Re: The Limits of Conscientious Refusal in Reproductive Medicine
ACOG Committee on Ethics Opinion No. 385: November, 2007
Attacking the conscience rights of their own
members
Ethics, Culture and Policy
Reproduced with permission
Paul Adams*
Like the National Association of Social Workers,
which released a
statement last May 2010 attacking the conscience
rights of its members and subordinating them to
client autonomy, the American College of
Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) has
reaffirmed its notorious 2007
Ethics Committee
position #385 on the limits of conscientious refusal
in reproductive medicine.
Odd that they persist in describing the killing
of unborn children as a part of "reproductive
medicine" since abortion seldom has anything to do
with treating illness, and is never about doing no
harm, or reproduction, and violates the Hippocratic
Oath!
In a forthcoming piece in the
Journal of Social Work Values
and Ethics, I conclude:
In the case of the life issues, the issue at stake is the fundamental moral
proscription on the intentional taking of innocent human life. This has been a
basic principle of ethics for millennia, an exceptionless norm which binds the
consciences of all in societies where the conscience is recognized at all. To
kill justly requires at least that the person is not innocent (as in capital
punishment or enemy soldiers in a just war); or is not a fully human person (as
has been argued in the case of Blacks, Jews, and unborn babies); or that killing
is not the intent but an unintended side effect (as with deaths of nearby
civilians from the bombing of a military target).
Of course, moral relativists, situationists, consequentialists, and ethical
emotivists may deny the existence or binding nature of such a proscription on
the killing of innocents. I will not take up here the objections to these
stances in moral philosophy, but simply note that if it is wrong to kill a
person, then it is also wrong to get someone else to do it. If it is, as I
believe, a grave evil for me to murder my spouse, it is no less wrong to hire
someone else to do it for me.
None of this has anything to do with imposing my views on the client, as
anti-exemptionists and militant secularists often claim. Patients and clients
have an uncontested moral right to informed consent and informed refusal. But
this is not the issue, as Pellegrino (2008) argues. The client may find abortion
morally permissible and it is certainly legally permissible in the United
States. I respect her right under law to decide to have an abortion and will not
condemn, moralize, or argue with her. But this is not the issue. "Conscientious
objection, " as Pellegrino (2008) says, "implies the physician's right not to
participate in what she thinks morally wrong, even if the patient demands it. It
does not presume the right to impose her will or conception of the good on the
patient" (p.299).