When do Human Beings Begin?
"Scientific" Myths and Scientific Facts
International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy 1999,
19:3/4:22-47
Copyright February 1999.
Reproduced with permission.
Dianne N. Irving, M.A., Ph.D.
*
Contents
Notes
. . . the use of terms such as "ovum" and
"egg"-which would include the term "fertilized egg"-is scientifically
incorrect, has no objective correlate in reality, and is therefore very
misleading-especially in these present discussions. Thus these terms
themselves would qualify as "scientific" myths. The commonly used term,
"fertilized egg," is especially very misleading, since there is really no
longer an egg (or oocyte) once fertilization has begun. What is being called
a "fertilized egg" is not an egg of any sort; it is a human being.
The question as to when a human being begins is strictly a scientific
question, and should be answered by human embryologists-not by philosophers,
bioethicists, theologians, politicians, x-ray technicians, movie stars, or
obstetricians and gynecologists. The question as to when a human person
begins is a philosophical question. Current discussions on abortion, human
embryo research (including cloning, stem cell research, and the formation of
mixed-species chimeras), and the use of abortifacients involve specific
claims as to when the life of every human being begins. If the "science"
used to ground these various discussions is incorrect, then any conclusions
will be rendered groundless and invalid. The purpose of this article is to
focus primarily on a sampling of the "scientific" myths, and on the
objective scientific facts that ought to ground these discussions. At least
it will clarify what the actual international consensus of human
embryologists is with regard to this relatively simple scientific question.
In the final section, I will also address some "scientific" myths that have
caused much confusion within the philosophical discussions on "personhood."
Getting a handle on just a few basic human embryological terms accurately
can considerably clarify the drastic difference between the "scientific"
myths that are currently circulating, and the actual objective scientific
facts. This would include such basic terms as: "gametogenesis," "oogenesis,"
"spermatogenesis," "fertilization," "zygote," "embryo," and "blastocyst."
Only brief scientific descriptions will be given here for these terms.
Further, more complicated, details can be obtained by investigating any
well-established human embryology textbook in the library, such as some of
those referenced below. Please note that the scientific facts presented here
are not simply a matter of my own opinion. They are direct quotes and
references from some of the most highly respected human embryology
textbooks, and represent a consensus of human embryologists internationally.
To begin with, scientifically something very radical occurs between the
processes of gametogenesis and fertilization-the change from a simple part
of one human being (i.e., a sperm) and a simple part of another human being
(i.e., an oocyte-usually referred to as an "ovum" or "egg"), which simply
possess "human life", to a new, genetically unique, newly existing,
individual, whole living human being (an embryonic single-cell human
zygote). That is, upon fertilization, parts of human beings have actually
been transformed into something very different from what they were before;
they have been changed into a single, whole human being.
During the process of fertilization, the sperm and the oocyte cease to
exist as such, and a new human being is produced. To understand this, it
should be remembered that each kind of living organism has a specific number
and quality of chromosomes that are characteristic for each member of a
species. (The number can vary only slightly if the organism is to survive.)
For example, the characteristic number of chromosomes for a member of the
human species is 46 (plus or minus, e.g., in human beings with Down's or
Turner's syndromes). Every somatic (or, body) cell in a human being has this
characteristic number of chromosomes. Even the early germ cells contain 46
chromosomes; it is only their mature forms - the sex gametes, or sperms and
oocytes - which will later contain only 23 chromosomes each.1
Sperms and oocytes are derived from primitive germ cells in the
developing fetus by means of the process known as "gametogenesis." Because
each germ cell normally has 46 chromosomes, the process of "fertilization"
can not take place until the total number of chromosomes in each are cut in
half. This is necessary so that after their fusion at fertilization the
characteristic number of chromosomes in a single individual member of the
human species (46) can be maintained-otherwise we would end up with a
monster of some sort.
To accurately see why a sperm or an oocyte are considered as only
possessing human life, and not as living human beings themselves, one needs
to look at the basic scientific facts involved in the processes of
gametogenesis and of fertilization. It may help to keep in mind that the
products of gametogenesis and fertilization are very different. The products
of gametogenesis are mature sex gametes with only 23 instead of 46
chromosomes. The product of fertilization is a living human being with 46
chromosomes. Gametogenesis refers to the maturation of germ cells, resulting
in gametes. Fertilization refers to the initiation of a new human being.
