Protection of Conscience Project
Protection of Conscience Project
www.consciencelaws.org
Service, not Servitude

Service, not Servitude

Freedom of conscience: "the heart of our democratic political tradition"


Full Text
Download PDF

Notes

1.  Lewis, Charles, "The next moral quagmire: conscience. Politics collides with freedom of workers' beliefs." National Post, 4 April, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-19).

2.  There are four kinds of professional medical organizations significant for our purposes today: regulatory authorities (like Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons), professional specialist associations (like the Society of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists Canada), professional interest associations (the Canadian Medical Association), and federations of regulatory authorities (like the Federation of Medical and Regulatory Authorities of Canada.

Professional regulatory authorities include Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons, Colleges of Pharmacists, etc. (See Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons, Provincial Medical Regulatory (Licensing) Authorities (Accessed 2010-05-20). These bodies are creatures of statute, sometimes specific to the profession, sometimes omnibus statutes that provide the ground rules for the regulation of all health care professions. They have the power to develop standards of practice or care and codes of ethics, and can enforce compliance with their standards and codes through disciplinary bylaws. They are analogous to the law societies that govern the legal profession in each province, like the Law Society of Upper Canada.

The second group includes a variety of professional specialist associations, like the Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons of Canada, which is concerned primarily with medical education, the Society of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists Canada or the British Columbia College of Family Physicians.(See Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons, National Specialist Societies (Accessed 2010-05-20). These associations have no regulatory authority and membership is voluntary, but they can develop professional standards or guidelines for their specialty. While binding only on their members, these standards tend to have wider influence. In particular, they are likely to inform the decisions of regulators as to what constitutes an appropriate standard of care. Further, they can actively influence public perceptions and policy through the media and contacts with governments. Analogous entities in the legal profession include the Advocates' Society or the Quebec Association of Family Law Practitioners.

The Canadian Medical Association and its provincial counterparts are representative of the third kind of professional organization: a generalist group that represents the interests of its members to governments and the public at large. The actual political and professional influence of these organizations depends upon their ability to speak credibly on behalf of a significant proportion of a given profession. Their counterparts in the legal profession are the Canadian Bar Association and similar provincial organizations.

The fourth category, the smallest, is comprised of federations of regulatory authorities, like the National Association of Pharmacy Regulatory Authorities (NAPRA) and the Federation of Medical and Regulatory Authorities of Canada (FMRAC). These groups attempt to develop common policies on matters relevant to practice across the country, such as common standards for licensing and registration. Membership is comprised of representatives from the provincial regulatory bodies, not of individuals. The comparable institution for the legal profession is the Federation of Law Societies of Canada.

3.  "Free the Doctor," Globe and Mail, 18 May, 1965. Quoted in de Valk, Alphonse, Morality and Law in Canadian Politics: The Abortion Controversy. Dorval, Quebec: Palm Publishers, 1974, p. 18 Two years later an editorial in the Globe stated that the Government had decided "that where religious moralities conflict, the State should support none, but leave the choice to individual conscience. It is a policy that should also be followed with abortion." "Now the job is to be done, let it be done right", Globe and Mail, 21 December, 1967. Quoted in de Valk, supra, p. 56

4.  One of these had a conscience clause almost identical to that in the British Abortion Act. Standing Committee on Health and Welfare, Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence, Appendix "QQ": Brief submitted by the Catholic Hospital Association of Canada . . . on the Matter of Abortion. February, 1968, P. 679, paragraph 19.

5.  Quoted in de Valk, supra, p. 44-45

6.  Standing Committee on Health and Welfare, Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence, Appendix "SS": Canadian Welfare Council Statement on Abortion to the House of Commons Standing Committee on Health and Welfare. February, 1968, p. 707

7.  Standing Committee on Health and Welfare, Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence, Appendix "QQ": Brief submitted by the Catholic Hospital Association of Canada . . . on the Matter of Abortion. February, 1968, p. 676

8.  The Progressive Conservatives and Creditistes put forward seven amendments intended to guarantee the right of conscientious objection to individuals or institutions. It was agreed that debate on one amendment would dispose of all seven. The clause had been proposed M.P. Robert McCleave, who was in favour of legalizing abortion. (Hansard- Commons Debates, 28 April, 1969, p. 8069)

What was then debated was to the following effect:

Nothing in the new law shall be construed as obliging any hospital to establish a therapeutic abortion committee, or any qualified medical practitioner to procure an abortion, or any member of a hospital staff to assist in abortion. (A sub-amendment was added to the original amendment. The paraphrase reflects the effect of both. (See Hansard-Commons Debates, April 28, 1969, p. 8056, 8063)

9.  Hansard-Commons Debates, April 28, 1969, p. 8058-8059

10.  Hansard- Commons Debates, 28 April, 1969, p. 8087. Senator Haidasz had long since achieved a strong pro-life reputation.

11.  The article appeared anonymously in The Humanist. See Pelrine, Eleanor Wright, Morgantaler: The Doctor Who Couldn't Turn Away. Canada: Gage Publishing, 1975, P. 79

12.  "Abortion-Care Education Is Deficient in U.S. Health Professional Training." Joint Announcement from Ibis Reproductive Health, the National Abortion Federation, and the Abortion Access Project, 9 May, 2006. (Accessed 2006-07-02).

Finer, Lawrence B., and Henshaw, Stanley K., "Abortion Incidence and Service in the United States in 2000." Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health, Vol. 35, No. 1 January/February, 2003 (Accessed 2008-11-30).

Ceci Connolly , Ceci, "Number of Abortion Providers At Its Lowest in Three Decades." Washington Post, 22 January, 2003 (Accessed 2006-07-02).

13.  Shaw, Jessica, "Reality Check: a close look at accessing abortion services in Canadian hospitals." Canadians for Choice, 2006. (Accessed 2010-05-19). While such claims must be taken with a grain of salt, about 60% of 170 Canadian obstetrician/gynaecologists who responded to a survey last year reported that they did not do abortions. About half of these were motivated by "personal beliefs." McAllister, Joe, "Most Canadian ob/gyns don't perform abortions." Medical Post, 18 August, 2009. (Accessed 2010-05-19).

14.  What constitutes a late term abortion is a somewhat subjective question. If we take fetal viability as a marker for what constitutes a 'late term' abortion, statistics in the United Kingdom show that as many as 50 babies survive abortions each year in the United Kingdom. Rogers, Lois, "Fifty babies a year are alive after abortion." The Sunday Times, 27 November, 2005. (Accessed 2006-06-13).

The British Medical Association has had to adopt policies to protect abortion survivors. [BMA Annual Representative Meeting, 2004: "That this Meeting calls upon the MSC and BMA to work with the GMC, NHS and appropriate Royal Colleges to ensure that babies born alive as a result of termination of pregnancy procedures receive the same full neonatal care as that available to other babies." (http://www.bma.org.uk) Accessed 2006-06-13.

15.  A survey conducted in 1998, years afer legalization of abortion in the United States, found that most of the 1,200 nurses surveys wanted as little to do with abortion as possible. Poggenpoel, M., Myburgh, C., & Gmeineer, A., (1998, September). "One voice regarding the legislation of abortion: Nurses who experience discomfort." Curationis, pp. 2-7. Cited in Marek, Marla J., "Nurses' Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting." JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004

Doctors at a hospital in Lyon, France, resigned en masse when administrators instructed them to implement a new law raising the gestational limit for abortion from 10 to 12 weeks. A study by the Jérôme Lejeune Foundation of the situation in Lyon found "intense reluctance" among doctors to carry out the later term abortions. "French Doctors Rethinking Abortions in Face of New Law: At One Hospital, Physicians Quit en Masse." Zenit, 7 November, 2001. (Accessed 2006-06-13).

Abortion is legal in Viet Nam. It is reported that "psychological trauma" experienced by physicians "could emerge as an important issue with the rapidly increasing number of people seeking to have abortions. " Dr. Nguyen Thi Hong Minh, director of the Central Obstetrics and Gynecology Hospital in Hanoi, described her adverse reaction to having to perform abortions at 20-22 weeks gestation. There was no indication in the report that physicians were compelled to provide abortions "Doctors under pressure as abortion demand goes up." Than Nien News, 15 March, 2010 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

Opposition to late term abortion can even lead to threats of legal action by concerned physicians. "Doctors Revolt over Last-Minute Abortion of Twin." British Nursing News On Line, 10 November, 2002. (Accessed 2006-06-13).

