Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario
Re: Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code
11 September, 2008
Full Text
The principle that conscientious objectors ought
to be forced to refer for or otherwise facilitate a
morally controversial procedure would apply to all
controversial procedures, such as sex-selective
abortion, infant male circumcision, assisted suicide
and euthanasia or even the amputation of healthy
body parts.
To demand that physicians provide or assist in
the provision of procedures or services that they
believe to be wrong treats them as things or tools
to be used by others. This is unacceptable because
it denies their "essential humanity."
In principle, it is not unreasonable for
physicians to refuse to refer patients for
procedures to which they object for reasons of
conscience. The referral/facilitation required in
the draft is the same kind of action that is defined
as "participation" in the AMA policies on capital
punishment and torture. Professional associations
will refuse all forms of direct and indirect
participation even in legal acts that they deem to
be immoral. This is precisely the position taken by
conscientious objectors.
Physicians who decline to do something they
believe to be wrong are not discriminating against
individuals on grounds prohibited by the Ontario
Human Rights Code. Their concern is to avoid direct
or indirect complicity in wrongdoing, not with the
personal characteristics, status or inclinations of
a patient.
In adjudicating complaints that involve conflicts
centred on the exercise of freedom or conscience by
physicians, the College should confine its review to
issues clearly within its competence, leaving human
rights issues to be addressed by more appropriate
authorities.
The four principles to which the draft statement
refers do not support the view that physicians are
obliged to "set aside their personal beliefs" and do
what they believe to be wrong, nor do the principles
contribute to the resolution of potential conflicts
in such cases.
Physicians should not be accused of preaching
simply because they comply with ethical guidelines
that require them to disclose moral or religious
views that may influence their practice, or explain
their position while providing information necessary
to respect the principle of informed consent.
The Project recommends that College Council take
the position that the suppression of fundamental
freedoms among physicians in the province must
proceed without the assistance of the College of
Physicians and Surgeons.
Table of Contents
I. Introduction
I.1. The submissions of the Ontario Human Rights
Commission to the College, dated 14 February, 2008
1
and 15 August, 2008,
2
indicate that the principal threat to freedom of
conscience and religion for physicians in the
province of Ontario emanates from the Commission
rather than from the College of Physicians and
Surgeons. The OHRC submissions raise more issues
than the College's draft policy.
I.2. Further: the Commission has extensive authority
to review statutes and regulations and direct
individuals and organizations in the interpretation
and application of the
Human Rights Code.
This is backed by the threat of prosecution before
the Human Rights Tribunal, which is guided by
Commission policies in its adjudication of cases.
3
I.3. As reflected in its August submission, the
Commission claims the power to direct the College as
to the precise wording of its ethical guidelines.
Its apparent intention is to use the College as an
instrument through which it will dictate the terms
upon which religious and non-religious believers
will be permitted to practise medicine in Ontario.
What other claims it may make to direct the
development of medical ethics remain to be seen.
I.4. Unfortunately, some will suspect that Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code
reflects College thinking previously frustrated by
resistance from physicians, now resurrected with the
help of the OHRC.4
Alternatively, the draft policy may be seen as a
first effort by the College to accommodate itself to
a new role as surrogate for the Commission. A more
charitable assessment would see Physicians and
the Ontario Human Rights Code as a good-faith
attempt at harm reduction: better that the
"inevitable" suppression of freedom of conscience
among physicians be managed quietly by knowledgeable
and sympathetic colleagues than by the OHRC. There
are precedents for this approach.5
I.5. Nonetheless, the present submission takes Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code at
face value, and is largely confined to the policy as
formulated by the College rather than the policy the
OHRC wishes to impose. It is not possible here to
adequately address the issues raised in the OHRC
submissions, particularly since the Commission, in
its fixation on the provision of services, does not
appear to appreciate the distinction between surgery
and automotive repair.
I.6. The scope of the present submission is further
restricted to those parts of the policy dealing with
moral or religious beliefs and professional
misconduct.
I.7. Since the publication of
Physicians and the
Ontario Human Rights Code, the President of the
College has affirmed that, despite the statements
made in the draft policy, "the College does not
expect physicians to provide medical services that
are against their moral or religious beliefs."6
An e-mail to physicians repeated this assurance and
drew specific attention to concerns raised among
respondents to a purported obligation to assist
patients in obtaining morally controversial
services.7
Accordingly, the focus of this submission will be
the issue of referral.
II. Preliminaries
II.1 Before dealing with substantive questions it
is necessary to draw attention to a number of points
that are highly relevant to the discussion, but
which are usually overlooked.
II.2 It has become an article of faith with many,
especially many holding public positions, that faith
has no place in public and professional life. This
is evident in the dogmatic assertion by the OHRC of
its belief that physicians "must essentially 'check
their personal views at the door' in providing
medical care."
8
II.3 The OHRC claim calls to mind comments made
by Dr. James Robert Brown in 2002. A professor of
science and religion of the University of Toronto,
Dr. Brown offered a simple solution for health care
workers who don't want to be involved with things
like abortion or contraception. These "scum" - that
was his word - should "resign from medicine and find
another job." His reasoning was very simple.
Religious beliefs are highly
emotional - as is any belief that is affecting your
behaviour in society. You have no right letting your
private beliefs affect your public behaviour.9
II.4 Now, when Dr. Brown declared that no one
should be allowed to let private belief affect
public behaviour, he was doing precisely that. He
was acting publicly upon his private belief
that conscientious objectors in health care should
not be allowed to act publicly upon theirs.
Dr. Brown did not explain why this should be so, but
others have made the attempt.
II.5 Religious beliefs, so the argument goes, are
unreliable and divisive because they are
unscientific, essentially 'private' and 'personal'
in nature. It is said that they must be banished
from public affairs in a secular society in the
interests of social harmony, progress and, now,
human 'rights.' Proponents of this view point to
religious wars and persecutions throughout history
to justify their claims. However, considered within
a broader social and historical context that
includes the oppressive and frequently bloody
pursuit of secular objectives in the French
Revolution, Stalinist Russia and Nazi Germany, the
argument is unpersuasive. And it becomes even less
persuasive in the case of individuals.
II.6 For example: after ten years of bloody wars,
the ancient Indian emperor Asoka became a Buddhist,
and decided that he should rule his people like a
father, with "morality and social compassion." Among
other things, he provided them with free hospitals
and veterinary clinics, and built new roads and rest
houses for travellers. In other words, Asoka let his
private beliefs affect his public behaviour.10
Like Mother Theresa of Calcutta - who also let her
private beliefs influence her public behaviour -
Asoka is still revered in India, nicknamed "the
saint."
II.7 Moving from ancient times into the last
century, one recalls that fewer than half the
Canadians who landed at Dieppe in 1942 made it back.
The Royal Hamilton Light Infantry landed with 582
men; 365 were killed or taken prisoner.11
John Foote was honorary chaplain to the regiment.