As the human embryologist Larsen2
states it, gametogenesis is the process that converts primordial germ cells
(primitive sex cells) into mature sex gametes-in the male (spermatozoa, or
sperms), and in the female (definitive oocytes). The timing of gametogenesis
is different in males and in females. The later stages of spermatogenesis in
males occur at puberty, and continue throughout adult life. The process
involves the production of spermatogonia from the primitive germ cells,
which in turn become primary spermatocytes, and finally spermatids-or mature
spermatozoa (sperms). These mature sperms will have only half of the number
of their original chromosomes-i.e., the number of chromosomes has been cut
from 46 to 23, and therefore they are ready to take part in
fertilization.3
Oogenesis begins in the female during fetal life. The total number of
primary oocytes-about 7 million-is produced in the female fetus' ovaries by
5 months of gestation in the mother's uterus. By birth, only about 700,000 -
2 million remain. By puberty, only about 400,000 remain. The process
includes several stages of maturation-the production of oogonia from
primitive germ cells, which in turn become primary oocytes, which become
definitive oocytes only at puberty. This definitive oocyte is what is
released each month during the female's menstrual period, but it still has
46 chromosomes. In fact, it does not reduce its number of chromosomes until
and unless it is fertilized by the sperm, during which process the
definitive oocyte becomes a secondary oocyte with only 23
chromosomes.
4
This halving of the number of chromosomes in the oocytes takes place by
the process known as meiosis. Many people confuse meiosis with a different
process known as mitosis, but there is an important difference. Mitosis
refers to the normal division of a somatic or of a germ cell in order to
increase the number of those cells during growth and development. The
resulting cells contain the same number of chromosomes as the previous
cells-in human beings, 46. Meiosis refers to the halving of the number of
chromosomes that are normally present in a germ cell - the precursor of a
sperm or a definitive oocyte - in order for fertilization to take place. The
resulting gamete cells have only half of the number of chromosomes as the
previous cells-in human beings, 23.
One of the best and most technically accurate explanations for this
critical process of gametogenesis is by Ronan O'Rahilly,5
the human embryologist who developed the classic Carnegie stages of human
embryological development. He also sits on the international board of Nomina
Embryologica (which determines the correct terminology to be used in human
embryology textbooks internationally):
"Gametogenesis is the production of [gametes], i.e.,
spermatozoa and oocytes. These cells are produced in the gonads, i.e., the
testes and ovaries respectively. ... During the differentiation of gametes,
diploid cells (those with a double set of chromosomes, as found in somatic
cells [46 chromosomes]) are termed primary, and haploid cells (those with a
single set of chromosomes [23 chromosomes]) are called secondary. The
reduction of chromosomal number ... from 46 (the diploid number or 2n) to 23
(the haploid number or n) is accomplished by a cellular division termed
meiosis. ... Spermatogenesis, the production of spermatozoa, continues from
immediately after puberty until old age. It takes place in the testis, which
is also an endocrine gland, the interstitial cells of which secrete
testosterone. Previous to puberty, spermatogonia in the simiferous tubules
of the testis remain relatively inactive. After puberty, under stimulation
from the interstitial cells, spermatogonia proliferate ... and some become
primary spermatocytes. When these undergo their first maturation division
(meiosis 1), they become secondary spermatocytes. The second maturation
division (meiosis 2) results in spermatids, which become converted into
spermatozoa."6
"Oogenesis is the production and maturation of
oocytes, i.e.; the female gametes derived from oogonia. Oogonia (derived
from primordial germ cells) multiply by mitosis and become primary oocytes.
The number of oogonia increases to nearly seven million by the middle of
prenatal life, after which it diminishes to about two million at birth. From
these, several thousand oocytes are derived, several hundred of which mature
and are liberated (ovulated) during a reproductive period of some thirty
years. Prophase of meiosis 1 begins during fetal life but ceases at the
diplotene state, which persists during childhood. ... After puberty, meiosis
1 is resumed and a secondary oocyte ... is formed, together with polar body
1, which can be regarded as an oocyte having a reduced share of cytoplasm.
The secondary oocyte is a female gamete in which the first meiotic division
is completed and the second has begun. From oogonium to secondary oocyte
takes from about 12 to 50 years to be completed. Meiosis 2 is terminated
after rupture of the follicle (ovulation) but only if a spermatozoon
penetrates. ... The term 'ovum' implies that polar body 2 has been given
off, which event is usually delayed until the oocyte has been penetrated by
a spermatozoon (i.e., has been fertilized). Hence a human ovum does not
[really] exist. Moreover the term has been used for such disparate
structures as an oocyte and a three-week embryo, and therefore should be
discarded, as a fortiori should 'egg'."7
(Emphasis added.)