16.  The reluctance of Scots physicians to provide abortions after 15 weeks gestation has resulted in women travelling to England for the procedure. "Ian Jones, chief executive of the BPAS . . . admitted that it could be difficult to find doctors and nurses, particularly in the west of Scotland, who were prepared to work at the clinic. He said the fact that so many women needed to travel to England for late abortions reflected the fact that medical staff in Scotland do not want to perform them." Templeton, Sarah Kate, "Private firm plans Scottish abortion clinic." The Sunday Herald, 19 January, 2003. (Accessed 2006-06-13).

On the other hand, abortions can be obtained in some locations very late into pregnancy. Foster, Kate, "Hospital Admits Abortion At 34 Weeks." Scotland on Sunday, 10 April 2005 (Accessed 2006-06-13).

By 2002 there had been a 578 percent increase in the numbers of abortions performed at 20 to 21 weeks gestation in Canada. "Discovery of birth defects leads to abortions: study." CBC News. 28 March, 2002 (Accessed 2006-06-13). The news report, drawing on Statistics Canada figures, noted that 96.7% of abortions in 2001 were performed before the 16th week. Since there were 105,154 abortions in 2001, about 3,480 abortions were performed after the 16th week: about nine per day. The Daily, 11 February, 2005 (Accessed 2006-06-13).

Two to three abortions performed up to and beyond 24 weeks gestation were reported to be occurring each week in an Alberta hospital, many resulting in live births of infants. Ko, Marnie, "Down the Slope to Infanticide: Nurses At Foothills Hospital Rebel Over The Horrifying Results Of Late-Term 'Genetic Terminations.'" Alberta Report Newsmagazine May 3, 1999.

And, for the same reason, a district health board in New Zealand has decided to subsidize travel to Australia for women who want second trimester abortions. "Royal College calls for conscience decision on second trimester abortions." Radio New Zealand,11 March, 2006 (Accessed 2006-03-11).

17.  A shortage of willing Canadian physicians caused women from Ontario and Quebec to go to the United States for late term abortions. Quebec Health Minister Philippe:"'In Quebec, our doctors at the present time don't feel comfortable doing abortions later than 22 weeks. From 20 to 22 weeks they're all done in Sherbrooke, after that we still don't have the capacity to do them here.'" "Quebec hopes to offer late-term abortions." CBC News, 10 September, 2004 (Accessed 2006-06-13). A 2006 report from Canadians for Choice referred to the arrangement. Shaw, Jessica, "Reality Check: a close look at accessing abortion services in Canadian hospitals." Canadians for Choice, 2006, p. 34. (Accessed 2010-05-19). According to the Canadians for Choice directory, only one abortion facility in Quebec performs abortions beyond 16 weeks gestation, and none beyond 21 weeks. (Accessed 2010-05-19)

18.  Peritz, Ingrid Peritz, and Séguin, Rhéal, "Quebec MNA's challenge Harper's abortion stance." Globe and Mail, 19 May, 2010 (Accessed 2010-05-19).

19.  Dr. Ward's survey of Western Cape physicians found that half would not do abortions for non-lethal congenital abnormalities. More important was his finding that 46% would refuse to perform abortions for socio-economic reasons; less than a third were willing to do so. Ward, Harvey, Are State Doctors in the Western Cape willing to implement the Choice of Termination of Pregnancy Act of 1996? An opinion survey conducted in the Western Cape in November 1997. In fulfillment for the requirements of the FCOG (S.A.) part 2.

95% to 99% of nurses surveyed in the California study I have mentioned would refuse involvement in sex selective abortion; the rate of objection to selective reduction in multifetal pregnancies ranged from 71% to 92%. Marek, Marla J., "Nurses' Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting." JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004. The range in both cases reflects responses that differed according to gestational age.

20.  For example: a study in the United Kingdom found that nurses developed increasingly negative attitudes to abortion the longer they worked in units where it was provided. Marshall, S.L., Gould, D. & Roberts, J. (1994) "Nurses' attitudes towards termination of pregnancy." Journal of Advanced Nursing, 20, 567-576. Cited in Marek, Marla J., "Nurses' Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting." JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004

Abortion had been legal in Britain for over a generation when a third of junior doctors were reported to be conscientious objectors to the procedure. Barratt, Helen "Abortion and Conscientious Objection." Triple Helix, Winter, 2001.

The Spanish pro-life group Provida reported that, a year after abortion was legalized in Spain, only 2 out of 100 gynaecologists in a Madrid hospital were willing to perform them. By 2004, abortions had been performed by only one doctor at the largest hospital in Valencia. "96% of gynecologists in Spain refuse to perform abortions." Catholic News Agency, 25 March, 2004 (Accessed 2006-06-13)

A survey by RN magazine disclosed that the number of nurses who refused to work in a unit where abortions were performed had increased over ten years from 48% to 61%. Ventura, M.J. (1999) "Where nurses stand on abortion." RN, 62(3), 44-48. Cited in Marek, Marla J., "Nurses' Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting." JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004.

Recent Californian research found rates of conscientious objection among nurses ranging from 23% to 99%, depending upon the reasons for the procedures. Moreover, two hospitals declined to participate in the survey because of fear that it would "stir up negative feelings" among staff: this, thirty years after the legalization of abortion in the United States. Marek, Marla J., "Nurses' Attitudes Toward Pregnancy Termination in the Labor and Delivery Setting." JOGNN, 33, 472-479; 2004.

On the other hand, other researchers have noted that experience has led to the development of more positive attitudes toward the procedure. See Meta Hammarstedt, Lars Jacobsson, Marianne Wulff and Ann Lalos, Views of midwives and gynecologists on legal abortion - a population-based study. Acta Obstetricia et Gynecologica Scandinavica, Volume 84 Page 58 - January 2005 doi:10.1111/j.0001-6349.2005.00695.x Volume 84 Issue 1: "The more experience of working with legal abortion, especially current experience, the less restrictive gynecologists and midwives are in their views. Compared with previous studies, staffs have become more liberal in their attitudes toward abortion and the relevant legislation."

21.  A classic example is provided by developments in Spain. The Spanish pro-life group Provida reported that, a year after abortion was legalized in Spain, only 2 out of 100 gynaecologists in a Madrid hospital were willing to perform them. By 2004, abortions had been performed by only one doctor at the largest hospital in Valencia. "96% of gynecologists in Spain refuse to perform abortions." Catholic News Agency, 25 March, 2004 (Accessed 2006-06-13)

Five years later the Spanish Minister of Justice, Francisco Caamano said that "there is no room for conscientious objection to abortion" in the country. Collegial Medical Organization President Dr. Juan Jose Rodriguez Sendin has rejected the Minister's assertion, stating that doctors will exercise their freedom to refuse to perform abortions whether the government likes it or not. The Minister's statement also brought a rebuke from the Association for the Defense of Conscientious Objection. "Spain's Justice Minister says doctors not allowed to object to abortion." Catholic News Agency, 14 August, 2009. (Accessed 2010-05-20)

Responding to the Minister of Justice, Dr. Esteban Rodriguez of Right to Life (Derecho a Vivir) in Spain said that objecting physicians would go to jail rather than perform abortions. He criticized the "totalitarian intentions" of the government. "Gynecologists in Spain plan to choose jail before performing an abortion." Catholic News Agency, 20 August, 2009. (Accessed 2010-05-20)

22.  Sometimes this collision is unintended. In England, for example, the Royal College of Nursing general secretary has suggested an expanded role for nurses in abortion. She stated that the organization wants to increase access to abortion in the early stages of pregnancy "and allow nurses greater involvement in providing services." While the general secretary affirmed the right of nurses to refuse to participate, she does not appear to have recognized that expecting more nurses to participate in abortion will increase the probability of pressure on conscientious objectors. "RCN Says No Need for Change in Abortion Law." RCN News Release, 30 June, 2005 (Accessed 2006-06-12.)

