WMA has emphasized that physicians "are
prohibited from participating or even being present" during torture or other
inhuman or degrading procedures.21 The Lancet, among others, has asked, "How
complicit are doctors in the abuse of detainees?"22 and other journal articles
have explored the answer with some anxiety.23
IV.20 Where capital punishment is legal, physicians may be
expected by the state or others to participate in executions, especially
those performed by means of lethal injection. The World Medical Association
states that physicians must not "participate in capital punishment in any
way, or during any step of the execution process," including planning and
instruction.24 The American Medical Association
(AMA) forbids physician
participation in executions, defining "participation" to include the same
kind of actions that would be involved in referral or delegation.25 The model
provided by the World Medical Association and AMA policy on physician
involvement in execution and torture indicates that, in principle, it is not
unreasonable for physicians to refuse to refer patients for procedures to
which they object for reasons of conscience, on the grounds that referral
would make them complicit in a wrongful act.
IV.21 The point here, of course, is not that capital punishment or
torture are morally equivalent to morally contested treatments. The point is
that, when professional associations are convinced that an act is seriously
wrong - even if it is legal - one finds them willing to refuse all forms of
direct and indirect participation in order to avoid moral complicity in the
act. The GMC acted on this principle when it disciplined a physician who
provided information about the sale of organs but did not actually engage in
the practice.26 It has also applied this principle in recent draft guidance on
assisted suicide.27 Conscientious objectors who refuse to refer or delegate
for morally contested treatments act on the same principle, and it would be
hypocritical if the GMC were to discipline them for doing so.
IV.22 Moreover, the principle that conscientious objectors ought to be
forced to refer a patient would, logically, apply to all morally contested
treatments. The GMC has already set a precedent by its approval of the
amputation of healthy limbs (See IV.7), which is logically consistent with
its support for sex-change surgery (See IV.1). Nonetheless, many physicians
do not share the GMC's ethical evaluation of such surgery. Before compelling
them to provide, refer or delegate for such procedures, the GMC should at
least demonstrate the superiority of its own moral beliefs and justify why
those who find them unsatisfactory should be made to conform to them, or be
struck from the medical register.
IV.23 Referral is often erroneously explained as "striking a balance"
between the interests of the physician and those of the patient. However, in
cases of conscientious objection their interests cannot be balanced because
they are not commensurable; they concern fundamentally different goods. A
patient has an interest in obtaining a particular product or service, but
the physician has an interest in maintaining his personal integrity. With
sufficient imagination and political will one may find a way to accommodate
the interests of both, but no 'balance' is achieved by subordinating one to
the other.
Physicians must set aside personal beliefs
IV.24 It is the expectation of the General Medical
Council that physicians will "set aside their personal beliefs" if those
beliefs effectively deny patients "access to appropriate medical treatment
or services" or cause "distress" to patients.
IV.25 Beliefs may be "personal," in the sense that one personally accepts
them, but this does not make them parochial, insignificant or erroneous.
Christian, Jewish and Muslim beliefs, for example, are shared by hundreds of
millions of people. They "personally" adhere to their beliefs just as
non-religious believers "personally" adhere to non-religious beliefs. In
neither case does the fact of this "personal" commitment provide grounds to
set beliefs aside. Thus, the reference to "personal" beliefs seems to have
no other purpose than to belittle the beliefs of objecting physicians.
IV.26 The draft asserts almost at the outset that physicians may practise
according to their beliefs only if they do not thereby deny patients "access
to appropriate medical treatment or services," (emphasis added). The
presumption that the contentious treatments are medical treatments may
reflect the bias of the GMC. It is prejudicial because it effectively
decides a key issue in advance. It is also unnecessary for the purposes of
the draft, which does not subsequently describe contentious treatments as
medical. (See I.5.)
IV.27 For the reasons stated in III.2, that a patient is "distressed" is
not necessarily evidence of professional misconduct.