For eight hours, repeatedly exposing himself to "an
inferno of fire," he assisted the Regimental Medical
Officer, going out to the wounded, carrying them to
shelter, and, later, carrying them on his back to
evacuation landing craft. Ultimately, he chose to
stay on the beach and be taken prisoner with those
left behind.12
II.8 Asoka, Mother Theresa and John Foote were
religious believers, but it is false to assert that
only religious believers are motivated by belief. In
1915, at Ypres, Canadian physician Francis Scrimger
ordered the evacuation of his dressing station, but
remained behind to stabilize a wounded officer. As
shells dropped around him, demolished the building
and set it on fire, he shielded his patient with his
own body as he worked, and then carried the larger
man to safety through an artillery barrage.13Foote,
a Presbyterian minister, and Scrimger, "an atheist
by outward appearances,"14both
acted in accordance with their personal beliefs;
both were awarded the Victoria Cross.
II.9 If one accepts the logic of Professor Brown,
Scrimger deserved the award but Foote did not,
because Foote had no business letting his religious
beliefs influence his public behaviour. On the other
hand, the stated policy of the Ontario Human Rights
Commission would deny both recognition, on the
broader grounds that both failed to 'check their
personal views at the door' when the bullets started
to fly.
II.10 The stories of Foote and Scrimger may
remind physician members of the College Council of
countless colleagues in the profession who, through
the centuries, have died of contagious and incurable
diseases contracted because they refused to abandon
their patients. Not a few of this number were
motivated by personal beliefs, religious or
otherwise, but the profession has never taken
towards them the attitude now demanded of it by the
Ontario Human Rights Commission.
II.11 All public behaviour - how one treats other
people, how one treats animals, how one treats the
environment - is determined by what one believes.
All beliefs influence public behaviour. Some of
these beliefs are religious, some not, but all are
beliefs. That human dignity exists -or that it does
not - or that human life is worthy of unconditional
reverence - or merely conditional respect - and
notions of beneficence, justice and equality are not
the product of scientific enquiry, but rest upon
faith: upon beliefs about human nature, the meaning
and purpose of life, the existence of good and evil.
II.12 Disputes about morality
- about the morality of contraception, assisted
suicide, stem cell research or artificial
reproduction - are always, at the core, disputes
between people of different beliefs, whether or not
those beliefs are religious. "Everyone 'believes',"
writes social critic Iain Benson. "The question is,
what do we believe in and for what reasons?"
Once we realize that everyone
necessarily operates out of some kind of faith
assumptions we stop excluding analysis of faith from
public life. We cannot simply banish "religious"
faiths from our common conversations about how we
ought to order our lives together while leaving
unexamined all those "implicit faiths" in such areas
as public education, medicine, law or politics.15
II.13 It might be argued that Professor Brown's
declaration expressed, not just a private
conviction, but a broad public consensus, a
consensus of serious establishment thinkers (like
members of the OHRC), or, perhaps, a consensus
reflecting "the ethics of the profession."16
II.14 However, this kind of 'consensus' is
typically achieved by taking into account only
opinions consistent with ethical, moral or religious
presuppositions that are congenial to a dominant
elite. The resulting 'consensus' is, in reality,
simply the majority opinion of like-minded
individuals, not a genuine ethical synthesis
reflecting common ground with those who think
differently.17
Unfortunately, this usually becomes clear only when
documents like Physicians and the Ontario Human
Rights Code become public knowledge, and those
excluded from the table make themselves heard.
II.15 More to the point, to identify beliefs as
'private' or 'personal' does not help to resolve a
question about the exercise of freedom of
conscience. The beliefs of many conscientious
objectors, while certainly personal in one sense,
are actually shared with tens of thousands, or even
hundreds of thousands or hundreds of millions of
people, living and dead, who form part of great
religious, philosophical and moral traditions. If
their beliefs are 'private,' those of Professor
Brown, the College Council and the OHRC are not less
so. Disputes about what counts as 'private' or
'public' thus end in a stalemate.
II.16 The question does not turn on privacy, but
truth. If the College Council possess a moral vision
that is superior to that of objecting physicians, it
is clear that Council's superior moral views ought
to prevail. But, in that case, Council members
should be able and willing to explain first, why
they are better judges of morality than objecting
physicians, and, second, why their judgement should
be forced upon unwilling colleagues. Avoiding the
issue by hiding behind noble sounding phrases like
"the ethics of the profession" will not do.
II.17 It is argued that there are limits to the
exercise of freedom of conscience and religion. This
is hardly a new proposition. Oliver Cromwell said as
much 400 years ago.
As for the People [of
Ireland], what thoughts they have in matters of
Religion in their own breasts I cannot reach; but
shall think it my duty, if they walk honestly and
peaceably, Not to cause them in the least to suffer
for the same. And shall endeavour to walk patiently
and in love towards them to see if at any time it
shall please God to give them another or a better
mind. And all men under the power of England, within
this Dominion, are hereby required and enjoined
strictly and religiously to do the same.18
But to act publicly upon religious belief
was, for Cromwell, another matter.
. . . I shall not, where I
have the power, and the Lord is pleased to bless me,
suffer the exercise of the Mass . . . nor . . .
suffer you that are Papists, where I can find you
seducing the People, or by any overt act violating
the Laws established; but if you come into my hands,
I shall cause to be inflicted the punishments
appointed by the Laws.19
II.18 Cromwell, the Supreme Court of Canada and
the Ontario Human Rights Commission all agree that
"the freedom to hold beliefs is broader than the
freedom to act on them."20
So, for that matter, do those who support freedom of
conscience in health care. The principle is not in
dispute. What is in dispute is where the line
between belief and expression is to be drawn, and
what is to be done with those who cross it. The
Irish did not share Cromwell's views about where the
line should be drawn, nor is it clear that there is
anything approaching a consensus in Canada on this
point. So it is useful to remember Oliver Cromwell
and the Irish when social and political elites begin
to sound like the Lord Protector.
II.19 What is conducive to human well-being is
determined by the nature of the human person. There
can be no agreement upon what is good for the
patient without first agreeing upon that. One's
understanding of the nature of the human person
determines not only how one defines the needs of the
patient, but how one approaches every moral or
ethical problem in medicine.
II.20 Reasoning from different beliefs about what
man is and what is good for him leads to different
definitions of "need," different understandings of
"harm," different concepts of right and wrong, and,
ultimately, to different ethical conclusions.21
II.21 Consider two different statements: (a) man
is a creature whose purpose for existence depends
upon his ability to think, choose and communicate;
b) man is a creature for whom intellect, choice and
communication are attributes of existence, but do
not establish his purpose for existence. Statements
(a) and (b) express non-religious belief, not
empirically verified fact. Such beliefs - usually
implicit rather than explicit - direct the course of
subsequent discussion.
II.22 Bioethicists working from (a) would have
little objection to the substitution of persistently
unconscious human subjects for animals in
experimental research.22
Those who accept (b) would be more inclined to
object.23
Finally, bioethicists who do not believe in
'purpose' beyond filling an ecological niche would
dismiss the whole discussion as wrong-headed.
II.23 What must be emphasized is that when people
cannot achieve a consensus about the morality of a
procedure, it is frequently because they are
operating from different beliefs about the nature of
the human person. Disagreement is seldom about facts
- the province of science - but about what to
believe in light of them - the province of
philosophy and religion.
II.24 These considerations also apply when one
attempts to rationally limit freedoms or balance
conflicting rights claims.