23.  "In our society, we all pay taxes for this medical system to receive services," said Dr. Preston Zuliani, the President of the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario. "And if a citizen or taxpayer goes to access those services and they are blocked from receiving legitimate services by a physician, we don't feel that's acceptable." Laidlaw, Stuart, "College of physicians debates doctors' rights to refuse treatments." Toronto Star, 18 September, 2008 (Accessed 2008-09-21)

24Globe and Mail, 18 January 1974. Quoted in de Valk, supra, p. 137

25.  In 1992, BC Health Minister Elizabeth Cull ordered 33 British Columbian hospitals to perform abortions. Hawkins, Anthony, "BC stamps out choice: Orders hospitals to do abortions; taxpayers to fund them" The Interim, 20 April, 1992. (Accessed 2010-05-18)

Between 1977 and 1984, nurse Linda Bradley was denied employment at four British Columbian hospitals because she did not want to assist with abortions. Desperate, she sacrificed her convictions to get a job at the Richmond General Hospital. She lost it after refusing to assist at the hysterotomy of a mother, five and a half months pregnant. Murphy, Sean, Nurse Refused Employment, Forced to Resign: A Two Tiered System of Civil Rights.

Over thirty years after the promises were made, postpartum nurses at Foothills Hospital in Calgary were told that they would have to be involved with late term abortions, regardless of their moral convictions. Ko, Marnie, "Personal Qualms Don't Count: Foothills Hospital Now Forces Nurses To Participate In Genetic Terminations." Alberta Report, April 12, 1999.

BC welfare worker Cecilia Moore was fired for refusing to authorize payment for an abortion that would have been illegal under the law as it then stood. Murphy, Sean,"Insubordination."

Three transition house workers in Ontario were fired - with the government's approval - for refusing to refer women for abortions. Kennedy, Frank, "Sweeney Defends Firings:Transition house workers fired, denied benefits for 'misconduct'". The Interim, March, 1989

A 1975 biography of Dr. Henry Morgentaler described how he and his staff performed an abortion on a shouting, squealing 16 year old severely retarded girl who could not understand what was happening. Pelrine, Eleanor Wright, Morgentaler: The Doctor Who Couldn't Turn Away. Gage Publishing, 1975, p. 55. Over twenty years later, as if demonstrating that Dr. Morgentaler was just a little ahead of his time, a Quebec Court ordered the abortion and sterilization of a mentally ill woman who was not capable of requesting or consenting to the procedures. Murphy, Sean, Conscience or Contempt of Court? Court orders abortion of woman.

26.  The progression is neatly illustrated by the name changes of a prominent American abortion advocacy group: from the "National Association for the Repeal of Abortion Laws" (1969) to the "National Abortion Rights Action League" (1973) to the "National Abortion and Reproductive Rights Action League" (1993). Key Moments in NARAL Pro-Choice America's History (Accessed 2006-06-22).

27.  Recall the Globe and Mail's plea that abortion be legalized "to enable doctors to perform their duties according to their conscience and their calling." Editorial, "Free the Doctor." Globe and Mail, 18 May, 1965. Quoted in de Valk, Alphonse, Morality and Law in Canadian Politics: The Abortion Controversy. Dorval, Quebec: Palm Publishers, 1974, p. 18.

28.  One of the most important 'movers and shakers' in this field is the Center for Reproductive Rights. CRR documents obtained by the Catholic Family and Human Rights Institute (CFAM) were entered in the United States Congressional Record (p. E2535 to E2547) on 8 December, 2003, to forestall efforts by the Center to suppress dissemination of the documents through litigation. They are available on the Protection of Conscience Project website [CRR documents].

The documents cited herein are:

International Legal Program Summary of Strategic Planning: Through October 31, 2003 (E2535)

ILPS Memo # 1- International Reproductive Rights Norms: Current Assessment (E2535-E2538);

ILPS Memo #2- Establishing International Reproductive Rights Norms: Theory of Change (E2538-E2539).

Domestic Legal Progam Summary of Strategic Planning Through October 31, 2004 (E2539)

DLPS Memo #1- Future of Traditional Abortion Litigation (E2539-2540);

DLPS Memo #2- Report to Strategic Planning Participants From Systematic Approach Subgroup (E2540-E2541).

DLPS Memo #3- Report to Strategic Planning Participants From "Other Litigation" Subgroup (E2541-E2542).

Program Strategies and Accomplishments (E2543)

The Center for Reproductive Rights: Summary and Synthesis of Interviews (E2543-2546)

The Center for Reproductive Rights Board of Directors - Primary Affiliation Information (E2547)

29.  "Legally binding or ''hard'' norms are norms codified in binding treaties such as the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) or the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW)." ILPS Memo # 1, E2535

30.  The Center acknowledges that there is no binding international legal instrument that recognizes a right to abortion. ILPS Memo # 1, E2536

31.  "The ILP's overarching goal is to ensure that governments worldwide guarantee reproductive rights out of an understanding that they are legally bound to do so." International Legal Program Summary of Strategic Planning: Through October 31, 2003 (E2535)

"Our goal is to see governments worldwide guarantee women's reproductive rights out of recognition that they are bound to do so." ILPS Memo #1, E2537; ILPS Memo # 2, E2538.

"The Center needs to continue its advocacy to ensure that women's ability to choose to terminate a pregnancy is recognized as a human right." ILPS Memo # 2, E2539

"Advocates use of enforcement mechanisms can help cultivate a "culture" of enforcement . . ." ILPS Memo #2, E2539

Pursuing the notion that abortion is part of "the fundamental rights strand of equal protection" is one of the suggestions in the report of the "Other Litigation" Subgroup, DLPS Memo #3, E2540. To establish abortion as a "fundamental" right would give it precedence over less "fundamental" rights in cases of conflict.

32.  The norms offer "a firm basis for the government's duties, including its own compliance and its enforcement against third parties." ILPS Memo #2, E2538

33.  "Supplementing . . .binding treaty-based standards and often contributing to the development of future hard norms are a variety of 'soft norms.' These norms result from interpretations of human rights treaty committees, rulings of international tribunals, resolutions of inter-governmental political bodies, agreed conclusions in international conferences and reports of special rapporteurs. (Sources of soft norms include: the European Court of Human Rights, the CEDAW Committee, provisions from the Platform for Action of the Beijing Fourth World Conference on Women, and reports from the Special Rapporteur on the Right to Health.)." ILPS Memo # 1, E2535

34.  "These lower profile victories will gradually put us in a strong position to assert a broad consensus around our assertions." ISLP Memo #1, E2538

35.  Dickens, Bernard M. "Informed Consent": Chapter 5 in Downie, Joceyln, Caulfield, Timothy and Flood, Colleen (Eds.) Canadian Health Law and Policy (2nd Ed.). Toronto: Butterworths, 2002, p. 149. The claim is examined and rejected in Murphy, Sean, Conscientious objection as a 'crime against humanity.'

36.  Amnesty International claims that a Nicaraguan law against abortion violates the Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment. The charge is completely at odds with the definition of "torture" used in the Convention, but consistent with attempts to characterize conscientious objection to abortion as a crime against humanity. Amnesty International, The Impact of the Complete Abortion Ban in Nicaragua: Briefing to the United Nations Committee Against Torture. London, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-21); Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment. (Accessed 2010-05-21); Murphy, Sean, Conscientious Objection as a Crime Against Humanity

37.  According to the Canadians for Choice directory, only one abortion facility in Quebec performs abortions beyond 16 weeks gestation, and none beyond 21 weeks (Accessed 2010-05-19).

38.  "It was quite a surprise, back in 1973, to be informed by an eminent professor of obstetrics and gynaecology . . .that as a Roman Catholic specialist, that "there is no place for to practice within the National Health Service unless you are prepared to change your views or to re-specialise in another field." . . .as a consequence became unemployed with a wife and three children and had to leave country, home and family in order to practise my chosen specialty in full freedom." Walley, R. L., Question of Conscience. THE FUTURE OF OBSTETRICS AND GYNAECOLOGY: The Fundamental Right To Practice and be Trained According to Conscience: An International Meeting of Catholic Obstetricians and Gynaecologists.

39.  Waldis, Niklaus, Personal Experience in Switzerland in 1989. THE FUTURE OF OBSTETRICS AND GYNAECOLOGY: The Fundamental Right To Practice and be Trained According to Conscience: An International Meeting of Catholic Obstetricians and Gynaecologist.