Thus, for fertilization to be accomplished, a mature sperm and a mature
human oocyte are needed. Before fertilization,8
each has only 23 chromosomes. They each possess "human life," since they are
parts of a living human being; but they are not each whole living human
beings themselves. They each have only 23 chromosomes, not 46
chromosomes-the number of chromosomes necessary and characteristic for a
single individual member of the human species. Furthermore, a sperm can
produce only "sperm" proteins and enzymes; an oocyte can produce only
"oocyte" proteins and enzymes; neither alone is or can produce a human being
with 46 chromosomes.
Also, note O'Rahilly's statement that the use of terms such as "ovum" and
"egg"-which would include the term "fertilized egg"-is scientifically
incorrect, has no objective correlate in reality, and is therefore very
misleading-especially in these present discussions. Thus these terms
themselves would qualify as "scientific" myths. The commonly used term,
"fertilized egg," is especially very misleading, since there is really no
longer an egg (or oocyte) once fertilization has begun. What is being called
a "fertilized egg" is not an egg of any sort; it is a human being.
Now that we have looked at the formation of the mature haploid sex
gametes, the next important process to consider is fertilization. O'Rahilly
defines fertilization as:
"... the procession of events that begins when a
spermatozoon makes contact with a secondary oocyte or its investments, and
ends with the intermingling of maternal and paternal chromosomes at
metaphase of the first mitotic division of the zygote. The zygote is
characteristic of the last phase of fertilization and is identified by the
first cleavage spindle. It is a unicellular embryo."9
(Emphasis added.)
The fusion of the sperm (with 23 chromosomes) and the oocyte (with 23
chromosomes) at fertilization results in a live human being, a single-cell
human zygote, with 46 chromosomes-the number of chromosomes characteristic
of an individual member of the human species. Quoting Moore:
"Zygote: This cell results from the union of an oocyte
and a sperm. A zygote is the beginning of a new human being (i.e., an
embryo). The expression fertilized ovum refers to a secondary oocyte that is
impregnated by a sperm; when fertilization is complete, the oocyte becomes a
zygote."10
(Emphasis added.)
This new single-cell human being immediately produces specifically human
proteins and enzymes11
(not carrot or frog enzymes and proteins), and genetically directs his/her
own growth and development. (In fact, this genetic growth and development
has been proven not to be directed by the mother.)12
Finally, this new human being-the single-cell human zygote-is
biologically an individual, a living organism-an individual member of the
human species. Quoting Larsen:
"... [W]e begin our description of the developing
human with the formation and differentiation of the male and female sex
cells or gametes, which will unite at fertilization to initiate the
embryonic development of a new individual."13
(Emphasis added.)
In sum, a human sperm and a human oocyte are products of
gametogenesis-each has only 23 chromosomes. They each have only half of the
required number of chromosomes for a human being. They cannot singly develop
further into human beings. They produce only "gamete" proteins and enzymes.
They do not direct their own growth and development. And they are not
individuals, i.e., members of the human species. They are only parts-each
one a part of a human being.
On the other hand, a human being is the immediate product of
fertilization. As such he/she is a single-cell embryonic zygote, an organism
with 46 chromosomes, the number required of a member of the human species.
This human being immediately produces specifically human proteins and
enzymes, directs his/her own further growth and development as human, and is
a new, genetically unique, newly existing, live human individual.
After fertilization the single-cell human embryo doesn't become another
kind of thing. It simply divides and grows bigger and bigger, developing
through several stages as an embryo over an 8-week period. Several of these
developmental stages of the growing embryo are given special names, e.g., a
morula (about 4 days), a blastocyst (5-7 days), a bilaminar (two layer)
embryo (during the second week), and a trilaminar (3-layer) embryo (during
the third week).14
Given these basic facts of human embryology, it is easier to recognize
the many scientifically inaccurate claims that have been advanced in the
discussions about abortion, human embryo research, cloning, stem cell
research, the formation of chimeras, and the use of abortifacients -and why
these discussions obfuscate the objective scientific facts. The following is
just a sampling of these current "scientific" myths.
Myth 1: "Prolifers claim that the abortion of a human embryo or a
human fetus is wrong because it destroys human life. But human sperms and
human ova are human life, too. So prolifers would also have to agree that
the destruction of human sperms and human ova are no different from
abortions-and that is ridiculous!"
Fact 1: As pointed out above in the background section, there is a
radical difference, scientifically, between parts of a human being that only
possess "human life" and a human embryo or human fetus that is an actual
"human being." Abortion is the destruction of a human being. Destroying a
human sperm or a human oocyte would not constitute abortion, since neither
are human beings. The issue is not when does human life begin, but rather
when does the life of every human being begin. A human kidney or liver, a
human skin cell, a sperm or an oocyte all possess human life, but they are
not human beings-they are only parts of a human being. If a single sperm or
a single oocyte were implanted into a woman's uterus, they would not grow;
they would simply disintegrate.