II.25 One frequently encounters references to a
"social contract" between the medical profession and
society, especially in discussions about the meaning
of "professionalism."24
The Royal College of Physicians has suggested
that, in relation to medical practice, it is more
accurate to speak of a "moral contract" between
society and the profession.25
Others have argued that the concept of a social
"covenant" provides a better framework for ethical
reflection.26
II.26 It is important to recognize that, whether
the term of choice be contract or covenant, or the
contract be social or moral, all such notions are
convenient fictions. The Oxford Companion to
Philosophy makes the point:
Contract, social: The
imaginary device through which equally imaginary
individuals, living in solitude (or, perhaps,
nuclear families) , without government, without a
stable division of labour or dependable exchange
relations, without parties, leagues, congregations,
assemblies or associations of any sort, come
together to form a society, accepting obligations of
some minimal kind to one another, and immediately or
very soon thereafter binding themselves to a
political sovereign who can enforce those
obligations.27
II.27 Theories of 'contract' and 'convenant' are
tools that can be usefully employed to explore
different aspects of human relationships, but they
become dangerous when they are thought to offer
adequate explanations of those relationships, or
when one moves from speculative discussion and
analysis to the enforcement of purported
obligations. It is also necessary to recall that
claims about the precise content of a contract
become especially intense when the parties involved
disagree.
II.28 Socialized medicine has been and continues
to be a great benefit to many people, but little
attention has been paid to the dynamic of
expectation that arises when the state assumes
primary responsibility for the delivery of health
care. Health care providers come to be seen as state
employees, and citizens begin to believe that they
are entitled to demand from health care providers
the services they have paid for through taxes.
II.29 In this case it is argued that there is an
actual rather than theoretical social contract for
the provision of health care, and that the state and
the medical profession are parties to it.
Nonetheless, given the nature and complexity of
health care, much of the precise content of such a
contract must remain undefined, so that conflicts
like the one now faced by the College will arise.
The problem becomes especially acute when legal but
morally controversial procedures are the focus of
the conflict.
II.30 Citizens are likely to expect the state to
enforce what they consider to be the terms of the
contract against reluctant employees and other
health care providers through institutions like the
College of Physicians and the OHRC. However, even if
one posits the existence of a contract, such an
expectation ignores two key points.
II.31 First: the terms of the contract on this
issue have never been defined or settled. It is a
matter of fact that, in assisting in the birth of
medicare, the medical profession did not agree that
its members would, from that point, deliver every
service demanded by the public, regardless of their
conscientious convictions. The state, a party to the
contract, can ask that it be re-negotiated, but
cannot unilaterally demand that the profession "read
in" non-existent provisions.
II.32 Second: even if physicians have become de
facto employees of the state since the introduction
of public health care, it does not follow that they
cannot exercise freedom of conscience and religion.
On the contrary: as employees of a "service
industry," they are entitled to the same
accommodation of freedom of conscience and religion
available to employees of other service industries.
II.33 The standard - set out by the OHRC itself -
is that they must be accommodated to the point of
undue hardship.28
Given the enormous resources available to their
employer - the state - it is difficult to imagine
under what circumstances it might experience "undue
hardship" in the delivery of health care. Not
incidentally, physicians are also entitled to demand
that their employer - the state - not permit their
workplace environments to be poisoned against them
by state institutions, like the OHRC.
II.34 Moving from imaginary devices to actual
law, some writers assert that the fiduciary duties
of physicians requires them to subordinate their
conscientious convictions to those of their
patients. Professors R.J. Cook and B.M. Dickens have
made this claim,29
citing the Supreme Court of Canada case, McInerney v. MacDonald.30
II.35 However, McInerney had absolutely
nothing to do with conflicts of conscience. It
concerned the duty of a physician to release a
patient's medical records to her upon request, and
the nature of fiduciary relationships was not
discussed at length. Moreover, the Court ruled that
fiduciary relationships and obligations are "shaped
by the demands of the situation"; they are not
governed by a "fixed set of rules and principles."
Mr. Justice La Forest, writing for the court,
stated, "A physician-patient relationship may
properly be described as'fiduciary' for some
purposes, but not for others."31
In other words, that the physician patient
relationship is fiduciary for the purpose of
disclosing patient records does not imply that it is
fiduciary for the purpose of suppressing the
conscientious convictions of the physician.
II.36 Finally, the court in McInerney accepted the characterization of the
physician-patient relationship as "the same . . . as
that which exists in equity between a parent and his
child, a man and his wife, an attorney and his
client, a confessor and his penitent, and a guardian
and his ward."32
Pursuing the analogy, no one has ever suggested that
the fiduciary obligations of parents, husbands,
attorneys, confessors, and guardians require them to
sacrifice their own integrity to the "desires" of
others. McInerney does not even remotely
imply that physicians have such a duty.33
II.37 It is also said that
health care workers cannot refuse to provide any
legal procedure, as if the legality of the procedure
were sufficient to impose a duty to provide it upon
either the profession as a whole or individual
physicians. It can be shown that this is not yet the
case, though the OHRC appears to be taking this
position.
11.38 Sex selective abortion: There is no
law against sex-selective abortion in Canada, nor
against determining the sex of an infant before
birth. Nonetheless, the Deputy Registrar of the
College of Physicians and Surgeons of British
Columbia was horrified in August, 2005, when he
learned that a pre-natal gender testing kit was
being marketed on the internet. Dr. T. Peter Seland,
described gender selection as "immoral." He
explained that College policy was not to disclose
the sex of a baby until after 24 weeks gestation in
order to reduce the risk of gender selection, and
that physicians violating the policy were liable to
be disciplined by the College.34
This clearly indicates that the legality of a
procedure is not reason enough to compel a health
care worker to provide it.
II.39 Amputation: In 1999, Dr. Robert
Smith of Scotland performed single leg amputations
on two patients who desired the amputation of
healthy limbs. The surgery was performed with the
permission of the Medical Director and Chief
Executive of the hospital, in a National Health
Service operating theatre with NHS personnel, after
consultation with the General Medical Council and
professional bodies.35
The procedures were legal and even deemed ethical by
regulatory authorities, but, to date, no one has
argued that this is sufficient reason to oblige
surgeons to amputate healthy limbs upon request, and
to compel physicians to refer for such surgery.
II.40 Execution: Capital punishment is
legal in a number of jurisdictions. 35 of the 38
American states that use lethal injection as a means
of execution permit the participation of physicians,
and 17 of them require it. "Thirteen jurors,
citizens of the state, have made a decision,"
explained one physician who assists with executions.
"And if I live in that state and that's the law,
then I would see it as being an obligation to be
available."36
The law is the law, after all. However, despite the
legality of the procedure, and in defiance of the
laws that actually require the attendance of
physicians, the Code of Ethics of the American
Medical Association forbids the participation of
physicians in executions,37
and those who ignore the ban risk losing their
licenses to practise.38
In the face of pending decision of the American
Supreme Court, a guest editorial commented on the
obvious conflict between the expectations of the law
and the attitude of physicians:
In their fuller examination of
Baze v. Rees, the justices should not presume
that the medical profession will be available to
assist in the taking of human lives . . .The future
of capital punishment in the United States will be
up to the justices, but the involvement of
physicians in executions will be up to the medical
profession.39
III. The problem of complicity
III.1 At first glance, the College draft policy
Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code
and subsequent clarification by the President are
contradictory and confusing. On the one hand, the
draft policy states that "there may be times when it
may be necessary for physicians to set aside their
personal beliefs," and implies that those who fail
to do so face prosecution for professional
misconduct or human rights offences.40
On the other, the President has publicly stated that
"the College does not expect physicians to provide
medical services that are against their moral or
religious beliefs."41
III.2 The apparent contradiction is resolved by
attending more closely to the President's statement.