40.  Catholic hospitals in the Australian state of Victoria may close as a result of a new law that makes referral for abortion mandatory. "State of Victoria, Australia demands referral, performance of abortions." Protection of Conscience Project

41.  The opposition to abortion that is a feature of indigenous African culture is in conflict with documents like the Maputo Plan of Action and the Maputo Protocol, all of which are intended to establish abortion (and other things) as legal rights.  Contrast Turyomumazima, Bonaventure, "No Place for Abortion in African Traditional Life - Some Reflections," with Maputo Plan of Action for the Operationalisation of the Continental Policy Framework for Sexual and Reproductive Health Rights, 2007-2010. African Union, Special Session of the African Union Conference of Ministers of Health, Maputo, Mozambique 18-22 September, 2006 (Accessed 2008-11-28) and Protocol to the African Charter on Human and Peoples' Rights on the Rights of Women in Africa. African Union, 2nd Ordinary Session of the Assembly of the Union, Maputo, 11 July, 2003 (Accessed 2008-11-28.)

42.  In 2007 the Committee for the Elimination of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW) asked Polish representatives "[h]ow many doctors had been suspended or fired because they refused to perform abortions?" The question appeared to reflect an expectation that such practices should be the norm. "Progress made in mainstreaming gender equality into Poland's national legislation, women's anti-discrimination committee told." UN General Assembly WOM1591, Dept. Of Public Information, 16 January, 2007 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

43.  In Portugal, abortion up to ten weeks gestation was legalized in 2007. As a result of widespread conscientious objection, the Portuguese Health Minister ordered the Portuguese Medical Association to remove the prohibition of abortion from its code of ethics. He insisted that it was unacceptable for codes of ethics to "go against the general law of the country." The Association eventually deleted direct reference to abortion in the code. The new language affirms that life is the highest value and cannot be interrupted after it begins, but the Association has adopted a neutral position as to when life begins. "Portugal moves to legalize abortion." Catholic Culture, Catholic World News Feature Stories, 12 March, 2007. (Accessed 2008-11-28.)

Hoffman, Matthew Cullinan, "Portuguese Government Orders Doctors to Remove Anti-Abortion Restrictions from Code of Ethics: Portuguese Bar Association denounces decision as 'arrogant and overbearing.'" LifeSiteNews.com, 22 October, 2007 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

Almeida, Henrique, "Portugal doctors stand by anti-abortion principles." Reuters, 15 November, 2007 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

Hoffman, Matthew Cullinan, "Portuguese Government to Prosecute Doctors Group Over 'Illegal' Anti-Abortion Ethics Policy." LifeSiteNews.com, 22 November, 2007 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

Hoffman, Matthew Cullinan, "Portuguese Physicians Capitulate to Pressure to Change Ethical Code to Allow Abortions." LifeSiteNews.com, 11 July, 2008 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

44.  The Spanish pro-life group Provida reported that, a year after abortion was legalized in Spain, only 2 out of 100 gynaecologists in a Madrid hospital were willing to perform them. By 2004, abortions had been performed by only one doctor at the largest hospital in Valencia. "96% of gynecologists in Spain refuse to perform abortions." Catholic News Agency, 25 March, 2004 (Accessed 2006-06-13)

Five years later the Spanish Minister of Justice, Francisco Caamano said that "there is no room for conscientious objection to abortion" in the country. Collegial Medical Organization President Dr. Juan Jose Rodriguez Sendin has rejected the Minister's assertion, stating that doctors will exercise their freedom to refuse to perform abortions whether the government likes it or not. The Minister's statement also brought a rebuke from the Association for the Defense of Conscientious Objection. "Spain's Justice Minister says doctors not allowed to object to abortion." Catholic News Agency, 14 August, 2009. (Accessed 2010-05-20)

Responding to the Minister of Justice, Dr. Esteban Rodriguez of Right to Life (Derecho a Vivir) in Spain said that objecting physicians would go to jail rather than perform abortions. He criticized the "totalitarian intentions" of the government. "Gynecologists in Spain plan to choose jail before performing an abortion." Catholic News Agency, 20 August, 2009. (Accessed 2010-05-20)

45.  Nurses at a convention in Bangalore reported that they were being forced to pariticpate in abortions, and that some who refused had been forced to resign."Catholic nurses under pressure to assist abortions." Spero News, 18 May, 2006 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

46.  A young nurse in Pakistan who refused to perform an abortion on two women was gang raped by three men from their families. The Punjab Health Association stated that this was not the first such incident. Wilkinson, Isambard, "Nurse raped for refusal to carry out abortions." The Telegraph, 27 February, 2006 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

47.  In 2008, the Saint Ignatius University Hospital (Hospital Universitario San Ignacio) in Colombia refused to provide a eugenic abortion. The Colombian government announced that it would fine the hospital the equivalent of about $5,100.00 for refusing to provide the procedure. Hoffman, Matthew Cullinan, "Colobmbian Government Fines Catholic Hospital for Refusing to Perform Abortion." LifeSite News, 12 May, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-20).

48.  Cantor, Julie D., When an Adult Female Seeks Ritual Genital Alteration: Ethics, Law and the Parameters of Participation. Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery, 117(4), 1 April, 2006, 1158-1164

49.  Dyer, Clare, "Surgeon amputated healthy legs." BMJ 2000;320:332 ( 5 February, 2000). (Accessed 2006-07-13); Fisher, Keren, and Smith, Robert, "More work is needed to explain why patients ask for amputation of healthy limbs." BMJ 2000;320:1147 ( 22 April, 2000) (Accessed 2006-07-13); Leonard, Sue, "Woman asks Falkirk hospital to cut off healthy legs." The Sunday Times, April 03, 2005 (Accessed 2006-07-13).

50"M.P.s reject need for father in IVF." BBC News, 20 May, 2008. (Accessed 2010-05-21)

51.  A lesbian sued two Christian doctors in California. Golde, Polo Black, "California Court Comes Out: The Bioethics of Benitez." Bioethics Forum, 22 August, 2008. (Accessed 2008-11-28). The case was settled out of court. Riley, Jennifer, "Lesbians, Christian Fertility Doctors Settle Out of Court." The Christian Post, 2 October, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

52.  Chapman, James, "Couples win the right to use IVF to create 'spare part babies'." Daily Mail, 9 November, 2007 (Accessed 2010-06-17).

53.  Ahuja KK, Mamiso J, Emmerson G, Bowen-Simpkins P, Seaton A, Simons EG.  Pregnancy following intracytoplasmic sperm injection treatment with dead husband's spermatozoa: ethical and policy considerations. Hum Reprod. 1997 Jun;12(6):1360-3.

BMJ 1997;314:143 (11 January) Letters: Widow's attempt to use her dead husband's sperm  (Accessed 2006-07-01)

"Widow wins access to dead husband's sperm."ABC News Online  (Accessed 2006-07-01)

54.  Mundy, Liza, "A World of Their Own: In the eyes of his parents, if Gauvin Hughes McCullough turns out to be deaf, that will be just perfect." Washington Post, 31 March, 2002 (Accessed 2006-07-01)

55.  A report from an "Assisted Suicide Consensus Panel" convened by the University of Pennsylvania included the following statement: "The willingness of other professionals-including nurses, social workers, and clergy-to participate and even take the lead in assisting suicides is critical to meet society's interest that assisted suicide should be humane, effective, and confined to appropriate cases." Faber-Langendoen, Kathy, and Karlawish, Jason H.T. for the University of Pennsylvania Center for Bioethics Assisted Suicide Consensus Panel, "Should Assisted Suicide Be Only Physician Assisted?" Annals of Internal Medicine, Vol. 132 No. 36, 21 March, 2000 (Accessed 2010-06-17).

56.  Montana judge ruled that the state constitution not only provided a "right" to assisted suicide, but that this legal right "necessarily incorporates the assistance of his doctor, as part of a doctor-patient relationship, so that the patient can obtain a prescription for drugs that he can take to end his own life, if and when he so determines." Montana First Judicial District Court, Lewis and Clark County, Cause No. ADV-2007-787, Robert Baxter et al v. State of Montana, Decision and Order, 5 December, 2008 (Accessed 2009-07-15).

