The President's Council on Bioethics
Thursday, September 11, 2008
Session 3: Conscience in the Practice of the Health Professions
Full Text
CHAIRMAN PELLEGRINO: Thank you very
much, Howard . Our third speaker is Dr. Farr Curlin .
Dr. Curlin.
DR. CURLIN: Thank you, Dr. Pellegrino , and I also would
like to say it's a great honor to have a chance to address the Council and
to be a part of this panel with my colleagues, although, as you'll see, I
will disagree with them on some important levels.
Let me begin with my observations as a physician and as one who has
observed the practices of other physicians. Physicians commonly refuse to
provide clinical interventions that patients request even when those
interventions are legal and permitted by the medical profession. These
refusals are neither new nor peripheral to clinical practice.
Physicians of course refuse interventions that they believe are
categorically unethical. In taking the Hippocratic Oath, physicians have for
centuries sworn to refuse to provide either abortifacients or any drug or
information that will be used to help kill patients. Physicians also refuse
practices that they believe are ethical in some cases but not in the case at
hand. For example, I believe it is ethically permissible to sedate dying
patients to the point of unconsciousness if the intended and direct effect
of the sedation is to relieve distressful symptoms that are refractory to
other treatments. Yet in my own practice of hospice and palliative medicine,
I sometimes disagree with patients, their families, or other health care
providers about whether we should increase the level of sedation in a
particular case.
Sometimes physicians refuse interventions that are the subject of
widespread public dispute, such as abortion or emergency contraception. More
often their refusals occasion little controversy. For example, surgeons
refuse to operate when they believe a surgery is unlikely to be successful
whether or not all of their colleagues agree. Physicians refuse requests for
antibiotics or other remedies even if the patient's symptoms satisfy some
threshold criteria for using these medications. Physicians may refuse
requested interventions because of tangible concerns about safety or
efficacy, or they may refuse because of concerns that are less tangible if
no less real. Some Catholic physicians refuse to provide contraceptive
medications because the Roman Catholic Church teaches that such medications
illicitly separate the procreative and unitive aspects of human sexuality.
More commonly, physicians' intangible concerns are not explicitly
religious. Some pediatricians refuse to provide growth hormone injections to
boys who are short because of concern about crossing a line between
treatment and enhancement. Internists and family physicians sometimes refuse
intensive work-ups and treatment regimens for what they believe are
psychosomatic syndromes, because they are concerned about being good
stewards of their colleagues' time and other medical resources.
Obstetrician-gynecologists who will abort fetuses with lethal congenital
anomalies may refuse to abort those with Down's Syndrome or cleft palate out
of concern about societal attitudes toward those with disability. Physicians
refuse patient requests even when patients are informed, even when threshold
medical criteria are met that would generally justify the intervention, and
even when physicians are aware that some of their colleagues would disagree
with their refusal.
So to say refusal[s] [are] conscientious is simply
to say that [they are] based on a physician's best judgment about what he or
she ought to do in a given case. . . they are . . . based on what physicians
believe are good reasons. In a morally pluralistic society, such reasons
will not be persuasive to all, but they will be intelligible and plausible.
So to say a refusal is conscientious is simply to say that it is based on
a physician's best judgment about what he or she ought to do in a given
case. In its recent opinion, the ethics committee of the American College of
Obstetricians and Gynecologists wrote that, "An appeal to conscience would
express a sentiment such as 'If I were to do X, I could not live with
myself. I would hate myself. I wouldn't be able to sleep at night.'"
Professor Brody mentioned a notion that my grandmother would turnover in her
grave if I did this.
I would suggest that conscientious refusals need not be so dramatic.
Rather, they are merely refusals based on what physicians believe are good
reasons. In a morally pluralistic society, such reasons will not be
persuasive to all, but they will be intelligible and plausible. And I should
note that in virtually every case of which I'm aware, people do give
reasons. I have not seen people, at least in public discourse, say "I can't
do this just because my conscience says so." Rather, they say "I can't do
that in good conscience because" and then what follows as a reason.
