Conscientious objection as a 'crime against humanity'
The original version of this essay appeared as an appendix in a 2008
Project submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Alberta.1
The new 'rights' language
Readers of Canadian Health Law and
Policy are to be persuaded that a health care worker who declines, for
reasons of conscience, to direct a patient to the morning after pill or
abortion commits the offence of "forced pregnancy." . . . if . . . not actually a crime against humanity
analogous to torture, . . . at least a gross violation of human rights that
ought to be prosecuted by human rights commissions.
When the National Association for the Repeal of Abortion Laws opened its
doors in the United States in 1969, the claim that abortion was a 'right'
was directed only at the repeal of laws against the procedure, so that women
would be free to seek abortions and, as the Globe and Mail put it, so
that physicians would be able "to perform their duties according to their
conscience and their calling."2 At that time,
Canadians were repeatedly assured that "nobody would be forcing abortion
procedures on anyone else."3
Current rights claims must be distinguished from this early period.
Contrary to early activist promises, current rights claims are meant to
force health care workers and institutions to provide or at least facilitate
abortion, contraception, and artificial reproduction, all of which remain
morally controversial. A major 'mover and shaker' in this project is the
Center for Reproductive Rights (CRR),4 an
American advocacy group described in internal documents as an organization
"comprised largely of economically advantaged white women."5
The Center's agenda includes, among other things, the legal enforcement of
what it describes as inalienable sexual rights.6
The ultimate goal of the CRR is to establish what it calls "hard norms" -
treaty-based international laws7- that
recognize access to abortion as a fundamental human right.8 It
plans to develop a "culture of enforcement" that will compel governments to
respect this 'right'9 and enforce it against
third parties - physicians and other health care workers.10
Even as it works toward this end, it is cultivating "soft norms" in the form
of statements by international, regional, and intergovernmental bodies.11
Professor Bernard M. Dickens appears to follow this strategy in a
standard text, Canadian Health Law and Policy. In his chapter on
Informed Consent, addressing the topic of conscientious objection and
disclosure of relevant information to a patient, he notes that Canada has
ratified the 1998 Treaty of Rome constituting the International
Criminal Court. Within the context of a discussion of the refusal of
physicians or institutions to advise women about the availability of the
morning after pill "in order to oblige continuation of any pregnancy that
may occur," he continues:
Articles 7 and 8 of the treaty characterize forced
pregnancy following rape as a crime against humanity and as analogous to
torture. Human rights commissions may share this view, reinforcing their
concerns about non-disclosure constituting both discrimination against women
and inhuman and degrading treatment. Accordingly, the right to object to
perform or immediately participate in medical procedures on grounds of
conscience carries no parallel right to refuse to inform those eligible to
receive these procedures where or how they are practically accessible.12
The goal here is clear enough. Readers of Canadian Health Law and
Policy are to be persuaded that a health care worker who declines, for
reasons of conscience, to direct a patient to the morning after pill or
abortion commits the offence of "forced pregnancy." The passage is meant to
convince them that, if this is not actually a crime against humanity
analogous to torture, it is at least a gross violation of human rights that
ought to be prosecuted by human rights commissions.
Dickens here glosses over the distinction between "forced pregnancy
following rape" (the subject of the Treaty) and his broader claim
concerning a "medically indicated procedure" (the subject of his essay).
Moreover, while he asserts only a duty of disclosure, the logic of his
argument implies (as he argues elsewhere) that there is a similar duty to
refer or otherwise facilitate the procedure.13
The Treaty of Rome: "forced pregnancy" and "torture"
What first attracts critical attention is that Dickens refers to the
Treaty of Rome in his text, but actually cites a different document as
authority for his claim that "forced pregnancy following rape" is "a crime
against humanity. . . analogous to torture."14
Why cite a secondary source rather than the Treaty itself?
A review of the Treaty15 suggests one
possible answer. The Treaty does not support Dickens' claims.
Specifically:
• In order to constitute a crime against humanity or war crime, the
offence of "forced pregnancy" must be "committed as part of a widespread
or systematic attack directed against any civilian population, with
knowledge of the attack" [Art. 7(1)], or during war [Art. 8(2)b]
• Pregnancy is only "forced" within the meaning of the Treaty if a woman
is unlawfully confined after having been raped "with the intent of
affecting the ethnic composition of any population or carrying out other
grave violations of international law." [Art. 7(2)f; Art. 8(2)b(xxii)]
• The definition of "forced pregnancy" must not "in any way be
interpreted as affecting national laws relating to pregnancy," which
include laws restricting or prohibiting abortion [Art. 7(2)f]
• "Torture" is not, at any point in the Treaty, associated with
pregnancy, whether forced or not. It is specifically defined as "the
intentional infliction of severe pain or suffering, whether physical or
mental, upon a person in the custody or under the control of the
accused." [Art 7(2)e]
The Elements of Crimes: "forced pregnancy" and "torture"
The Elements of Crimes simply confirms the provisions of the
Treaty, both with respect to torture and "forced pregnancy." The document
adds nothing that even remotely suggests that conscientious objection to
medical procedures or services could be a crime against humanity, or that it
is analogous to torture. Again: why cite this document in preference to the
Treaty of Rome?