57.  In November, 2008, an Italian appeals court agreed that food and fluids could be withdrawn from a woman who had been living in a vegetative state since a car accident in 1992. The ruling was the result of litigation by her father. Squires, Nick, "Italy agrees to first withdrawal of life support in the country." The Telegraph, 13 November, 2008 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

Subsequently, the nuns caring for her refused to do so. White, Hilary, "Italian Nuns Refuse to Kill Eluana Englaro." LifeSite News, 17 November, 2008 (Accessed 2010-05-21) She died in February, 2009 a few days after food and fluids were stopped and doctors began to remove life support, in the midst of a national controversy. Owen, Richard, "'Right to Die' Coma woman Eluana Englaro dies." The Times, 10 February, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

58.  In northern India a judge gave a deadline to employees of the Medical Health Department to bring ten people in to be sterilized. Catholic teachers were ordered to promote sterilization among their pupils and their families. "Church in India Condemns Judge's Sterilization Order." Zenit, 23 February, 2006 (Accessed 2008-11-28).

59.  Oullette, Alicia, "Eyes Wide Open: Surgery to Westernize the Eyes of an Asian Child." Hastings Center Report, 2009- January/February (Accessed 2010-05-21).

60.  Noble, Tom, "Embryos screened for deafness - a quiet first for Australia." 11 July, 2003 (Accessed 2006-07-01).

Helen McCrave, a woman in the United Kingdom was told that her IVF treatment would be delayed for an indeterminate period because she does not have blonde hair and blue eyes. The conditions for treatment include a requirement that she donate some of her eggs to the IVF facility, but the demand was for eggs from blonde, blue-eyed donors. McNeil, Rob, "IVF help 'only if you are a blonde'." Evening Standard (London), 15 July, 2004 (Accessed 2006-07-01).

61.  Murphy, Sean, Belgium: Mandatory Referral for Euthanasia. December, 2003.

62.  Several articles in a 2006 number of the Journal of Medical Ethics discuss the use of patients in persistent vegetative states as experimental subjects. Some authors asserted that they would be especially useful in studies of the long-term effects of animal organ transplants. R Sparrow, Right of the living dead? Consent to experimental surgery in the event of cortical death. J. Med. Ethics, Oct 2006; 32: 601 - 605.

S Curry, Living patients in a permanent vegetative state as legitimate research subjects. J. Med. Ethics, Oct 2006; 32: 606 - 607.

H Draper, Research and patients in a permanent vegetative state. J. Med. Ethics, Oct 2006; 32: 607.

J Thompson, Relatives of the living dead. J. Med. Ethics, Oct 2006; 32: 607 - 608.

N Levy, A Ravelingien, J Braeckman, F Mortier, E Mortier, and I Kerremans, Respecting rights ... to death. J. Med. Ethics, Oct 2006; 32: 608 - 611.

63.  American surgeons have carried out sham operations, which involved drilling holes in patients' skulls, as placebo surgery designed to test the effectiveness of a new treatment for Parkinson's disease. "Doctors Drill into Patients' Heads in Placebo Surgery" (Accessed 29 Sept., 1999).

64.  St. Vincent Hospital, Santa Fe, New Mexico and Nurses District 1199, New Mexico, Memorandum of Understanding for Circumcision Procedure, 31 January, 1995.

65.  University of Manchester Professor John Harris, a member of the British Medical Association's ethics committee, justifies infanticide as a logical extension of late term abortion. ''There is no obvious reason why one should think differently, from an ethical point of view, about a fetus when it's outside the womb rather than when it's inside the womb.'' UK medical ethicist: Infanticide 'justifiable' - Government adviser suggests acceptable to kill babies with 'defects' soon after birth. World Net Daily, 25 January, 2004 (Accessed 21 September, 2005).

66.  Oldham, Jeanette, "'I want to be father and mother'." The Scotsman, 10 December, 2001 (Accessed 2006-07-01).

67.  In 1997 and 1998, Dr. Robert Smith, a surgeon at the Falkirk and District Royal Infirmary in Scotland, performed single leg amputations on two men. There was nothing wrong with their legs. Both men suffered from a disorder called apotemnophilia, or Body Integrity Identy Disorder (BIID). Dr. Smith was concerned that if he did not perform the amputations the patients might resort to back street amateurs, or attempt amputations themselves, thereby putting their health and lives at risk. "I have very serious concerns that they will either go to unlicensed practitioners and there are practitioners advising on the Internet to provide this service. They may take the law into their own hands, they may lie under a railway line, on a railway line and be run over by a train. They use shotguns and shoot their limbs off and they are really quite a desperate bunch." Complete Obsession. BBC2, 9:30pm, 17 February, 2000 (Accessed 2006-07-13).

Similarly, one of the patients whose leg was removed said that some people seeking amputations "simulate accidents" and "others turn to back-street operators." "'No regrets' for healthy limb amputee." BBC News, 6 February, 2000, 15:43 GMT. BBC News,  (Accessed 2006-07-15)

68.  Cantor, Julie D., When an Adult Female Seeks Ritual Genital Alteration: Ethics, Law and the Parameters of Participation. Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery, 117(4), 1 April, 2006, 1158-1164

69.  "If the patient were to have no assistance from his doctor, he may be forced to kill himself sooner rather than later because of the anticipated increased disability with the progress of his disease, and the manner of the patient's death would more likely occur in a manner that violates his dignity and peace of mind, such as by gunshot or by an otherwise unpleasant method, causing undue suffering to the patient and his family." Montana First Judicial District Court, Lewis and Clark County, Cause No. ADV-2007-787, Robert Baxter et al v. State of Montana, Decision and Order, 5 December, 2008. (Accessed 2009-07-15).

70.  The legalization of assisted suicide in Washington state is generating attacks on health care workers unwilling to be involved with the procedure. The first patient to ask for a lethal prescription could not find a physician willing to provide it before he died. His granddaughter complained that Spokane area hospitals "do not provide support or direction of any kind" for assisted suicide. She is urging citizens to contact legislators to demand "access to all our rights according to the law." The implication is that institutions and/or health care workers should be forced to participate in assisted suicide. Bean, Leah, "Death with Dignity a Law, but unavailable." The Spokesman Review, 26 April, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-22)

71.  The Center For Reproductive Rights (CRR) supported a legal challenge to the Costa Rican ban on in vitro fertilization launched by ten infertile Costa Rican couples. CFAM Friday Fax, December 30, 2004, Volume 8, Number 2 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

According to statistics from the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), between 1992 and 2002 the total number of IVF births to British women of all ages trebled. "Dozens of babies being born to mothers over 50." The Telegraph, 8 May, 2006 (Accessed 2006-07-01).

"Murderer wins right to be a father." BBC News, 5 December, 2007. (Accessed 2010-05-22)

Canadian courts have ruled that public funding is not required for in vitro fertilization. Cameron v. Attorney General of Nova Scotia [1999] NSJ No. 297 (September 14, 1999), leave to appeal to the Supreme Court of Canada denied. Moulton, Donna Lee, "Supreme Court refuses to hear MD's fertility case." Canadian Medical Association Journal, 3 October, 2000 163(7) (Accessed 2010-05-24). 

However, political pressure for public funding continues. See Nisker, Jeff, "Distributive Justice and Infertility Treatment in Canada." J Obstet Gynaecol Can 2008;30(5):425-431 (Accessed 2010-05-21).  

Citing Nisker, a guest editorial in the SOJC's Journal argues for public funding on the grounds that patients suffering from infertility deserve publicly funded access to IVF because "[t]hey've already paid their taxes." Hughes, Edward, "Access to Effective Infertility Care in Canada." J Obstet Gynaecol Can 2008;30(5):389-390. (Accessed 2010-05-22).

Society of Obsetrticians and Gynaecologists of Canada, SOGC calls on all provinces and territories for full funding of IVF treatments. News Release, 22 March, 2010. (Accessed 2010-05-24)

72.  Canning, Cheryl, "Doctor's faith under scrutiny:Barrie physician won't offer the pill, could lose his licence." The Barrie Examiner, 21 February, 2002.