Myth 2: "The product of fertilization is simply a 'blob,' a 'bunch
of cells', a 'piece of the mother's tissues'."
Fact 2: As demonstrated above, the human embryonic organism formed
at fertilization is a whole human being, and therefore it is not just a
"blob" or a "bunch of cells." This new human individual also has a mixture
of both the mother's and the father's chromosomes, and therefore it is not
just a "piece of the mother's tissues". Quoting Carlson:
"... [T]hrough the mingling of maternal and paternal
chromosomes, the zygote is a genetically unique product of chromosomal
reassortment, which is important for the viability of any
species."15(Emphasis
added.)
Myth 3: "The immediate product of fertilization is just a
'potential' or a 'possible' human being-not a real existing human being."
Fact 3: As demonstrated above, scientifically there is absolutely
no question whatsoever that the immediate product of fertilization is a
newly existing human being. A human zygote is a human being. It is not a
"potential" or a "possible" human being. It's an actual human being-with the
potential to grow bigger and develop its capacities.
Myth 4: "A single-cell human zygote, or embryo, or fetus are not
human beings, because they do not look like human beings."
Fact 4: As all human embryologists know, a single-cell human
zygote, or a more developed human embryo, or human fetus is a human
being-and that that's the way they are supposed to look at those particular
periods of development.
Myth 5: "The immediate product of fertilization is just an 'it'-it is
neither a girl nor a boy."
Fact 5: The immediate product of fertilization is genetically already
a girl or a boy-determined by the kind of sperm that fertilizes the oocyte.
Quoting Carlson again:
"...[T]he sex of the future embryo is determined by
the chromosomal complement of the spermatozoon. (If the sperm contains 22
autosomes and 2 X chromosomes, the embryo will be a genetic female, and if
it contains 22 autosomes and an X and a Y chromosome, the embryo will be a
genetic male.)"16
Myth 6: "The embryo and the embryonic period begin at
implantation." (Alternative myths claim 14 days, or 3 weeks.)
Fact 6: These are a few of the most common myths perpetuated
sometimes even within quasi-scientific articles-especially within the
bioethics literature. As demonstrated above, the human embryo, who is a
human being, begins at fertilization-not at implantation (about 5-7 days),
14-days, or 3 weeks. Thus the embryonic period also begins at fertilization,
and ends by the end of the eighth week, when the fetal period begins.
Quoting O'Rahilly:
"Prenatal life is conveniently divided into two
phases: the embryonic and the fetal. The embryonic period proper during
which the vast majority of the named structures of the body appear, occupies
the first 8 postovulatory weeks. ... [T]he fetal period extends from 8 weeks
to birth ..."17
(Emphasis added.)
Myth 7: "The product of fertilization, up to 14-days, is not an
embryo; it is just a 'pre-embryo'-and therefore it can be used in
experimental research, aborted, or donated."
Fact 7: This "scientific" myth is perhaps the most common error,
which pervades the current literature. The term "pre-embryo" has quite a
long and interesting history. (See Irving and Kischer, The Human
Development Hoax: Time To Tell The Truth!, for extensive details and
references.) But it roughly goes back to at least 1979 in the bioethics
writings of Jesuit theologian Richard McCormick in his work with the Ethics
Advisory Board to the United States Department of Health, Education and
Welfare,18
and those of frog developmental biologist Dr. Clifford Grobstein in a 1979
article in Scientific American,19
and most notably in his classic book, Science and the Unborn: Choosing
Human Futures (1988).20
Both McCormick and Grobstein subsequently continued propagating this
scientific myth as members of the Ethics Committee of the American Fertility
Society, and in numerous influential bioethics articles, leading to its
common use in bioethics, theological, and public policy literature to this
day.
The term "pre-embryo" was also used as the rationale for permitting human
embryo research in the British Warnock Committee Report
(1984),21
and then picked up by literally hundreds of writers internationally,
including, e.g., Australian writers Michael Lockwood, Michael Tooley, Alan
Trounson-and especially by Peter Singer (a philosopher), Pascal Kasimba (a
lawyer), Helga Kuhse (an ethicist), Stephen Buckle (a philosopher) and Karen
Dawson (a geneticist, not a human embryologist).
Note that none of these is even a scientist, with the exception of Karen
Dawson, who is just a geneticist.