IV.28 The expectation that physicians will "set aside their personal
beliefs" may reflect the view that, as professionals, physicians should be
willing to subordinate their personal interest and comforts to those of
their patients: that self-sacrifice is an important aspect of
professionalism.28 However, self-sacrifice has never been understood to
include the sacrifice of one's integrity. To abandon one's moral or ethical
convictions in order to provide services demanded by others is prostitution,
not professionalism.29
IV.29 The GMC's expectation that physicians will "set aside their
personal beliefs" actually requires more than that. One cannot simply "set
aside" beliefs and operate in a moral vacuum. Thus, the draft document
requires not only that physicians give up moral or ethical standards they
believe to be true, but that they adopt standards approved by the GMC, even
if they believe them to be false. What is expected is religious, moral or
ethical conversion. The draft document signals the intention of the GMC to
prosecute those who refuse to convert to the religious, moral or ethical
systems it approves.
IV.30 Alternatively, the GMC may be content to allow physicians to
believe what they wish, so long as they outwardly conform to its
expectations by acting as if their beliefs do not exist. Rather than
pursuing a policy of forced conversion, the GMC may simply be resurrecting
the Test Act in modern professional dress: requiring physicians to agree to
do what they believe to be gravely wrong as a condition for practising
medicine in the United Kingdom.30
IV.31 In either case, it would be unfair to impose on physicians
long-discredited policies of forced conversion and exclusion that would be
plainly unacceptable to other professions and to the people of the United
Kingdom as a whole.
IV.32 It may be argued that freedom of conscience is not unlimited, and
that the limits the GMC seeks to impose are reasonable. However, nothing in
the draft document indicates that the GMC has actually considered the nature
or importance of personal integrity and freedom of conscience, or that it
has carefully investigated the issues relevant to establishing a rational
and principled approach to limiting fundamental freedoms.
IV.33 Freedom of conscience can be exercised in two different but
complementary ways; one may pursue an apparent good, or one may avoid an
apparent evil. The decision to pursue an apparent good can be called the
exercise of perfective freedom of conscience because it is potentially
perfective of the human person. A decision to avoid an apparent evil can be
described as an exercise of preservative freedom of conscience.
IV.34 The distinction between preservative and perfective freedom of
conscience is critical. Preservative freedom of conscience is more
fundamental than perfective freedom of conscience because the latter depends
upon the preservation of moral character ensured by the former. By its
nature, perfective freedom of conscience demands much more of society than
preservative freedom of conscience.
IV.35 Limiting perfective freedom of conscience prevents people from
doing the good that they wish to do, and may (if no alternatives are
available) prevent them from perfecting themselves, fulfilling their
personal aspirations or achieving some social goals. This may do them some
wrong, but, if it does them some wrong, it does not necessarily do them an
injury.
IV.36 In contrast, to force people to do something they believe to be
wrong is always an assault on their personal dignity and essential humanity,
even if they are objectively in error; it is always harmful to the
individual, and it always has negative implications for society. It is a
policy fundamentally opposed to civic friendship, which grounds and sustains
political community and provides the strongest motive for justice. It is
inconsistent with the best traditions and aspirations of liberal democracy,
since it instills attitudes more suited to totalitarian regimes than to the
demands of responsible freedom. By demanding the submission of intellect,
will and conscience it reduces the person to a form of servitude that cannot
be reconciled with principles of equality.31
Terminology
V.1 The guideline should
a) use consistent terminology by referring only to
beliefs;
b) refrain from describing the beliefs of objecting
physicians as personal, or from describing them in other irrelevant or
prejudicial terms;
c) acknowledge and explain the distinction made by
ethical and religious traditions between care and treatment;
d) describe morally contested treatments simply as
treatments or services rather than medical treatments or services.
Notice
V.2 The guideline should clarify that the expectation that advance notice
should be given of objections to morally contested procedures does not mean
that physicians are expected to anticipate every conceivable situation in
which such an objection might arise.
Discussion of beliefs
V.3 The guideline should
a) clarify that physicians will not be disciplined
for reasonably complying with their obligation to disclose their objections
and for conversation with a patient that naturally follows from the
disclosure;
b) acknowledge that patient resentment of or anger at
physician beliefs does not afford grounds for discipline;
c) acknowledge that the emotional reaction of a
patient to the required disclosure of physician objections is not
necessarily evidence of professional misconduct.