73.  St. Elizabeth's Hospital in Humboldt, Saskatchewan stopped contraceptive tubal ligations because they were contrary to Catholic teaching. Two physicians then resigned in protest. A woman complained to the provincial Human Rights Commission that denial of tubal ligation was discrimination based on gender and religion. The Saskatchewan Catholic Health Corporation had to pay almost $8,000.00 to settle the complaint. Ultimately, the hospital's Catholic affiliation was ended and control of the hospital was transferred to a regional health authority. Deibert, Dave, "Sask. doctors resign over tubal ligation policy." Victoria Times Colonist, 21 December, 2006. (Accessed 2008-11-28). "Woman given settlement after being denied tubal ligation." CBC News, 13 September, 2007 (Accessed 2008-11-28). French, Janet, "Region to control Humboldt hospital." The StarPhoenix, 20 September, 2007. (Accessed 2008-11-28).

74L. v. Lithuania, (Application No. 27527/03) 11 September, 2007, European Court of Human Rights (Accessed 2010-05-22).

75.  In 2007, the ruling party announced that it would force every hospital in the country to provide euthanasia or to refer patients to facilities that would do so. The party was willing to tolerate conscientious objection by physicians on condition that they refer them for euthanasia provided by more willing colleagues. "Hospitals must provide euthanasia." Expatica, 18 April, 2007 (Accessed 28 November, 2008).

76.  Professor Ian Wilmut, who cloned Dolly, the sheep, argues that cloning human embryos to treat illnesses is a good idea, but adds that it would be immoral not to do so. "Cloning 'could beat gene disease'." BBC News, 5 June, 2006. (Accessed 2006-07-01)

77.  "Eventually," said Professor Greg Stock of the University of California, "it will be thought as reckless to have a child without genetic screening as to have a child without pre-natal screening, as happens today." Daily Express, 25 October, 2000 (Accessed October, 2000).

78.  In addition to arguing that physicians and nurses should encourage terminally ill patients to consider suicide, Baroness Mary Warnock has stated that "it is a genuinely wicked thing" for them to disregard explicit requests for assisted suicide. The remarks were made during a debate at All Soul's Unitarian Church in Belfast, Northern Ireland. Belfast Newsletter, 6 January, 2009 (Accessed 2010-05-21).

79.  Fernandez-Lynch, Holly, Conflicts of Conscience in Health Care: An Institutional Compromise. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2008, p. xii-xiii (hereinafter "Conflicts.")

80.  Some physicians, she says, assert that it would be wrong for them to do X, but not wrong for someone else. Sincerely motivated by nothing more than a personal "idiosyncratic understanding of morality," they make no broader moral claims (p. 23). It appears that they attract the author's sympathetic notice because they do not challenge the hegemony of moral pluralism.

But Fernandez Lynch seems troubled by physicians who are adhere to what they consider to be "God's absolute standards" that apply to everyone. She observes that they not only refuse to provide a service they believe is wrong, but say that no one else should provide it either (p. 24). She seems to agree that this reflects an agenda that is really "all about the control of others."(p. 23)

Here the author has fallen into absurdity. Anyone who believes that something is truly wrong - murder, for example - will also believe that no one should do it. The author herself takes exactly this position with respect to discrimination ( ". . . preferences based on racist, sexist, homophobic, or other sorts of bigoted views can be appropriately excluded from legitimate discourse as entirely illogical and not even arguably correct." p.92; ". . . invidious discrimination is clearly an evil . . ." p. 155; ". . . preferences based on racist, sexist, homophobic, or other sorts of bigoted views can be appropriately excluded from legitimate discourse as entirely illogical and not even arguably correct." p. 92)

Elsewhere, in a passage that could have been written by an objecting physician, she asserts, as a matter of "fact," that "there is never an obligation to participate in genuine wrongdoing."

It is certainly the case that no professional obligation could rightfully include a duty to engage in true moral transgressions, regardless of voluntary entry into a profession or the existence of a professional monopoly. ( p. 201. Similarly, she agrees that a physician would be justified in refusing to assist a patient to do something "truly wrong." p. 84).

However, she immediately denies that physicians should be allowed to act on these principles. That would, she claims, "permit the physician's conscience to become a law unto itself" and impose views on patients "with which they may reasonably disagree."(p. 201)

It would seem to follow from the author's reasoning that a physician must not be forced to provide a service he believes to be immoral, but must not be allowed to assess the morality of the service he is asked to provide. He is free to act on his conscience - except in questions of morality. This kind of incoherent conclusion is the result of the corrosive effect of the author's espousal of moral pluralism, which precludes any personal identification of genuine wrongdoing or true moral transgression. What begins as a high-sounding statement of moral principle at once dissolves into meaningless cant.

This incoherence also undermines her principal argument for maintaining moral diversity in the profession. As noted above, she posits that the debate engendered by such diversity will allow us to "siphon out the most accurate version of moral truth."(p. 85) But we cannot recognize "the most accurate version of moral truth" unless (a) moral truth exists, and (b) we least have an accurate idea of what it looks like. If moral truth does not exist, or if we cannot recognize it, no amount of debate within the profession will tell us whether or not we have "the most accurate version" of it.

The most plausible explanation for this lapse is anti-religious prejudice, if not against religion generally, then against religions that profess the kind of moral certitude that the author demonstrates when she denounces racial discrimination. Her position seems to be that moral absolutism is acceptable as long as it does not depend on religious belief.

81.  John Paul II, Encyc. Evangelium Vitae (25 March, 1995) 74. (Accessed 2009-09-16) Fernandez Lynch describes this as "a powerful statement about the nature of conscience, complicity in morally objectionable actions, and avoidance of injustice," generally acceptable to religious and nonreligious people alike, regardless of their political views. Conflicts., p. 1.

82Conflicts, p. 33, 241, 257

83.  Murphy, Sean, Service or Servitude: Reflections on Freedom of Conscience for Health Care Workers.

84Conflicts, p. 256

85Conflicts, p. 146, 165-193

86.  To accomplish this, the author suggests that a designated institution ensure access to services through effective distribution of health care resources and connect patients with willing physicians. Conflicts, p. 14, 74-75, 97, 112, 146, 165-193

87Conflicts, p. 24, 99, 256

88Conflicts, p. 56, 80, 245

89Conflicts, p. 129, 172

90Conflicts, p. 167, 227. Note that she rejects the demand that all physicians should be made to achieve technical competence in the procedure. This requirement, too, would seriously undermine the compromise she proposes. Conflicts, p. 205

91Conflicts , p. 75. She later cites a survey that found "four out of five women supported policies allowing individual pharmacists to refuse to dispense contraceptives when the pharmacy bore the obligation of assigning another employee to fill the prescription." The results were reversed when the obligation was removed. Conflicts, p. 104

92Conflicts, p. 99

93Conflicts, p. 84

94.  However, the author perceptively notes that the pursuit of moral pluralism has generated conflict, which many have tried to avoid by forcing people "to restrict their beliefs to their personal lives." Conflicts, p. 22

95Conflicts, p. 135

96Conflicts, p. 85. That is because, she says, the moral questions involved often cannot be answered by "empirical testing or any other comprehensive doctrine for distinguishing right from wrong." (Conflicts, p. 84.) "No one can empirically prove that abortion kills a person with full moral status," she writes, "or that contraception is an offense against God." (Conflicts, p. 148) Similarly - though she does not say it - no one can, in her terms, prove that abortion does not kill a person with full moral status, or prove that contraception is not an offense against God.

97Conflicts, p. 85.

98.  Identifying Julian Savulescu and Rosamund Rhodes in particular. Conflicts, p. 58, 62

99Conflicts, p. 101

100.  Conflicts, p. 80

101Conflicts, p. 206-207, 214

102Conflicts, p. 87-88, 90-93

103Conflicts, p. 10

104Conflicts, p. 22-23

105Conflicts, p. 80-81. "Society benefits from having morally serious people in the profession who are unwilling to just follow orders and who contribute to the rich moral debate that helps avoid blindly accepting the normative permissibility of whatever is technically possible and has not been legally prohibited." Conflicts, p. 86

106.  Consider, as the author does, the Tuskegee study: almost 400 black men in Alabama, deceived and denied treatment for syphilis so that physicians could study the disease. Final Report of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study Legacy Committee (May 20, 1996). University of Virginia, Claude Moore Health Sciences Library (Accessed 2009-09-17).