Oddly, the influential book by Singer, Kuhse, Buckle, and Dawson,
Embryo Experimentation,22
(which uses the term "pre-embryo," and which contains no scientific
references for its "human embryology" chart or its list of "scientific"
terms), along with the work of theologian McCormick and frog developmental
biologist Grobstein, was used in the United States as the scientific basis
for the 1994 National Institutes of Heath (NIH) Human Embryo Research
Report.23 That
Report concluded that the "preimplantation embryo" (they, too, originally
used the term "pre-embryo") had only a "reduced moral status." (Both the
Warnock Report and the NIH Report admitted that the 14-day limit for human
embryo research was arbitrary, and could and must be changed if necessary.)
It is particularly in the writings of these and other bioethicists that
so much incorrect science is claimed in order to "scientifically" ground the
"pre-embryo" myth and therefore "scientifically" justify many of the issues
noted at the beginning of this article. This would include abortion, as well
as the use of donated or "made-for-research" early human embryos in
destructive experimental human embryo research (such as infertility
research, cloning, stem cell research, the formation of chimeras, etc.). To
begin with, it has been demonstrated above that the immediate product of
fertilization is a human being with 46 chromosomes, a human embryo, an
individual member of the human species, and that this is the beginning of
the embryonic period. However, McCormick and Grobstein24
claim that even though the product of fertilization is genetically human, it
is not a "developmental individual" yet-and in turn, this "scientific fact"
grounds their moral claim about this "pre-embryo." Quoting McCormick:
"I contend in this paper that the moral status-and
specifically the controversial issue of personhood-is related to the
attainment of developmental individuality (being the source of one
individual) ... It should be noted that at the zygote stage the genetic
individual is not yet developmentally single-a source of only one
individual. As we will see, that does not occur until a single body axis has
begun to form near the end of the second week post fertilization when
implantation is underway."25
(Emphasis added.)
Sounds very scientific. However, McCormick's embryology is already
self-contradictory. Implantation takes place at 5-7 days. The "single body
axis" to which he refers is the formation of the primitive streak, which
takes place at 14 days. McCormick often confuses these different periods in
his writings. But McCormick continues:
"This multicellular entity, called a blastocyst, has
an outer cellular wall, a central fluid-filled cavity and a small gathering
of cells at one end known as the inner cell mass. Developmental studies show
that the cells of the outer wall become the trophoblast (feeding layer) and
are precursors to the later placenta. Ultimately, all these cells are
discarded at birth."26Emphasis
added.)
The clear implication is that there is absolutely no relationship or
interaction between these two cell layers, and so the "entity" is not a
"developmental individual" yet. However, quoting Larsen:
"These centrally placed blastomeres are now called the
inner cell mass, while the blastomeres at the periphery constitute the outer
cell mass. Some exchange occurs between these groups. ... The cells of this
germ disc (the inner cell layer) develop into the embryo proper and also
contribute to some of the extraembryonic membranes."27(Emphasis
added.)
Similarly, it is not factually correct to state that all of the cells
from the outer trophoblast layer are discarded after birth. Quoting Moore:
"The chorion, the amnion, the yolk sac, and the
allantois constitute the fetal membranes. They develop from the zygote but
do not participate in the formation of the embryo or fetus-except for parts
of the yolk sac and allantois. Part of the yolk sac is incorporated into the
embryo as the primordium of the gut. The allantois forms a fibrous cord that
is known as the urachus in the fetus and the median umbilical ligament in
the adult. It extends from the apex of the urinary bladder to the
umbilicus."28
(Emphasis added.)
Since scientists, in trying to "reach" young students in a more familiar
language, sometimes use popularized (but scientifically inaccurate and
misleading) terms themselves, the ever-vigilant O'Rahilly expresses concern
in his classic text about the use of the term "fetal membranes":
"The developmental adnexa, commonly but inaccurately
referred to as the 'fetal membranes,' include the trophoblast, amnion,
chorion, umbilical vesicle (yolk sac), allantoic diverticulum, placenta and
umbilical cord. They are genetically a part of the individual and are
composed of the same germ layers."29(Emphasis
added.)
Consequently, it is also scientifically incorrect to claim that only the
inner cell layer constitutes the "embryo proper." The entire
blastocyst-including both the inner and the outer cell layers-is the human
embryo, the human being, the human individual.
Finally, McCormick claims that this "pre-embryo" has not yet decided how
many individuals it will become, since the cells are totipotent and twinning
can still take place. Therefore, they argue, there is no "individual"
present until 14-days and the formation of the primitive streak, after which
twinning cannot take place.30
However, twinning is possible after 14 days, e.g., with fetus-in-fetu and
Siamese twins. Quoting from O'Rahilly again:
"Partial duplication at an early stage and attempted
duplication from 2 weeks onward (when bilateral symmetry has become
manifest) would result in conjoined twins (e.g., 'Siamese
twins')."31
(Emphasis added.)