College officials do not expect physicians to
provide services that they believe to be wrong
(i.e., perform or assist in an abortion, for
example), but this does not preclude a demand that
they facilitate the provision of such services (by
arranging for abortion). And this is exactly what
the draft policy proposes:
Tell patients about their
right to see another physician . . . If patients or
potential patients cannot readily make their own
arrangements to see another doctor or health care
provider, physicians must ensure arrangements are
made, without delay, for another doctor to take over
their care.42
(emphasis added)
Similarly, the draft policy strongly implies that
physicians are obliged to help individuals arrange
for artificial reproduction.43
In principle, there is no reason why such a rule
would not extend to any other morally controversial
procedure.
III.3 It thus appears that College officials are
working from what might be called the 'Absolutionist
Premise:' that someone who merely arranges for
an act is absolved of moral responsibility because
only someone who actually does an act is morally
responsible for it. In the words of the American
College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, "the
logic of conscience, as a form of self-reflection on
and judgement about whether one's own acts are
obligatory or prohibited, means that it would be odd
or absurd to say, "I would have a guilty conscience
if she did X."44
III.4 Alternatively, College officials may admit
that some moral responsibility is incurred by
referral or by otherwise facilitating a procedure,
but that the degree of responsibility is
sufficiently diminished in such cases that it is of
no real significance. Call this the 'Dismissive
Premise.'
III.5 On either account, the position of College
officials raises the issues discussed in paragraphs
II.12 to II.15. Whether they
assert that referral or facilitation do not incur
moral responsibility, or that the degree of moral
responsibility incurred is so minimal as to be
inconsequential, they are making a moral judgement
and demanding that others adhere to it.
III.6 The Absolutionist Premise is
illustrated by the opinion of Newsweekcolumnist
Jonathan Alter. In the weeks following the terrorist
attacks on the United States in September, 2001,
Alter argued that it was time to think about
torturing terrorist suspects who might have
information about plans for such horrendous crimes.
He acknowledged that physical torture was "contrary
to American values," but argued that torture is
appropriate in some circumstances, and proposed a
novel 'compromise:' that the United States turn
terrorist suspects who won't talk over to "less
squeamish allies,"45
a practice known as "extraordinary rendition." The
allies would then do what Americans would not,
without compromising American values.
III.7 Less than a year later, Canadian citizen
Maher Arar, returning home from Zurich through New
York, was detained, interrogated and "rendered" to
Syria by U.S. authorities.46
In Syria he was imprisoned for almost a year,
"interrogated, tortured and held in degrading and
inhumane conditions."47
III.8 A subsequent "comprehensive and thorough"
investigation "did not turn up any evidence that he
had committed any criminal offence" and disclosed
"no evidence" that he was a threat to Canadian
security."48
College Council will recall that a commission of
inquiry was appointed to investigate "the actions of
Canadian officials" in the case.49
III.9 What was of concern to Mr. Arar, the public
and the government was whether or not Canadian
officials had caused or contributed to what happened
to Mr. Arar, even though his deportation to Syria
was effected by the United States, and Syrian
officials imprisoned and tortured him. The key issue
was whether or not Canada was complicit in torture.
III.10 Concern about Canadian complicity surfaces
repeatedly in the report of the commission of
inquiry: in briefing notes to the Commissioner of
the RCMP,50
in the testimony of the Canadian Ambassador to
Syria,51
in references to the possibility of RCMP complicity
in his deportation,52
about the perception of complicity if CSIS agents
met Mr. Arar in Syria,53
in the suggestion that evidence of complicity could
show "a pattern of misconduct,"54
and in the conclusions and recommendations of the
report itself.55
III.11 The issue of complicity arose again in
2007 when a report in Toronto's Globe and Mail
alleged that prisoners taken in Afghanistan by
Canadian troops and turned over to Afghan
authorities were being mistreated and tortured.56
"Canada is hardly in a position to claim it did not
know what was going on," said the Globe. "At
best, it tried not to know; at worst, it knew and
said nothing."57
On this view, one can be complicit in wrongdoing not
only by acting, but by failing to act, and even by
silence. The Globe editorial brings to mind the
words of Martin Luther King and Mahatma Ghandi.58
III.12 Thus far the complicity of government
officials. But The Lancet, among others, has
asked, "How complicit are doctors in the abuse of
detainees?"59
and other journal articles have explored the answer
with some anxiety.60
III.13 The Arar Inquiry, the concerns raised by
the Globe and Mail story about Afghan
detainees and the alarm raised about physician
complicity in torture make sense only on the
presumption that one can be morally responsible for
acts actually committed by another person. The
Absolutionist Premise does not provide a plausible
starting point for moral reasoning.
III.14 The Dismissive Premise is more
promising. Granted that one can be morally
responsible for acts actually committed by another,
there may be differences of opinion about what kind
of action or omission incurs such responsibility.
These differences need not be thoroughly canvassed
in this paper. It is sufficient to ask if the kind
of action required by the draft policy could have
that effect. That is: if a physician refers or
otherwise helps a patient to obtain what be believes
to be an immoral procedure, is he a culpable
participant in the provision of the procedure?
III.15 The issue of
culpable participation in a morally controversial
procedure has been considered by the American
Medical Association in its policy on capital
punishment.61
It forbids physician participation in executions,
and defines participation as
(1) an action which would
directly cause the death of the condemned;
(2) an action which would
assist, supervise, or contribute to the ability of
another individual to directly cause the death of
the condemned;
(3) an action which could
automatically cause an execution to be carried out
on a condemned prisoner.
III.16 Among the actions identified by the AMA as
"participation" in executions are the prescription
or administration of tranquillizers or other drugs
as part of the procedure, directly or indirectly
monitoring vital signs, rendering technical advice
or consulting with the executioners, and even
(except at the request of the condemned, or in a
non-professional capacity) attending or observing an
execution.
III.17 The attention paid to what others might
consider insignificant detail is exemplified in the
provision that permits physicians to certify death,
providing that death has been pronounced by someone
else, and by restrictions on the donation of organs
by the deceased.
III.18 The AMA also prohibits physician
participation in torture. Participation is defined
to include, but is not limited to, "providing or
withholding any services, substances, or knowledge
to facilitate the practice of torture."62
The Canadian Medical Association, while not faced
with the problem of capital punishment, has voiced
its opposition to physician involvement in the
punishment or torture of prisoners. The CMA states
that physicians "should refuse to allow their
professional or research skills to be used in any
way" for such purposes.63
III.19 While referral is not mentioned in the AMA
policy on capital punishment, nor in the Canadian or
American policies on torture, one cannot imagine
that either the AMA or CMA would agree that
physicians who refuse to participate in torture or
executions should be made to "ensure arrangements
are made, without delay" to find a substitute. In
fact, it is likely that both the CMA and AMA would
censure a physician who did so voluntarily, on the
grounds that such conduct would make him complicit
in a gravely immoral act.