She also refers to human experimentation on concentration camp inmates during the Holocaust (Lifton, Robert Jay, The Nazi Doctors: Medical Killing and the Psychology of Genocide. New York: Basic Books, 2000) and the participation of physicians in abusive interrogations and torture Conflicts, p. 82, citing Matthews, Richard G., "Indecent Medicine: In Defense of the Absolute Prohibition against Physician Participation in Torture," Am. J. Bioethics 6, no.3 (2006):W34

Or consider Canadian physicians, who, executing orders from the Alberta Eugenics Board, sterilized over 4,500 Albertans purported to be "mentally defective." Some of these people were also used as guinea pigs in drug tests and as sources of tissue for research. Marsh, James H., "Eugenics: Keeping Canada Sane." The Canadian Encyclopaedia (Accessed 2009-09-17). Muir v. The Queen in right of Alberta, 132 D.L.R. (4th) 695. Court File No. 8903 20759, Edmonton, Alberta. Court of Queen's Bench, Veit J. January 25, 1996

107Conflicts, p. 82. Instead, the author adopts the reasoning of attorney Howard Lesnick: "A polity that encourages its citizens to bring to bear their own serious moral reflections on the morally significant decisions they face will be more likely to grow in justice and humanity."

Lesnick argues that the "varying religious scruples" of individual professionals act as "a counsel of restraint" in the prevailing pluralist ethos, and that this has a broader social value. Lesnick, Howard, "The Religious Lawyer in a Pluralist Society," Fordham Law Review 66 (1998), 1469, 1489-1490. Lesnick, Howard, "The Religious Lawyer in a Pluralist Society," Fordham Law Review 66 (1998), 1469, 1489-1490. Quoted in Conflicts, p. 81. Fernandez Lynch identifies a social benefit provided by objecting physicians as their "counsel of restraint" in the face of demands spawned by technological developments. Conflicts, p. 81.

108Conflicts, p. xii

109.  All she offers is speculation that conscience is "a slippery concept," something in the way of an "ethical tug", a "motivator," some fuzzy feeling, or an "interior voice." Conflicts, p. 35, citing [n61, p 270] Eisgruber, Christopher L., Sager, Lawrence G. "The Vulnerability of Conscience: The Constitutional Basis for Protecting Religious Conduct." U. Chi. L. Rev. 61 (1994): 1245, 1291; "[T]he interior, quintessentially human voice that speaks to us of goodness and duty, the voice we must obey if we are to keep our integrity." Conflicts, p. 35, quoting Hasson, Kevin Seamus, The Right to be Wrong: Ending the Culture War over Religion in America. San Francisco, CA: Encounter Books, 2005. p. 14.

110Conflicts, p. xii

111.  The author states that her solution "preserves the moral integrity of physicians in most circumstances."(Conflicts, p. 10) But how can we be sure of this, if we don't know what freedom of conscience is or how it relates to moral integrity? For example, having frequently referred to the importance of personal or moral integrity, the author nonetheless asserts that, in what she calls 'hard cases', the personal integrity of a physician "can be outweighed by the need for professional integrity." (Conflicts, p. 196-197) And what could "moral integrity" possibly mean within the context of moral pluralism?

112Conflicts, p. 24, 99

113Conflicts, p. 224

114.  "Contract, social: The imaginary device through which equally imaginary individuals, living in solitude (or, perhaps, nuclear families) , without government, without a stable division of labour or dependable exchange relations, without parties, leagues, congregations, assemblies or associations of any sort, come together to form a society, accepting obligations of some minimal kind to one another, and immediately or very soon thereafter binding themselves to a political sovereign who can enforce those obligations." Honderich, Ted (Ed.) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2nd Ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. p. 174

115Conflicts, p. 6, 10, 13, 43, 47, 49, 52, 54, 57, 58, 70-75, 86, 88-89, 111, 120, 123, 124, 132, 136,156, 197, 199, 207, 250

116Conflicts, p. 13, 38-39, 43

117Conflicts, p. 121-127

118Conflicts, p. 127-129

119Conflicts, p. 130-132

120Conflicts, p. 133, 226-229

121Conflicts, p. 133

122.  It is the province of science to determine when a human individual begins to be - that is, to exist. The existence of a human being is a purely biological matter. However, science cannot determine what moral obligations are called forth by the existence of a human being, nor can it determine that the individual is a human person. That is a philosophical question, and science is not competent to decide philosophical questions. Its correct and limited role is to provide factual data that philosophers and ethicists incorporate into their deliberations. Irving, Dianne N., "When do Human Beings Begin? 'Scientific' Myths and Scientific Facts." International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy 1999, 19:3/4:22-47

123.  Fernandez Lynch encountered this assertion more than once while researching the book, but does not appear to have recognized its significance. She cited a paper by the Project Administrator as an example of an unworkably broad understanding of "needs," apparently because the paper did not specifically define "needs." The point of the paper, however, (and the reason for the absence of the kind of definition she was seeking) is precisely the point here: that such a definition presumes some kind of underlying definition of the human person. Conflicts, p. 130-131; Murphy, Sean, Freedom of Conscience and the Needs of the Patient. Presented at the Obstetrics and Gynaecology Conference New Developments - New Boundaries in Banff, Alberta (November 9-12, 2001).

Exactly same point was made in a second paper [Murphy, Sean, Service or Servitude: Reflections on Freedom of Conscience for Health Care Workers. ] cited and quoted twice by the author (Conflicts, p. 8, 256).

124Conflicts, p. 14-15. This probably explains why Fernandez Lynch later applies a statement from Pope John Paul II in support of the polemical assertion that "physicians cannot be permitted to hold physicians hostage to their personal moral beliefs. (Conflicts, p. 99; p. 284, n.1; also referred to without citation at Conflicts, p. 14-15) "John Paul II observed that 'freedom of conscience does not confer a right to indiscriminate recourse to conscientious objection. When an asserted freedom turns into license or becomes an excuse for limiting the rights of others, the state is obliged to protect, also by legal means, the inalienable rights of its citizens against such abuses.'" The fragment of text chosen by the author is misleading because she has taken it is seriously out of context. Her claim that the Pope "was referring to the dangers of political fundamentalism in denying human rights" is a manifestly inadequate gloss of complex document about freedom of conscience. No on actually familiar with the writings and thought of John Paul II would have attempted such a spurious association. For the source (incorrectly cited by Fernandez Lynch) see John Paul II, If You Want Peace, Respect the Conscience of Every Person. Message for the XXIV World Day of Peace, 1 January, 1991 (Accessed 2010-05-26).

125.  Fernandez Lynch apparently sees the origin of the current controversy as a conflict between physician and patient autonomy, describing the patient autonomy movement as a "challenge to the autonomy of physicians." (Conflicts, p. 22) This is at least in part because some prominent commentators have explained it in those terms. Proponents of what she calls the "patient-centric" approach, she says, leave little or no room for physician autonomy (Conflicts, p. 61). In contrast, she quotes Edmund Pellegrino's assertion that an attack on physician autonomy is an assault on "an essential part of the person's humanity. . .". (Conflicts, p. 67, quoting Pellegrino, Edmund D., "Patient and Physician Autonomy: Conflicting Rights and Obligations in the Physician Patient Relationship," J. Contemp. Health Law & Policy 10 (1993) 47, 58-59.) She focuses on finding ways to "protect the autonomy of both parties" and "preserve the autonomy of all interested individuals" (Conflicts, p. 87, 99). When she argues for that objecting physicians should violate their convictions in hard cases, she appeals to the principle of autonomy: their autonomous decision to enter the profession, and the lesser autonomy of patients (Conflicts, p. 196-198). Similarly, she justifies limitations on freedom of conscience by describing them as "essential to the protection of patient autonomy, safety or serious medical interests."(Conflicts, p. 229) It is significant that the author repeatedly emphasizes the need to preserve autonomy rather than integrity, and places autonomy - not integrity - on par with safety and "serious medical interests." The author's views reflect the dominant position that autonomy has achieved in contemporary thought.