And even Karen Dawson acknowledges this as scientific fact in her article
in Embryo Experimentation:
"After the time of primitive streak formation, other
events are possible which indicate that the notion of 'irreversible
individuality' may need some review if it is to be considered as an
important criterion in human life coming to be the individual human being it
is ever thereafter to be. There are two conditions which raise questions
about the adequacy of this notion: conjoined twins, sometimes known as
Siamese twins, and fetus-in-fetu. ... Conjoined twins arise from the
twinning process occurring after the primitive streak has begun to form,
that is, beyond 14 days after fertilization, or, in terms of the argument
from segmentation, beyond the time at which irreversible individuality is
said to exist. ... This situation weakens the possibility of seeing
individuality as something irreversibly resolved by about 14 days after
fertilization. This in turn raises questions about the adequacy of using the
landmark of segmentation in development as the determinant of moral
status."32(Emphasis
added.)
It is unfortunate that the NIH Human Embryo Research
Panel
33 did not read this particular portion of the Singer et al. book
before making their recommendations about the moral status of the early
human embryo.
The scientific fact is that there is no such thing as a "pre-embryo" in
the real world. The term is a complete myth. It was fabricated out of thin
air in order to justify a number of things that ordinarily would not be
justifiable. Quoting O'Rahilly, who sits on the international board of
Nomina Embryologica, again:
"The ill-defined and inaccurate term 'pre-embryo,'
which includes the embryonic disk, is said either to end with the appearance
of the primitive streak or to include neurulation. The term is not used in
this book."34
(Emphasis added.)
Unfortunately, the convenient but mythological term "pre-embryo" will be
used to "scientifically" justify several of the other "scientific" myths to
follow, which in turn will be used to justify public policy on abortion and
human embryo research world-wide.
Myth 8: "Pregnancy begins with the implantation of the blastocyst
(i.e., about 5-7 days)."
Fact 8: This definition of "pregnancy" was initiated to
accommodate the introduction of the process of in vitro fertilization, where
fertilization takes place artificially outside the mother in a petri dish,
and then the embryo is artificially introduced into the woman's uterus so
that implantation of the embryo can take place. Obviously, if the embryo is
not within the woman's body, she is not "pregnant" in the literal,
traditional sense of the term. However, this artificial situation cannot
validly be substituted back to redefine "normal pregnancy," in which
fertilization does take place within the woman's body in her fallopian tube,
and subsequently the embryo itself moves along the tube to implant itself
into her uterus. In normal situations, pregnancy begins at fertilization,
not at implantation. Quoting Carlson:
"Human pregnancy begins with the fusion of an egg and
a sperm, but a great deal of preparation precedes this event. First both
male and female sex cells must pass through a long series of changes
(gametogenesis) that converts them genetically and phenotypically into
mature gametes, which are capable of participating in the process of
fertilization. Next, the gametes must be released from the gonads and make
their way to the upper part of the uterine tube, where fertilization
normally takes place. Finally, the fertilized egg, now properly called an
embryo, must make its way into the uterus, where it sinks into the uterine
lining (implantation) to be nourished by the mother."35
(Emphasis added.)
Myth 9: "The 'morning-after pill,' RU486, and the IUD are not
abortifacient; they are only methods of contraception."
Fact 9: The "morning-after pill," RU486, and the IUD can be
abortifacient, if fertilization has taken place. Then they would act to
prevent the implantation of an already existing human embryo-the
blastocyst-which is an existing human being. If the developing human
blastocyst is prevented from implanting into the uterus, then obviously the
embryo dies. In effect, these chemical and mechanical methods of
contraception have become methods of abortion as well. Quoting Moore:
"The administration of relatively large doses of
estrogens ('morning-after pill') for several days, beginning shortly after
unprotected sexual intercourse, usually does not prevent fertilization but
often prevents implantation of the blastocyst. Diethylstilbestrol, given
daily in high dosage for 5-6 days, may also accelerate passage of the
dividing zygote along the uterine tube ... Normally, the endometrium
progresses to the secretory phase of the menstrual cycle as the zygote
forms, undergoes cleavage, and enters the uterus. The large amount of
estrogen disturbs the normal balance between estrogen and progesterone that
is necessary for preparation of the endometrium for implantation of the
blastocyst. Postconception administration of hormones to prevent
implantation of the blastocyst is sometimes used in cases of sexual assault
or leakage of a condom, but this treatment is contraindicated for routine
contraceptive use. The 'abortion pill' RU486 also destroys the conceptus by
interrupting implantation because of interference with the hormonal
environment of the implanting embryo. ... An intrauterine device (IUD)
inserted into the uterus through the vagina and cervix usually interferes
with implantation by causing a local inflammatory reaction. Some IUDs
contain progesterone that is slowly released and interferes with the
development of the endometrium so that implantation does not usually
occur."36
(Emphasis added.)