III.20 In any case, it is reasonable to hold that
the kind of action required by Physicians and the
Ontario Human Rights Code is the same kind of
action that is defined as "participation" in the AMA
policies on capital punishment and torture. The
model provided by the AMA policy indicates that, in
principle, at least, it is not unreasonable for
physicians to refuse to refer patients for
procedures to which they object for reasons of
conscience, on the grounds that referral would make
them complicit in a wrongful act.
III.21 The point here, of course, is not that
capital punishment or torture are morally equivalent
to artificial reproduction, contraception or other
controversial medical procedures. The point is that,
when professional associations are convinced that an
act is seriously wrong - even if it is legal - one
finds them willing to refuse all forms of direct and
indirect participation in order to avoid moral
complicity in the act. This is precisely the
position taken by conscientious objectors in health
care.
III.22 Having considered the problem of
complicity, it is now worth asking why the subject
of complicity in wrongful acts is not only of grave
concern to ethical physicians, medical journals, and
professional associations, but why it can so
thoroughly arouse the public, the media, and
politicians: why commissions of inquiry will so
meticulously investigate the possibility of
complicity, producing hundreds upon hundreds of
pages of detailed analysis of the evidence taken, at
no little cost to the public purse.
III.23 A jaded few will respond that reports of
scandal will always sell newspapers, that scandal
always energizes the self-righteous (both the
religious and the politically-correct varieties) and
that scandal is one of the traditional weapons used
against opponents by politicians of all stripes.
There is some truth to this, but, going deeper into
it, why is complicity in wrongdoing scandalous?
III.24 The answer must be that there is something
about complicity in wrongdoing that triggers an
almost instinctive reaction in people, something
about it that touches some peculiar, deep and almost
universal sense of abhorrence. One says "almost"
instinctive and "almost" universal because, of
course, there have always been exceptions:
Eichmanns, Pol Pots, Rwandan machete men, for
example. And the degree of sensitivity varies from
person to person, from subject to subject, and from
one culture to another. Nonetheless, complicity in
wrongdoing can be a source of scandal, a political
weapon and the subject for public inquiries only
because it has some real and profound significance.
III.25 The nature of that significance is
suggested by a number of expressions: "poisoned"
fruit doctrine, "tainted"evidence, money that has to
be "laundered," and "dirty" hands. A senior Iraqi
surgeon, commenting on the complicity of physicians
in torture under Saddam Hussein, said that "the
state wanted them to have 'dirty hands'."64
In contrast, some writers refer approvingly to a
"dirty hands principle":
Philosopher Sidney Axinn tells
us the Dirty Hands principle "holds that in order to
govern an institution one must sometimes do things
that are immoral." He goes on to say that advocates
would claim that "we do not want leaders who are so
concerned with their own personal morality that they
will not do `what is necessary' to ... win the
battle.... We have an inept leader if we have a
person who is so morally fastidious that he or she
will not break the law when that is the only way to
success" (Axinn, 1989: 138).65
But whichever view one takes of "dirty hands,"
all of these expressions convey an uncomfortable
sense that something is felt to be soiled by
complicity in wrongdoing. What is that something?
And what is the nature of that cloying grime?
III.26 The answer suggested by the Project is
that the "something" is not a "thing" at all, but
the human person, and that the sense of uncleanness
or taint associated with complicity in wrongdoing is
the natural response of the human person to
something fundamentally opposed to his nature,
well-being and dignity.
IV. The human person
IV.1 The physician, a unique someone who
identifies himself as "I" and "me,"66
has only one identity, served by a single conscience
that governs his conduct in private and professional
life. This moral unity of the human person is
identified as integrity, a virtue highly prized by
Martin Luther King, who described it at as essential
for "a complete life."67
[W]e must remember that it's
possible to affirm the existence of God with your
lips and deny his existence with your life. . . . We
say with our mouths that we believe in him, but we
live with our lives like he never existed . . .
That's a dangerous type of atheism.68
IV.2 Against this, some writers have invoked the
venerable concept of self-sacrifice.
"Professionalism," Professor R. Alta Charo suggests
rhetorically, ought to include "the rather
old-fashioned notion of putting others before
oneself."69
IV.3 But self-sacrifice, in the tradition of
King, Gandhi and Lewis, while it might mean going to
jail or even the loss of one's life, has never been
understood to include the sacrifice of one's
integrity. To abandon one's moral or ethical
convictions in order to serve others is
prostitution, not professionalism. "He who
surrenders himself without reservation," warned C.S.
Lewis, "to the temporal claims of a nation, or a
party, or a class" - one could here add 'profession'
- "is rendering to Caesar that which, of all things,
emphatically belongs to God: himself."70
IV.4 The integrity or wholeness of the human
person was also a key element in the thought of
French philosopher Jacques Maritain. He emphasized
that the human person is a "whole, an open and
generous whole" that to be a human person "involves
totality."
71
The notion of personality thus
involves that of totality and independence; no
matter how poor and crushed a person may be, as such
he is a whole, and as a person subsists in an
independent manner. To say that a man is a person is
to say that in the depth of his being he is more a
whole than a part and more independent than servile.72
IV.5 This concept is not foreign to the practice
of modern medicine. Canadian ethicist Margaret
Somerville, for example, asserts that one cannot
overemphasize the importance of the notion of
'patient-as-person' and acknowledges a "totality of
the person" that goes beyond the purely physical.73
IV.6 "Man," wrote Maritain, "is an individual who
holds himself in hand by his intelligence and his
will."
He exists not merely
physically; there is in him a richer and nobler
existence; he has spiritual superexistence through
knowledge and through love.74
IV.7 Applying this principle, Maritain asserted
that, even as a member of society or the state, a
man "has secrets that escape the group and a
vocation which the group does not encompass."75
His whole person is engaged in society through his
social and political activities and his work, but
"not by reason of his entire self and all that is in
him." 76
For in the person there are
some things - and they are the most important and
sacred ones - which transcend political society and
draw man in his entirety above political society -
the very same whole man who, by reason of another
category of things, is a part of political society.