126.  When working out the ethical problem of conscientious objection in hard cases, the author conducts the discussion entirely within the framework of autonomy and choice, concluding that freedom of conscience should be subordinated when it is necessary to preserve freedom of choice for the patient. (Conflicts, p. 196-199) Elsewhere she asserts that patient choice must not be compromised by physician views about what services are appropriate or optimal.(Conflicts, p. 203)

127.  In the author's case, consider her prejudice against religious beliefs that purport to be based on absolute standards of right and wrong. (Conflicts, p. 23-24)

128.  The author refers to the importance of "moral autonomy" Conflicts, p. xiii-xiv, 7, 196) and agrees with John Rawls that moral pluralism is beneficial because it permits individuals "to pursue their own conceptions of the good." (Conflicts, p. 22) The tendency of the law to identify religious belief as an expression of personal autonomy is discussed in Berger, Benjamin, L., Law's Religion: Rendering Culture. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, Vol. 45, No. 2. (http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=961031) Accessed 2009-09-22. This is also discussed in Brown, Mr. Justice David, The Courts' Spectacles: Some Reflections on the Relationship between Law and Religion in Charter Analysis - Reasonable Accommodation and Role of the State: A Democratic Challenge. CIAJ Conference, 24 September, 2008, Quebec City.

129.  The author describes monopoly control of power as characteristic of professionalism (Conflicts, p. 10, 69-70, 79, 86, 132, 214), and identifies power and admiration as forms of compensation formerly paid to physicians as part of a purported social contract (Conflicts, p. 46). Physician power is offered as one of the explanations for the comparatively recent development of controversy about freedom of conscience in health care (Conflicts, p. 19), and resistance of physicians to the patient autonomy movement is explained as an attempt by the profession "to reclaim some of its lost power." (Conflicts, p. 22) The author validates professional ethics to the extent that they have "developed as part of the negotiation of power with the public." (Conflicts, p. 136)

130.  Hence the centrality of social contract theory in the author's approach.

131.  The author asserts that failure to obtain the consent of the victims is "a major reason" for the historical and professional condemnations of the conduct of Nazi physicians during the Holocaust and of American researchers involved in the Tuskegee experiment, though this is not stated clearly as her own view. (Conflicts, p. 82) She questions the idea that consent is always sufficient to justify a procedure, but the discussion is inconclusive. (Conflicts, 83). However, when she later justifies the suppression of what she calls the "moral autonomy" of an objecting physician in a hard case, she does so precisely because of the physician's alleged implied consent to subordinate his "personal integrity" to "professional integrity" upon entering the profession. Alternatively, she alleges that he has a duty to consent in such circumstances. (Conflicts, p. 196-197) This seems inconsistent with her earlier rejection of the "consent paradigm" of medical professionalism (Conflicts, p. 48-57) That conclusion, however, was based on her belief that physicians could not be shown to have consented to meet all patient demands, not on rejection of the notion of justification by consent.

132.  Canada's Chief Justice based a right to assisted suicide (distinguished from murder only by consent) on the fundamental importance of individual autonomy and self-determination" and "the promotion of individual autonomy." Re: Rodriguez and Attorney-General of British Columbia et al; British Columbia Coalition of People with Disabilities, et al, Intervener, 107 DLR (4th) 342, Supreme Court of Canada

133Conflicts, p. 223

134.  Thus, the author claims that if a large number of physicians were to refuse to provide services demanded by the public, they would act improperly by exercising legislative power without the consent of the governed. (Conflicts, p. 69) It would, she asserts, be "an illegitimate imposition of views" on those who disagree. (Conflicts, p. 86) Similarly, she describes conscientious objection in hard cases as a political act that usurps legitimate government authority. (Conflicts, p. 201)

135.  The author appears to accept the view that there is no moral equality (of persons) in the absence of a balance of power (Conflicts, p. 198, quoting Fenton and Lomasky). "T]he power imbalance inherent in the doctor-patient relationship," (Conflicts, p. 238) has become a dominant theme not only in the medical profession, but in other disciplines. Consider, for example, the themes of power and control reflected in the philosophy of the McMaster University School of Social Work: "As social workers, we operate in a society characterized by power imbalances that affect us all. These power imbalances are based on age, class, ethnicity, gender, geographic location, health, physical ability, race, sexual preference and income. We see personal troubles as inextricably linked to oppressive structures. We believe that social workers must be actively involved in the understanding and transformation of injustices in social institutions and in the struggles of people to maximize control over their own lives." (Accessed 2007-11-13)

136.  Arendt, Hannah, "Ideology and Terror: A Novel Form of Government." The citations and quotes attributed to her are from this chapter, which was added to the 1958 edition of her 1951 book, The Origins of Totalitarianism. (Accessed 2007-11-08)

137 The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Article 18. Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship and observance. (Accessed 2009-12-11).

138.  Maritain, Jacques, Man and the State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951, p. 77

139.  Maritain, Jacques, Man and the State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951, p. 77-78

140.  Maritain, Jacques, Man and the State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951, p. 110

141.  John Paul II, Encyclical Centesimus Annus (1991) 46. (Accessed 2007-11-15)

142.  Lewis, C.S., Screwtape Proposes a Toast and Other Pieces. London and Glasgow: Collins (Fontana Books) 1974, p. 18, 25

143.  Brown, Mr. Justice David, The Courts' Spectacles: Some Reflections on the Relationship between Law and Religion in Charter Analysis - Reasonable Accommodation and Role of the State: A Democratic Challenge. CIAJ Conference, 24 September, 2008, Quebec City.

144.  Maritain, Jacques (John J. Fitzgerald, trans.) The Person and the Common Good. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002, p. 36, 43, 45

145.  King, Martin Luther, Sermon: The Three Dimensions of a Complete Life. New Covenant Baptist Church, Chicago, Illinois, 9 April 1967. (Accessed 2005-08-02).

"[W]e must remember that it's possible to affirm the existence of God with your lips and deny his existence with your life. . . . We say with our mouths that we believe in him, but we live with our lives like he never existed . . . That's a dangerous type of atheism." King, Martin Luther, Sermon: Rediscovering Lost Values. 2nd Baptist Church, Detroit 28 February, 1954 (Accessed 2005-08-02).

146.  He emphasized that, for even the poorest and most downtrodden man, to be a human person "involves . . .totality and independence." Maritain, Jacques (John J. Fitzgerald, trans.) The Person and the Common Good. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002, p. 59; Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 3, 9

147.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 3-4

148.  Somerville, Margaret, Death Talk: The Case Against Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide. Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queens University Press, 2001, p. 191-192.

149.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 3.

150.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 18.

151.  Maritain, Jacques (John J. Fitzgerald, trans.) The Person and the Common Good. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002, p. 71; Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 14.

152.  Maritain, Jacques (John J. Fitzgerald, trans.) The Person and the Common Good. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002, p. 73; Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 15-17, 76.

153.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 11.

154.  Maritain, Jacques (John J. Fitzgerald, trans.) The Person and the Common Good. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2002, p. 58.

155.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 65.

156.  Maritain, Jacques (Doris C. Anson, trans.) The Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 45.

157.  Joad, C.E.M., Guide to the Philosophy of Morals and Politics. London: Gollancz Ltd., (1938), p. 803. Quoted in R. v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 at p. 178. () Accessed 2008-09-10.

158.  Joad, C.E.M., Guide to the Philosophy of Morals and Politics. London: Gollancz Ltd., (1938), p. 805. Cited in R. v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 at p. 178. (Accessed 2008-09-10). See Maritain, Jacques, Man and the State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951, p. 13.

159.  Lewis, C.S., "The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment." In Hooper, Walter (Ed.) C.S. Lewis: First and Second Things. Glasgow: William Collins & Sons, 1985, p. 101.

160.  King, Martin Luther, Letter from Birmingham Jail, 16 April, 1963. (Accessed 2005-08-02).

161.  Wojtyla, Karol, Love and Responsibility. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993, p. 27.

162.  Kant, Immanuel, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals. (Accessed 2008-09-10). Quoted in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Metaphysics" () Accessed 2008-09-10.

163.  R. v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) (Accessed 2008-09-10).

164.  R. v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) (Accessed 2008-09-10).

165 R. v. Morgentaler (1988)1 S.C.R 30 (Supreme Court of Canada) (Accessed 2008-09-10).

166.  Solzhenitsyn, Alexander, "As Breathing and Consciousness Return." In From Under the Rubble. Bantam Books (USA & Canada) 1976, p. 23.

Text