Unfair discrimination
V.4 The guideline should clarify what standards the GMC will apply when
considering allegations that a physician has "unfairly" discriminated
against a patient.
"Health consequences"
V.5 The guideline should clarify that the obligation to treat the health
consequences of patient conduct does not imply an obligation to provide
morally contested treatments.
Preservation of personal integrity
V.6 The guideline should distinguish between attempts to control patient
conduct by obstruction of morally contested treatment and attempts to
maintain personal integrity by refusing to facilitate such treatments by
referral, delegation, or preparation.
Presentation of options
V.7 The guideline should acknowledge that physicians will not be
disciplined simply for failing to provide information or advice that they
believe will harm the patient or make them complicit in a morally contested
treatment.
"Particular group"
V.8 The guideline should make clear that physicians
a) may decline to provide services or treatments that
they believe make them complicit in wrongful acts, but
b) may not decline to provide services or treatments
because of personal characteristics of
a patient unrelated to moral or ethical evaluation
of the consequences of the services or treatments.
V.9 The guideline should not base ethical evaluation of physician conduct
upon the alleged group status of a patient.
Referral and delegation
V.10 The guideline may recommend
a) that objecting physicians consider referral and
delegation for morally contested treatments as a means of accommodating
patient requests while maintaining their personal integrity, and
b) if referral or delegation is not acceptable, that
objecting physicians be prepared to explain the moral or ethical reasoning
for their judgement.
V.11 The guideline should not demand that objecting physicians refer
patients or otherwise facilitated morally contested treatments.
"Personal integrity"
V.12 The guideline should be revised to eliminate any suggestion that
a) physicians should be forced to adopt beliefs that
they find objectionable; or
b) physicians ought to do what they believe to be
wrong.
Notes
1. General Medical Council,
Personal beliefs and medical practice: A draft for consultation
(18 April-13 June, 2012) (Accessed 2012-05-17)
2. The situation would be otherwise if the
physician were to affirm the conduct of the patient, but this is not
something one would expect an objecting physician to do, and simply
providing post-procedural treatment or care does not necessarily imply
such an affirmation.
3. The draft quotes a passage in Good
Medical Practice that refers to "psychological, spiritual,
religious, social and cultural factors" that are relevant to patient
care and treatment.
4. Good Medical Practice 52.
5. Good Medical
Practice 52.
6. MacNair, Trisha,
"Selective Reduction in Pregnancy." BBC Health, June, 2008.
(Accessed 2012-05-02) In 2002 at the Royal Victoria Infirmary in
Newcastle it was suggested that a twin with a serious heart defect
should be aborted in the 35th week of pregnancy. The suggestion was
highly controversial and one physician threatened to commence legal
action against the medical director of the hospital if the abortion
proceeded. Rogers, L., "Doctors revolt over last-minute abortion of
twin," The Sunday Times, 10 November, 2002. Also reported in
British Nursing News on Line, 10 November, 2002 (Accessed
2006-06-13)
GLADonline, 18 November, 2002. (Accessed 2012-05-02)
7. Most physicians in the United Kingdom do
not provide abortions after 12 to 14 weeks gestation, and seem
uninterested in developing the skills to do so. [Quinn, Ben and Boseley,
Sarah,
"Anti-abortion climate 'will deter new generation of doctors': British
Pregnancy Advisory Service attacks politicisation of abortion and warns
of impact on future healthcare." The Guardian, 1 April 2012
(Accessed 2012-04-02)] The reluctance of Scots physicians to provide
abortions after 15 weeks gestation has resulted in women travelling to
England for the procedure. [Templeton, Sarah Kate,
"Private firm plans Scottish abortion clinic." The Sunday Herald,
19 January, 2003. (Accessed 2012-06-03).] Abortion had been legal in
Britain for over a generation when a third of junior doctors were
reported to be conscientious objectors to the procedure. [Saunders,
Peter,
"Abortion and Conscientious Objection." Triple Helix,
January, 1999.] The shortage of British physicians willing to provide
abortions after 12 to 14 weeks is not an isolated phenomenon associated
to domestic political issues. On the contrary: it appears to be part of
a world-wide pattern:
"French Doctors Rethinking Abortions in Face of New Law: At One
Hospital, Physicians Quit en Masse." Zenit, 7 November,
2001. (Accessed 2012-06-03);
"Doctors under pressure as abortion demand goes up." Than Nien
News, 15 March, 2010 (Accessed 2010-05-21);
"Quebec hopes to offer late-term abortions." CBC News, 10
September, 2004. (Accessed 2006-06-13);
"Royal College calls for conscience decision on second trimester
abortions." Radio New Zealand,11 March, 2006 (Accessed
2006-03-11); Ward, Harvey,
Are State
Doctors in the Western Cape willing to implement the Choice of
Termination of Pregnancy Act of 1996? An opinion survey conducted in the
Western Cape in November 1997. In fulfillment for the
requirements of the FCOG (S.A.) part 2.; Marek, Marla J., Nurses'
Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting.
JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004.
8. Oldham,
Jeanett, "'I
want to be father and mother.'" The Scotsman, 10 December,
2001 (Accessed 2012-05-25)
9. For example,
there is substantial disagreement about the wisdom of providing
artificial reproductive services for single people and same-sex couples.
See Somerville, Margaret,
"Dispossessed
and forgotten: the new class of genetic orphans."
Mercatornet, 18 September, 2007 (ccessed 2012-05-25);
"Focus on Same Sex Marriage: The Case Against." Mercatornet,
28 July, 2011. (Accessed 2012-05-25)
10. Assuming, of course, that the GMC will not
require that anyone who provides abortions at all is obliged to acquire and
maintain the skills necessary to provide third trimester abortions.
11. Ramsay, Sarah,
"Controversy over UK surgeon who
amputated healthy limbs". The Lancet, Volume 355, Number
9202, 05 February 2000. (Accessed 4 October, 2001)
12. Pilkington, Ed and McVeigh, Karen,
"'Ashley treatment' on the rise amid concerns from disability rights
groups: Controversial medical procedure to limit growth of severely
disabled children is being increasingly used, Guardian learns."
The Guardian, 15 March 2012 (Accessed 2012-03-16)
13. Boseley, Sarah,
"Law
decided fate of Mary and Jodie." The Guardian, 5 February
2002 (Accessed 2012-05-02)
14.
Citing the precedent of 'harm
reduction' by providing syringes to drug addicts, some members of the
Royal College of Nursing have argued that patients who mutilate
themselves by burning or cutting should be allowed to keep their 'tools'
with them in hospital. They claim that this helps patients deal with
mental trauma and actually reduces suicidal ideation. St. George's
mental health hospital in Staffordshire provided cleaning equipment for
blades and similar 'tools' in a pilot project, and has suggested that
this should be included in a patient care plan. Triggle, Nick,
"Nurses back
supervised self-harm: Nurses want to be allowed to let patients who
self-harm continue to do so in a safe environment in hospitals."
BBC News, 25 April, 2006 (Accessed 2012-05-02)
15. Haaretz reports that
psychiatric drugs are being prescribed to members of the ultra-orthodox
Jewish Haredi community to suppress sexual urges and help them to
conform to religious prohibitions against masturbation, homosexual
conduct and frequent sexual relations. A posting on the Practical Ethics
blog of Oxford University asks whether or not psychiatrists may, for
reasons of conscience, refuse to prescribe drugs for this reason. The
writer, quoting Julian Salvulescu, reasons "a psychiatrist has no ground
for conscientious objection and should provide the treatment to
Haredim," but ultimately concludes that this seems "intuitively
incorrect." See Ettinger, Yair, H"Rabbi's
little helper: Forget 'Big Brother': Psychiatric drugs are frequently
administered within the Haredi community at leaders' requests, in order
to bring members in line with norms, say sources." Haaretz,
(Accessed 2012-05-02); Devolder, Katrien,
"Psychiatric drugs to enhance conformity to religious norms, and
conscientious objection." University of Oxford, Practical
Ethics: Ethics in the News, 10 April, 2012. (Accessed 2012-05-02)
16.