77
IV.8 Even as part of society, Maritain insisted,
"the human person is something more than a part;"78
he remains a whole, and must be treated as a whole.79
A part exists only to comprise or sustain a whole;
it is a means to that end. But the human person is
an end in himself, not a means to an end.80
Thus, according to Maritain, the nature of the
human person is such that it "would have no man
exploited by another man, as a tool to serve the
latter's own particular good."81
IV.9 British philosopher Cyril Joad applied this
to the philosophy of democratic government:
To the right of the individual
to be treated as an end, which entails his right to
the full development and expression of his
personality, all other rights and claims must, the
democrat holds, be subordinated. I do not know how
this principle is to be defended any more than I can
frame a defence for the principles of democracy and
liberty.82
In company with Maritain, Professor Joad insisted
that it is an essential tenet of democratic
government that the state is made for man, but man
is not made for the state.83
IV.10 To reduce human persons to the status of
tools or things to be used for ends chosen by others
is reprehensible: "very wicked," wrote C.S. Lewis.84
Likewise, Martin Luther King condemned segregation
as "morally wrong and awful" precisely because it
relegated persons "to the status of things."85
IV.11 Similarly, Polish philosopher Karol Wojtyla
(later Pope John Paul II):
. . . we must never treat a
person as a means to an end. This principle has a
universal validity. Nobody can use a person as a
means towards an end, no human being, nor yet God
the Creator.86
IV.12 Maritain, Joad, Lewis, King and Wojtyla
reaffirmed in the twentieth century what Immanuel
Kant had written in the eighteenth: "Act so that you
treat humanity, whether in your own person or in
that of another, always as an end and never as a
means only."87
IV.13 Perhaps ironically, this was the approach
taken when Madame Justice Bertha Wilson of the
Supreme Court of Canada addressed the issue of
freedom of conscience in the landmark 1988 case R
v. Morgentaler. Madame Justice Wilson argued
that "an emphasis on individual conscience and
individual judgment . . . lies at the heart of our
democratic political tradition."88
Wilson held that it was indisputable that the
decision to have an abortion "is essentially a moral
decision, a matter of conscience."
The question is: whose
conscience? Is the conscience of the woman to be
paramount or the conscience of the state? I believe.
. . that in a free and democratic society it must be
the conscience of the individual. Indeed, s. 2(a)
makes it clear that this freedom belongs to
"everyone", i.e., to each of us individually.89
IV.14 "Everyone" includes every physician. But,
at this point in the judgement, Wilson was not
discussing whether or not the conscience of a woman
should prevail over that of an objecting physician,
but how the conscientious judgement of an individual
should stand against that of the state. Her answer
was that, in a free and democratic society, "the
state will respect choices made by individuals and,
to the greatest extent possible, will avoid
subordinating these choices to any one conception of
the good life."90
IV.15 Quoting the above passage from Professor
Joad's book, Wilson approved the principle than a
human person must never be treated as a means to an
end - especially an end chosen by someone else, or
by the state. Wilson rejected the idea that, in
questions of morality, the state should endorse and
enforce "one conscientiously-held view at the
expense of another," for that is "to deny freedom of
conscience to some, to treat them as means to an
end, to deprive them . . .of their 'essential
humanity'."91
IV.16 In the tradition of Kant, C.S. Lewis,
Martin Luther King, Cyril Joad and Karol Wojtyla,
and following Madame Justice Wilson, for the OHRC or
the College of Physicians and Surgeons to demand
that physicians provide or assist in the provision
of procedures or services that they believe to be
wrong is to treat them as means to an end and
deprive them of their "essential humanity."
IV.17 The OHRC proposes physicians, as a matter
of principle and even as a matter of law, can be
compelled to do what they believe to be wrong, and
that they can be punished if they do not. It is the
position of the Project that this is a blasphemy
against the human spirit. Applying to the
Commission's demands the words of Alexander
Solzhenitsyn, "To this putrefaction of soul, this
spiritual enslavement, human beings who wish to be
human cannot consent."92
V. Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code
V.1 According to Physicians and the Ontario
Human Rights Code, "physicians should be aware
that the College is obliged to consider the [Human
Rights] Code when determining whether
physician conduct is consistent with the
expectations of the profession. Compliance with the
Code is one factor the College will consider
when evaluating physician conduct."
V.2 The College acknowledges that it "does not
have the expertise or the authority to make complex,
new determinations of human rights law," which
suggests that it believes that it has the expertise
and authority to apply existing human rights law.
Even if one accepts this opinion, prudence suggests
that compliance with the Code should not be a
significant factor in the College's assessment of a
case except in the clearest of cases.
V.3 Complaints involving physicians who have
declined to do something for reasons of conscience
or religion are not the clearest of cases. The
profound and complex issues involved and the
far-reaching consequences of decisions in such cases
afford the College good reason to confine its review
to issues clearly within its competence, and leave
human rights issues to be dealt with directly by
those who profess to have the requisite expertise
and authority.
V.4 Physicians who decline to do something they
believe to be wrong are not discriminating against
individuals on grounds prohibited by the Ontario
Human Rights Code. Their concern is to avoid
direct or indirect complicity in wrongdoing, not
with the personal characteristics, status or
inclinations of a patient.
V.5 In its discussion of physician-patient
conflicts arising from the religious convictions of
the physician, Physicians and the Ontario Human
Rights Code makes no clear distinction between
the needs of a patient and the desires of a patient,
referring at one point to needs,
93 and at another to "a patients's
need or desire."94
This must be clarified, because the difference
between "need" and "desire" is significant. Similar
clarification is necessary with respect to the
meaning of "require,"95
since it can be interpreted to mean either a bona
fide need for treatment, or a demand by the
patient that may or may not reflect such a need.
V.6 The draft policy acknowledges that
"[p]ersonal beliefs and values and cultural and
religious practices are central to the lives of
physicians and patients." However, given what
follows, it is clear that this is merely a pro
forma observation that contributes nothing of
substance to the document.
V.7 Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights
Code states that physicians whose moral or
religious beliefs affect their practise of medicine
should "proceed cautiously." Added to this is a
warning that physicians who "restrict medical
services offered" on the basis of their
conscientious convictions may be prosecuted for
professional misconduct or violations of the Human Rights Code, and that, should that occur,
they will have "no defence." This must be read in
conjunction with the principal policy statement
concerning moral or religious beliefs:
. . . as a physician's
responsibility is to place the needs of the patient
first, there will be times when it may be necessary
for physicians to set aside their personal beliefs
in order to ensure that patients or potential
patients are provided with the medical treatment and
services they require.
V.8 Taken together, these statements indicate
that the exercise of fundamental freedoms of
conscience and religion by physicians is barely
tolerable, even indefensible, and that physicians
will sometimes be expected to do what they believe
to be wrong.
V.9 It is unclear whether this is meant as a
friendly warning or a veiled threat. In either case,
a free people grateful for hard-won liberties
bequeathed to them by the likes of John Foote and
Francis Scrimger will find it profoundly offensive
and demeaning.
V.10 For reasons explained in
Part IV, it is
unreasonable to suggest that a physician ought to
sacrifice his personal integrity by conforming to a
request or demand that he do something he believes
to be wrong. The suggestion is based upon an
erroneous understanding of the concept of sacrifice.
V.11 According to Physicians and the Ontario
Human Rights Code, "there is no hierarchy of
rights in the Charter; freedom of religion
and conscience, and equality rights are of equal
importance."96
V.12 In the relevant passage in the judgement
cited to support the statement, the court addressed
arguments from religious groups that to grant
persons of the same sex the legal right to 'marry'
would threaten their religious freedoms. The
intervening Interfaith Coalition had expressed
concern that "religions whose beliefs preclude the
recognition of same-sex marriage could find
themselves required to participate in such
marriages, or be discriminated against because of
their beliefs." The court, however, did not think
the concern was valid, because "there is no
hierarchical list of rights in the Charter,
and freedom of religion and conscience must live
together with s. 15 equality rights."
One cannot trump the other. .