And since the whole human blastocyst is the embryonic human being-not
just the inner cell layer-the use of chemical abortifacients that act "only"
on the outer trophoblast layer of the blastocyst, e.g.,
methotrexate,37
would be abortifacient as well.
Myth 10: "Human embryo research, human cloning, stem cell
research, and the formation of chimeras are acceptable kinds of research
because until implantation or 14 days there is only a 'pre-embryo', a
'potential' human embryo or human being present. A real human embryo and a
human being (child) do not actually begin unless and until the 'pre-embryo'
is implanted into the mother's uterus."
Fact 10: These claims are currently being made by bioethicists,
research scientists, pharmaceutical companies, and other biotech research
companies-even by some members of Congress. However, they too are
"scientific" myths.
Scientifically it is perfectly clear that there is no such thing as a
"pre-embryo," as demonstrated in Fact 7. As demonstrated in the background
material, the immediate product of fertilization is a human being, a human
embryo, a human child-the zygote. This zygote is a newly existing,
genetically unique, genetically male or female, individual human being-it is
not a "potential" or a "possible" human being. And this developing human
being is a human being, a human embryo, a human child whether or not it is
implanted artificially into the womb of the mother.
Fertilization and cloning are different processes, but the immediate
products of these processes are the same. The immediate product of human
cloning would also be a human being-just as in human fertilization. It is
not a "pre-embryo" or a "potential" human embryo or human being. Stem cell
research obtains its "stem cells" by essentially exploding or otherwise
destroying and killing a newly existing human blastocyst who is,
scientifically, an existing human being.
The formation of chimeras, i.e., the fertilization of a gamete of one
species (e.g., a human oocyte) with the gamete of another species (e.g., a
monkey sperm) also results in an embryo that is "half-human." All of these
types of research have been banned by most countries in the world. And all
of these types of research are essentially human embryo research-for which
the use of federal funds has been banned.
Myth 11: "Certain early stages of the developing human embryo and
fetus, e.g., during the formation of ancestral fish gills or tails,
demonstrates that it is not yet a human being, but is only in the process of
becoming one. It is simply 'recapitulating' the historical evolution of all
of the species."
Fact 11: This "scientific" myth is yet another version of the
"potential," "possible," "pre-embryo" myths. It is an attempt to deny the
early human embryo its real identity as a human being and its real
existence. But quoting once again from O'Rahilly:
"The theory that successive stages of individual
development (ontogeny) correspond with ('recapitulate') successive adult
ancestors in the line of evolutionary descent (phylogeny) became popular in
the 19th century as the so-called biogenetic law. This theory of
recapitulation, however, has had a 'regrettable influence in the progress of
embryology' (citing de Beer). ... Furthermore, during its development an
animal departs more and more from the form of other animals. Indeed, the
early stages in the development of an animal are not like the adult stages
of other forms, but resemble only the early stages of those
animals."
38
Hence, the developing human embryo or fetus is not a "fish" or a "frog,"
but is categorically a human being-as has been already demonstrated.
The question as to when a human person begins is a philosophical
question-not a scientific question. I will not go into great detail
here,39
but "personhood" begins when the human being begins-at fertilization. But
since many of the current popular "personhood" claims in bioethics are also
based on mythological science, it would be useful to just look very briefly
at these philosophical (or sometimes, theological) arguments simply for
scientific accuracy as well.
Philosophically, virtually any claim for so-called "delayed
personhood"-that is, "personhood" does not start until some point after
fertilization-involves the theoretical disaster of accepting that the idea
or concept of a mind/body split has any correlate or reflects the real
world. Historically this problem was simply the consequence of wrong-headed
thinking about reality, and was/is totally indefensible. It was abandoned
with great embarrassment after Plato's time (even by Plato himself in his
Parmenides!), but unfortunately resurfaces from time to time, e.g., as with
Descartes in his Meditations, and now again with contemporary
bioethics.
40 And as in the question of when a human being begins, if the
science used to ground these philosophical "personhood" arguments is
incorrect, the conclusions of these arguments (which are based on that
incorrect science) are also incorrect and invalid.
Myth 12: "Maybe a human being begins at fertilization, but a human
person does not begin until after 14-days, when twinning cannot take place."