Perhaps the answer lies, not in what The Elements of Crimes
includes, but in what it leaves out. It leaves out reference to the
Treaty provision that recognizes the right of states to restrict or
prohibit abortion by law, which is not relevant to the purpose of the
document [Art. 7(2)f]. But the provision is highly relevant to Dickens'
claim that delaying access to abortion is a violation of human 'rights,'
since it flatly contradicts the notion that abortion is a human 'right.'
What else has been left out
Neither the Treaty of Rome nor The Elements of Crimes
associates "forced pregnancy," even as it is defined by the Treaty, with
torture. It is grouped with "rape, sexual slavery, enforced prostitution . .
. enforced sterilization, or any other form of sexual violence of comparable
gravity," but not with torture [Art. 7(1)g]. Nonetheless, Professor Dickens
somehow manages to conclude that the documents "characterize forced
pregnancy following rape . . .as analogous to torture."
The only possible explanation for this is that Professor Dickens
considers "forced pregnancy" analogous to torture because are both included
among the crimes against humanity listed in Article 7(1) of the Treaty. On
this basis, then, every crime in the list is analogous to all of the others,
so that "forced pregnancy" is analogous not only to torture, but to murder,
forcible transfers of population, enforced disappearance of persons and
apartheid, while murder is analogous to unlawful imprisonment, deportation,
etc. If this is how Professor Dickens arrived at his singular conclusion, it
is an open question whether his reasoning does a greater disservice to the
law or to the English language.
In any case, the Treaty itself has something to say about analogy:
The definition of a crime shall be strictly construed and shall not
be extended by analogy. In case of ambiguity, the definition shall be
interpreted in favour of the person being investigated, prosecuted or
convicted. [Art. 22(2)]
Thus, the kind of extension of meaning advocated by Professor Dickens is
expressly prohibited by the Treaty. This, too, Professor Dickens
leaves out of his essay.
Summary
Professor Dickens very selectively borrows terms from the Treaty of
Rome. He arranges his material to make it appear that conscientious
objection that delays access to the morning after pill or abortion is
actually or very nearly a crime against humanity analogous to torture, or,
at least, an egregious violation of human rights.
In addition to selective borrowing, Dickens leaves out everything
necessary for a proper understanding of the Treaty of Rome, which,
incidentally, includes everything that might cause a reader to question his
claims. Finally, he directs the reader not to the Treaty, which
includes a provision that is arguably fatal to his thesis, but to a document
that omits the provision.
Professor Dickens' polemic seamlessly weaves the agenda of the Center for
Reproductive Rights into a standard Canadian reference work. There is no
doubt that this is advantageous to the Center and its allies, but it brings
into question the reliability of Canadian Health Law and Policy.
Perhaps it is time for a third and more carefully revised edition of the
book.
Notes
1. Protection of Conscience Project,
Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Alberta Re: CPSA
Draft Standards of Practice (8 October, 2008)
2. "Free the Doctor", Globe and Mail, 18 May,
1965. Quoted in de Valk, Alphonse, Morality and Law in Canadian Politics:
The Abortion Controversy. Dorval, Quebec: Palm Publishers, 1974, p. 18].
Two years later the Globe argued that, in the case of abortion,
"where religious moralities conflict, the State should support none, but
leave the choice to individual conscience."["Now the job is to be done, let
it be done right", Globe and Mail, 21 December, 1967. Quoted in de
Valk, Alphonse,Morality and Law in Canadian Politics: The Abortion
Controversy. Dorval, Quebec: Palm Publishers, 1974, p. 56]
3. The assurance given by a Canadian M.P. to a
parliamentary committee studying her private member's bill to legalize
abortion. [Quoted in de Valk, Alphonse, Morality and Law in Canadian
Politics: The Abortion Controversy. Dorval, Quebec: Palm Publishers,
1974, p. 44-45]
Similar assurances came from the Canadian Welfare Council: "At the risk of
labouring the obvious, no woman will be required to undergo an abortion, no
hospital will be required to provide the facilities for abortion, no doctor
or nurse will be required to participate in abortion."[Standing Committee
on Health and Welfare, Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence, Appendix "SS":
Canadian Welfare Council Statement on Abortion to the House of Commons
Standing Committee on Health and Welfare. February, 1968, p. 707].
Nor was the Catholic Hospital Association concerned: "We note that there is
no question of [our hospitals] being obliged to change their present norms
of conduct. On the contrary, proponents of a 'liberalized' abortion law
admit that it should exempt those who object to being involved in procuring
abortions." [Standing Committee on Health and Welfare, Minutes of
Proceedings and Evidence, Appendix "QQ": Brief submitted by the Catholic
Hospital Association of Canada . . . on the Matter of Abortion. February,
1968, p. 8058-8059]. Canadian Justice Minister John Turner rejected a
protection of conscience amendment to the government bill legalizing
abortion because, he said, the proposed law imposed no duty on hospitals to
set up committees, imposed no duty on doctors to perform abortions, and did
not even impose a duty on doctors to initiate an application for an
abortion. [Hansard- Commons Debates, 28 April, 1969, p. 8069]
4.