"Assisting a Criminal Offence." MDU Journal, Vol. 7, Issue 22,
November, 2011, p. 24. (Accessed 2012-05-17)
17. United Kingdom Parliament,
House of Lords Select
Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill: Selections from
the First Report
18. Joint Committee On Human Rights
Twelfth Report:
Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill, Para. 3.11 to
3.16. (Accessed 2012-06-03)
19. Select Committee on Assisted Dying for
the Terminally Ill Bill,
Minutes of Evidence: Examination of Witnesses (Questions 70
- 79) , Thursday, 16 September, 2004, Q70. (Accessed 2012-05-23)
20. World Medical Association,
Declaration of Tokyo: Guidelines for Physicians Concerning Torture and
other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment in Relation to
Detention and Imprisonment. (May, 2005) (Emphasis added)
(Accessed 2012-05-22)
21. World Medical Association, News Release,
"Physicians Reminded of their ethical obligations in relation to torture
and interrogation." (15 May, 2009) (Emphasis added) (Accessed
2012-05-22)
22. Editorial, "How complicit are doctors in
the abuse of detainees?" The Lancet, Vol 364, August 21, 2004,
p. 725-729
23. Miles, Steven H., "Abu Ghraib: its
legacy for military medicine." The Lancet, Vol 364, August 21,
2004, p. 725-729; Lifton, Robert Jay, Doctors and Torture. N
Engl J Med 351;5
24. World Medical Association,
WMA
Resolution on Physician Participation in Capital Punishment
(October, 2008) (Accessed 2012-05-22)
25. American Medical Association Policy
E-2.06:
Capital Punishment (Accessed 2012-06-03)
26. The Council found that the doctor had
not participated in the organ trade, but that his conduct amounted to
"encouragement of the trade in human organs from live donors". BBC
News,
"Organ trade GP suspended." 15 October, 2002 (Accessed 2012-05-18)
27. Among the kinds of conduct that may
constitute illicit facilitation or cooperation in assisted suicide, the
GMC includes: "encouraging a person to commit suicide, for example, by
suggesting it (whether prompted or unprompted) as a 'treatment' option .
. .providing practical assistance, for example, by helping a person who
wishes to commit suicide to travel to the place where they will be
assisted to do so . . . writing reports, knowing or having reason to
suspect that the . . . reports would be used to enable the person to
obtain encouragement or assistance in committing suicide. . .providing
information or advice about other sources of information about assisted
suicide, and what each method involves from a medical perspective . . ."
General Medical Council,
Guidance for the Investigation Committee and case examiners when
considering allegations about a doctor's involvement in encouraging or
assisting suicide: a draft for consultation. (Accessed
2012-05-23)
28. "Professionalism," Professor R. Alta
Charo suggests rhetorically, ought to include "the rather old-fashioned
notion of putting others before oneself." Charo, R. Alta,
The
Celestial Fire of Conscience- Refusing to Deliver Medical Care.
N Eng J Med 352:24, June 16, 2005. (Accessed 2012-06-03.)
29. Payne, Stewart,
"Hospice helped dying man lose his virginity." The Telegraph,
31 January, 2007. (Accessed 2008-11-28) See also Choy, Heather Low,
"Sex visits organised for disabled men." news.com.au, Tasmania
News, 28 September, 2005. (Accessed 2008-11-30)
30. The Test Acts in England,
Ireland and Scotland required people to pass certain 'tests' as a
condition for holding public office. Although the Test Acts might be
described as "laws of general application," they excluded Catholics and
Non-conformists from public office because the prescribed tests required
them to do what they believed to be gravely wrong, or to convert to the
Church of England.
31. For an extended discussion of the
distinction between perfective and preservative freedom of conscience,
see Murphy, Sean Notes
toward an understanding of freedom of conscience. Protection of
Conscience Project, 15 March, 2012.