Fact 12: The particular argument in Myth 12 is also made by
McCormick and Grobstein (and their numerous followers). It is based on their
biological claim that the "pre-embryo" is not a developmental individual,
and therefore not a person, until after 14 days when twinning can no longer
take place. However, it has already been scientifically demonstrated here
that there is no such thing as a "pre-embryo," and that in fact the embryo
begins as a "developmental individual" at fertilization. Furthermore,
twinning can take place after 14 days. Thus simply on the level of science,
the philosophical claim of "personhood" advanced by these bioethicists is
invalid and indefensible.
Myth 13: "A human person begins with 'brain birth,' the formation
of the primitive nerve net, or the formation of the cortex-all physiological
structures necessary to support thinking and feeling."
Fact 13: Such claims are all pure mental speculation, the product
of imposing philosophical (or theological) concepts on the scientific data,
and have no scientific evidence to back them up. As the well-known
neurological researcher D. Gareth Jones has succinctly put it, the
parallelism between "brain death" and "brain birth" is scientifically
invalid. "Brain death" is the gradual or rapid cessation of the functions of
a brain. "Brain birth" is the very gradual acquisition of the functions of a
developing neural system. This developing neural system is not a brain. He
questions, in fact, the entire assumption and asks what neurological reasons
there might be for concluding that an incapacity for consciousness becomes a
capacity for consciousness once this point is passed. Jones continues that
the alleged symmetry is not as strong as is sometimes assumed, and that it
has yet to be provided with a firm biological base.41
Myth 14: "A 'person' is defined in terms of the active exercising of
'rational attributes' (e.g., thinking, willing, choosing,
self-consciousness, relating to the world around one, etc.), and/or the
active exercising of 'sentience' (e.g., the feeling of pain and pleasure)."
Fact 14: Again, these are philosophical terms or concepts, which
have been illegitimately imposed on the scientific data. The scientific fact
is that the brain, which is supposed to be the physiological support for
both "rational attributes" and "sentience," is not actually completely
developed until young adulthood. Quoting Moore:
"Although it is customary to divide human development
into prenatal (before birth) and postnatal (after birth) periods, birth is
merely a dramatic event during development resulting in a change in
environment. Development does not stop at birth. Important changes, in
addition to growth, occur after birth (e.g., development of teeth and female
breasts). The brain triples in weight between birth and 16 years; most
developmental changes are completed by the age of 25."42
(Emphasis added.)
One should also consider simply the logical-and very real-consequences if
a "person" is defined only in terms of the actual exercising of "rational
attributes" or of "sentience." What would this mean for the following list
of adult human beings with diminished "rational attributes": e.g., the
mentally ill, the mentally retarded, the depressed elderly, Alzheimer's and
Parkinson's patients, drug addicts, alcoholics-and for those with diminished
"sentience," e.g., the comatose, patients in a "vegetative state,"
paraplegics, and other paralyzed and disabled patients, diabetics or other
patients with nerve or brain damage, etc.? Would they then be considered as
only human beings but not also as human persons? Would that mean that they
would not have the same ethical and legal rights and protections as those
adult human beings who are considered as persons? Is there really such a
"split" between a human being and a human person?
In fact, this is the position of bioethics writers such as the Australian
animal rights philosopher Peter Singer,43
the recently appointed Director of the Center for Human Values at Princeton
University. Singer argues that the higher primates, e.g., dogs, pigs, apes,
monkeys, are persons-but that some human beings, e.g., even normal human
infants, and disabled human adults, are not persons. Fellow bioethicist
Norman Fost actually considers "cognitively impaired" adult human beings as
"brain dead." Philosopher/bioethicist R.G. Frey has also published that many
of the adult human beings on the above list are not "persons," and suggests
that they be substituted for the higher primates who are "persons" in purely
destructive experimental research.44
The list goes on.
Ideas do have concrete consequences-not only in one's personal life, but
also in the formulation of public policies. And once a definition is
accepted in one public policy, the logical extensions of it can then be
applied, invalidly, in many other policies, even if they are not dealing
with the same exact issue-as happens frequently in bioethics.
Thus, the definitions of "human being" and of "person" that have been
concretized in the abortion debates have been transferred to several other
areas, e.g., human embryo research, cloning, stem cell research, the
formation of chimeras, the use of abortifacients-even to the issues of brain
death, brain birth, organ transplantation, the removal of food and
hydration, and research with the mentally ill or the disabled. But both
private choices and public policies should incorporate sound and accurate
science whenever possible. What I have tried to indicate is that in these
current discussions, individual choices and public policies have been based
on "scientific" myth, rather than on objective scientific facts.