CRR documents obtained by the Catholic Family and Human Rights Institute
(CFAM) were entered in the United States Congressional Record (p. E2535 to
E2547) on 8 December, 2003, to forestall efforts by the Center to suppress
dissemination of the documents through litigation. They are available on the
Project website.
The documents cited herein are:
- International Legal Program Summary of Strategic Planning: Through
October 31, 2003 (E2535)
- ILPS Memo # 1- International Reproductive Rights Norms: Current
Assessment (E2535-E2538);
- ILPS Memo #2- Establishing International Reproductive Rights
Norms: Theory of Change (E2538-E2539).
- Domestic Legal Progam Summary of Strategic Planning Through October
31, 2004 (E2539)
- DLPS Memo #1- Future of Traditional Abortion Litigation
(E2539-2540);
- DLPS Memo #2- Report to Strategic Planning Participants From
Systematic Approach Subgroup (E2540-E2541).
- DLPS Memo #3- Report to Strategic Planning Participants From
"Other Litigation" Subgroup (E2541-E2542).
- Program Strategies and Accomplishments (E2543)
- The Center for Reproductive Rights: Summary and Synthesis of
Interviews (E2543-2546)
- The Center for Reproductive Rights Board of Directors - Primary
Affiliation Information (E2547)
5. Which the "Other Litigation Subgroup" believed
undermined the credibility of the CRR with respect to the interests of
"women of colour." DLPS Memo #3, E2541) One of the Center's trustees also
expressed concern that much of the funding from individuals was coming from
donors over 60 years old ( The Center for Reproductive Rights: Summary and
Synthesis of Interviews, E2546)
6. ". . .both the ICPD Programme of Action and the
Beijing PFA reflect an international consensus recognizing the inalienable
nature of sexual rights." ILPS Memo # 1, 2537
7. "Legally binding or ''hard'' norms are norms codified
in binding treaties such as the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (ICCPR) or the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms
of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW)" ILPS Memo # 1, E2535
8. ". . . there is no binding hard norm that recognizes
women's right to terminate a pregnancy. To argue that such a right exists,
we have focused on interpretations of three categories of hard norms: the
rights to life and health; the right to be free from discrimination; those
rights that protect individual decision-making on private matters." ILPS
Memo #1, E2536
9. "The ILP's overarching goal is to ensure that
governments worldwide guarantee reproductive rights out of an understanding
that they are legally bound to do so." International Legal Program Summary
of Strategic Planning: Through October 31, 2003 (E2535)
"Our goal is to see governments worldwide guarantee women's reproductive
rights out of recognition that they are bound to do so." ILPS Memo #1,
E2537; ILPS Memo # 2, E2538.
"The Center needs to continue its advocacy to ensure that women's ability to
choose to terminate a pregnancy is recognized as a human right." ILPS Memo #
2, E2539
"Advocates use of enforcement mechanisms can help cultivate a "culture" of
enforcement . . ." ILPS Memo #2, E2539
Pursuing the notion that abortion is part of "the fundamental rights strand
of equal protection" is one of the suggestions in the report of the "Other
Litigation" Subgroup, DLPS Memo #3, E2540. To establish abortion as a
"fundamental" right would give it precedence over less "fundamental" rights
in cases of conflict.
10. The norms offer "a firm basis for the government's
duties, including its own compliance and its enforcement against third
parties." ILPS Memo #2, E2538
11. "Supplementing . . .binding treaty-based standards
and often contributing to the development of future hard norms are a variety
of 'soft norms.' These norms result from interpretations of human rights
treaty committees, rulings of international tribunals, resolutions of
inter-governmental political bodies, agreed conclusions in international
conferences and reports of special rapporteurs. (Sources of soft norms
include: the European Court of Human Rights, the CEDAW Committee, provisions
from the Platform for Action of the Beijing Fourth World Conference on
Women, and reports from the Special Rapporteur on the Right to Health.)."
ILPS Memo # 1, E2535
12. See Dickens, Bernard M. "Informed Consent": Chapter
5 in Downie, Joceyln, Caulfield, Timothy and Flood, Colleen (Eds.)
Canadian Health Law and Policy (2nd Ed.). Toronto: Butterworths, 2002,
p. 149.
13. Cook RJ, Dickens BM, Access to emergency
contraception. J. Obstet Gynaecol Can 2003;25 (11):914-6; Cook RJ, Dickens
BM, "In Response". J.Obstet Gyanecol Can, February, 2004; 26(2)112
14. Report of the Preparatory Commission for the
International Criminal Court, Addendum:
Finalized
draft text of the Elements of Crimes. New York: 2000. Accessed
2008-09-30
15.
Rome
Statute of the International Criminal Court, Accessed 2008-09-30