. the equality rights of same-sex couples do not
displace the rights of religious groups to refuse to
solemnize same-sex marriages which do not accord
with their religious beliefs. Similarly, the rights
of religious groups to freely practise their
religion cannot oust the rights of same-sex couples
seeking equality, by insisting on maintaining the
barriers in the way of that equality.97
V.13 In the event of a collision between freedom
of conscience and religion and equality rights, it
is not clear how the issue can be adjudicated if
Canadian courts insist that there is "no hierarchy
of rights," except by applying the personal, social,
moral, philosophical or political views of the
adjudicator. In any case, the reference to the
non-hierarchical arrangement of Charter
rights does not support the view that physicians are
obliged to "set aside their personal beliefs" when
faced by demands that they provide services or
procedures to which they object for reasons of
conscience. If the passage has any relevance to the
exercise of freedom of conscience by physicians, it
is that it cannot be trumped by the kind of appeal
to equality rights that is being made by the OHRC.
V.14 According to Physicians and the Ontario
Human Rights Code, the "[f]reedom to exercise
genuine religious belief does not include the right
to interfere with the rights of others."98
V.15. The single sentence in the case to which
this statement refers appears a part of the
judgement that discusses the failure of the BC
College of Teachers to balance religious freedom
against other freedoms.
Students attending [Trinity
Western University] are free to adopt personal rules
of conduct based on their religious beliefs provided
they do not interfere with the rights of others.
Their freedom of religion is not accommodated if the
consequence of its exercise is the denial of the
right of full participation in society.99
V.16 In essence, the court was, in this part of
the judgement, reiterating the view that one Charter right cannot trump another, and that
restriction on the exercise of religious freedom of
teachers can only be justified by evidence that the
restriction is required to prevent some kind of
"detrimental impact on the school system.
V.17 The College draft statement contains two
significant words: "genuine" and "interfere." The
former does not appear in the judgement cited, and
it is not clear what purpose it serves in the
College document. The substantive meaning of the
statement turns entirely upon what constitutes
"interference."
V.18 The significance of the draft statement in
the present context is whether or not refusing to
participate in what one holds to be a wrongful act
can constitute "interference" with another's
"rights," and (considering the case cited) how this
could have a "detrimental impact"on the delivery of
health care.
V.19 Even if one believes that such a refusal
does constitute interference and does have some kind
of detrimental impact, one moves no further towards
a satisfactory resolution of the conflict. The
demand by a patient that a physician do what he
believes to be wrong can also be characterized as
"interference" with another's rights, and it can
also be said to have a "detrimental impact" on the
delivery of health care, since it can hardly be
maintained that medical ethics will be vastly
improved if the only physicians permitted to
practice are those willing to do what they believe
to be wrong.
V.20 Like the reference to the non-hierarchical
arrangement of rights in the Charter, the second
statement in the College draft document does not
support the view that physicians are obliged to "set
aside their personal beliefs" when faced by demands
that they provide services or procedures to which
they object for reasons of conscience.
V.21 According to Physicians and the Ontario
Human Rights Code, "the right to freedom of
religion is not unlimited, it is subject to such
limitations as are necessary to protect public
safety, order, health, morals or the fundamental
rights or freedoms of others."100
V.22 One of the cases cited to support the
statement concerns a teacher who, when not working,
was locally notorious for his virulently
anti-semitic public statements and writings that
were reasonably perceived to have poisoned the
school environment against Jewish students.
101 It is not clear what relevance
this case has to that of a physician who refuses to
participate in what he considers to be a wrongful
act, unless the College believes a physician who
refuses to do what he believes to be wrong is a
threat to public safety, order, health, morals or
the fundamental rights or freedoms of others.
V.23 The leading case cited is the origin of the
wording used in the draft statement. A Calgary drug
store was charged under the Lord's Day Act for
operating on Sunday. The Supreme Court of Canada
struck down the Act because its "acknowledged
purpose" was "the compulsion of religious
observance" and employed "a form of coercion
inimical to the spirit of the Charter," thus
offending its guarantee of freedom of religion and
conscience.102
V.24 The first point to note is that what the
College document puts forward as a case that
supports limitation of religious freedom was
actually about the importance of religious freedom
and the need to protect religious minorities in a
country "from the threat of 'the tyranny of the
majority.'" The principle has application in the
case of a physician threatened by the College or the
OHRC for refusing to do what he believes to be
wrong, but not in the way suggested by the draft
document.
V.25 The part of the judgement from which the
College draft policy was drawn deserves to be quoted
at somewhat greater length:
A free society is one which
aims at equality with respect to the enjoyment of
fundamental freedoms, and I say this without any
reliance upon s. 15 of the Charter. Freedom
must surely be founded in respect for the inherent
dignity and the inviolable rights of the human
person. . . .
. . . .One of the major
purposes of the Charter is to protect, within
reason, from compulsion or restraint. . . . Freedom
in a broad sense embraces both the absence of
coercion and constraint, and the right to manifest
beliefs and practices. Freedom means that, subject
to such limitations as are necessary to protect
public safety, order, health, or morals or the
fundamental rights and freedoms of others, no one is
to be forced to act in a way contrary to his beliefs
or his conscience.
V.26 In this passage, Mr. Justice Dickson was
emphasizing the importance of religious freedom, not
the importance of restricting or suppressing it.
Again, the College draft policy does not contribute
to the resolution of potential conflicts between a
physician and a patient who demands that he do
something he believes to be wrong.
V.27 According to Physicians and the Ontario
Human Rights Code, "courts will consider how
directly the act in question interferes with a core
religious belief;" and, further, "Courts will seek
to determine whether the act interferes with the
religious belief in a 'manner that is more than
trivial or insubstantial. The more indirect the
impact on a religious belief, the more likely courts
are to find that the freedom of religion should be
limited."103
V.28 Neither of the cases cited to support the
draft statement refers to or distinguishes between
direct and indirect impacts on religious belief.
Neither of the cases cited uses the term "core"
religious belief. In fact, the principal value of
the leading case cited is found in the Supreme
Court's affirmation that neither the state nor its
courts are qualified to "to interpret and determine
the content of a subjective understanding of a
religious requirement." It is open to the court only
"to inquire into the sincerity of a claimant's
belief, where sincerity is in fact at issue."104
The College statement thus implies a more
restrictive approach to religious belief than was
taken in either of the decisions.
V.29 The leading case cited resulted in a split
5-4 decision. Five judges found that infringement
had occurred and that it was not trivial or
insubstantial; three ruled there was no
infringement, except with respect to one of the
appellants, which they found to be legitimate; one
held that an infringement had occurred but was
justifiable in view of the rights of others. The
differing views of the judges and a ruling by the
bare majority suggests the unpredictable nature of
"rights-balancing" exercises that depend,
ultimately, on an adjudicator's subjective views
about the relative importance of religious belief
and other social concerns.
V.30 In the absence of any ordering principle,
the introduction of the terms "trivial" and
"insubstantial" does not shed any additional light
on the problem of balancing conflicting rights and
freedoms. Once more, the draft College statement
does not support the view that physicians are
obliged to "set aside their personal beliefs" when
faced by demands that they do something they believe
to be wrong.
Professional misconduct
V.31 The draft policy states that physicians must
provide information and advice to patients about all
available procedures, even if they conflict with
their moral or religious beliefs. The expectation
presumes either that the mere giving of information
or advice has no moral significance, or, if it does,
that it is inconsequential. This is not necessarily
the case.
V.32 This is demonstrated by the policies of the
AMA on physician participation in execution and
torture. The AMA prohibits physicians from rendering
technical advice or consulting with executioners or
"providing . . .knowledge to facilitate the practice
of torture." (See III.15-III.18)
It is also demonstrated by the policy of the College
of Physicians and Surgeons of British Columbia,
which forbids disclosure to the parents of the sex
of a child in utero. (See II.37) Finally, in 2002, the General Medical
Council in the United Kingdom suspended the license
of a physician for six months because he had
provided information about live donor organ
transplantation to undercover reporters and had thus
encouraged the trade in human organs,105
even though he had not actually participated in the
trade.
V.33 The difficulty here is to balance the desire
of a physician to avoid complicity in a wrongful act
with the importance of informed decision-making by
the patient, which requires that the patient have
all of the information relevant for the purpose of
choosing a course of treatment. It is necessary to
respect both the freedom of conscience of the
physician and the freedom and right of the patient
to make a fully informed choice.
V.34 One satisfactory compromise would see the
physician explain all legal options, including those
he finds morally objectionable, and disclose the
fact and reasons for his objections. In this way,
the patient obtains the information he requires to
make a fully informed choice, but the physician has
not compromised his own integrity by appearing to
recommend a procedure that he considers morally
objectionable. In such circumstances it is important
for the physician to convey his position in a manner
that does not provoke justifiable concern about
"preaching" or attempting to "convert" the patient
to his opinion. On the other hand, it is equally
important to avoid gratuitous accusations of
"preaching" or attempting to "convert" the patient
simply because the physician has made his own views
clear.
V.35 The requirement that a physician not express
personal judgements about the lifestyle of a patient
appears to preclude even discussion about smoking,
the need for a change of diet or an increase in
exercise. Health and lifestyle are usually related.
The wording of the policy should be revised to
reflect this.
V.36 The College should make clear that physician
will not be considered to be promoting his own
religious beliefs or seeking to convert patients
simply because he has complied with ethical
guidelines that require him to disclose views that
may influence his recommendations for treatment, or
because he has disclosed his views in circumstances
described in VI.34.
V.37 Similarly, a complaint should not lie
against a physician for expressing a judgement about
the patient by reason only that he has complied with
ethical guidelines that require him to disclose
views that may influence his recommendations for
treatment, or that he has disclosed his views in
circumstances described in V.34.
V.38 In support of its position, Physicians
and the Ontario Human Rights Code cites Personal
Beliefs and Medical Practice, a policy document
produced by Britain's General Medical Council.106
Paragraph 21 of that document asserts that an
objecting physician must provide a patient with
contact information for a colleague who will provide
the controversial procedure. It also directs the
reader to the relevant passage in an earlier
publication, Good Medical Practice (2006),which
advises physicians that if they have declined to
provide a procedure and advised a patient of his
right to see another doctor, they must "ensure that
arrangements are made for another suitably qualified
colleague to take over" if it is not practical for
the patient to do so.107
V.39 Physicians and the Ontario Human Rights
Code did not explain why it chose to refer to a
British policy document rather than Canadian
publications like the CMA approved Joint
Statement on Preventing and Resolving Ethical
Conflicts Involving Health Care Providers and
Persons Receiving Care.108
V.40 In any case, the GMC documents do not appear
to have taken into account evidence taken in 2004
and 2005 by the British House of Lords Select
Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill
and the conclusions of the Committee. The bill, in
its original form, included a requirement that
objecting physicians refer patients for euthanasia.
Numerous submissions protested this provision
because it made objecting physicians a moral party
to the procedure,109
and the Joint Committee on Human Rights concluded
that the demand was probably a violation of the European Convention on Human Rights.110
The bill's sponsor, Lord Joffe, promised to delete
the provision in his next draft of the bill.111
V.41 For the reasons set out in
Part III
and Part IV, the
requirement that an objecting physician facilitate
what he believes to be a wrongful act by referring a
patient or otherwise arranging for the provision of
the treatment is unacceptable.
VI. Looking to the future
VI.1 The principle that conscientious objectors
ought to be forced to refer for or otherwise
facilitate a morally controversial procedure would,
logically, apply to all controversial procedures. If
for no other reason than prudent self-interest,
physicians and other health care workers who are
inclined to support mandatory referral should think
carefully about the broader ramifications of such a
policy, especially if their own views would make
them unwilling to facilitate sex-selective abortion,
infant male circumcision, assisted suicide and
euthanasia or even the amputation of healthy body
parts.
VI.2 There is no reason to distinguish between
the amputation of healthy legs and the amputation of
healthy genitals. If a man can compel a surgeon to
alter his body to conform to his self-image or
understanding of himself as a female, there is no
principled reason why someone who sees himself as a
one-legged or one-armed person should not be able to
demand that a healthy leg or arm be amputated to
conform to his self-image, and at public expense.
According to the OHRC, to refuse to refer for
sex-change surgery or to perform the surgery would,
in the former case, invite prosecution for wrongful
discrimination on grounds of sexual 'orientation.'
Continuing to apply its logic, to refuse to perform
or refer for amputation would be wrongful
discrimination on grounds of disability (BIID).
VI.3 That one might be forced to refer for or
otherwise facilitate assisted suicide and euthanasia
is not a possibility that is commonly considered,
since the procedures are illegal in most
jurisdictions. But laws can be changed, as they have
been in the Netherlands, Belgium and Oregon, and
such changes in law bring with them changes in
expectations. Since late 2003, general practitioners
in Belgium unwilling to perform euthanasia have
faced demands that they help patients find
physicians willing to provide the service. It is
argued that mandatory referral for euthanasia is
required by respect for patient autonomy, the
paradigm of "shared decision making" and the fact
that euthanasia is a legal "treatment option."112
VII. Recommendations to the College
VII.1 The Ontario Human Rights Commission appears
to be of the opinion that it has the authority and
competence to restrict and suppress the exercise of
fundamental freedoms of conscience and religion in
the province Ontario. It demonstrates an alarming
enthusiasm for this project.
VII.2 On the other hand, the expertise of the
College of Physicians and Surgeons lies in the
practice of medicine. It is doubtful that the
College can contribute to an improvement in the
practice of medicine or enhance the enjoyment of
fundamental rights and freedoms in Ontario by
accepting a new and troublesome role as a surrogate
for the OHRC.
VII.3 The submissions of the OHRC to the College
also bring the Council face to face with the issue
of complicity. Members of the College Council must
ask to what extent they wish to be complicit in the
actions of the OHRC.
VII.4 Whether for reasons of conscience or
reasons of competence, or both, it is open to the
College Council to take the position that the
suppression of fundamental freedoms among physicians
in the province may be the task of the OHRC, but
that the OHRC must proceed without the assistance of
the College of Physicians and Surgeons. The Project
recommends this as a just and prudent response that
will not compromise the mandate or responsibilities
of the College.
Other Responses to Physicians and the Human
Rights Code
Organizations and institutions
Individuals
General
Benson, Iain
Budziszewski, J.
Manning, Preston
Murphy, Sean
Reynolds, Larry
Saunders, Peter
Prev | Next