Now, critics sometimes suggest that health care professionals' stated
reasons for refusing particular interventions are specious and hide unspoken
prejudices. I was encouraged to hear Professor Brody note that we should
presume good faith about people's objections. In the essay that was in the
briefing booklet, Professor Brody and Susan Night say they "suspect that
what the conscientious pharmacist" who refuses emergency contraceptive pills
- what that pharmacist actually objects to but does not have the nerve to
say outright is the possibility that a woman can engage in sexual activity
without having to face the moral consequences of her potentially illicit
act.
Now, it goes without saying that physicians who act capriciously are not
acting conscientiously, yet the scare quotes around the terms conscientious
and moral suggest, I think, that the authors do not acknowledge or take
sufficiently seriously genuine moral disagreement about postcoital
contraception.
The conscience as a human faculty is both limited
and fallible. Yet, however fallible, conscientious refusals are, I think, a
logical and necessary consequence of physicians exercising discernment or
clinical judgment.
To say that conscientious refusals are central to the practice of
medicine is not to say that every conscientious refusal is justified. Father
Paris talked about that in some detail earlier. A conscience that is
malformed or misinformed will err. I'll give you a clinical example. A
conscientious physician may fail in his duties to relieve a patient's
debilitating pain because he has not been trained to pay close attention to
and work hard to address pain. Alternatively, he may fail because he
incorrectly interprets the patient's behavior as drug-seeking and
malingering. The conscience as a human faculty is both limited and fallible.
Yet, however fallible, conscientious refusals are, I think, a logical and
necessary consequence of physicians exercising discernment or clinical
judgment.
It has long been recognized that medical decisions cannot be reduced to
doing what patients want or even to clinical algorithms, rules of thumb, and
scientific data. This is in part because the application of medical science
always embodies and expresses normative ideas about the body and what it
means to be human, to flourish, and to fulfill our obligations to one
another. Science can neither provide these ideas nor settle disagreements
about them. In addition, even if there were agreement about these underlying
moral issues, physicians still must consider and weigh up innumerable
different factors, probably many of them unconsciously, in order to discern
how best to seek the health of a particular patient in a particular context,
all things considered.
This task is almost always attended by ambiguity and uncertainty, and it
requires what Aristotle called phronesis or practical wisdom, which
in the practice of medicine has been called good clinical judgment. If
physicians are to exercise clinical judgment in seeking their patient's
health, they will necessarily refuse some patient requests.
. . .with respect to the present controversies, it
cannot be that conscientious refusals per se are ethically problematic. What
we are after are criteria by which to distinguish those refusals that are
consistent with physicians' professional obligations from those that
contradict those obligations. To find such criteria, we have to figure out
what in fact physicians are obligated to do.
So, with respect to the present controversies, it cannot be that
conscientious refusals per se are ethically problematic. What we are after
are criteria by which to distinguish those refusals that are consistent with
physicians' professional obligations from those that contradict those
obligations. To find such criteria, we have to figure out what in fact
physicians are obligated to do.
We might start with the obligation, as Dr. Pellegrino put it at the end
of the morning session, the obligation that has been self-evident to people
from virtually every culture and moral tradition throughout the centuries;
namely, the obligation to care for the sick so as to preserve and restore
their health. The Hippocratic Oath states, "Into whatever houses I enter, I
will go into them for the benefit of the sick," and this universally
recognized obligation still provides a powerful criterion by which we can
discern that some refusals, however conscientious, are incompatible with
good medical practice.
For example, the physician who refuses to care for patients with HIV
because of antipathy towards homosexuals or for black patients because of
racial prejudice or for criminals because of revulsion at their crimes
thereby violates, in my understanding, his or her constitutive professional
obligations to seek the health of patients precisely because they are sick
without regard to their other characteristics. However, this obligation to
seek health does not provide a criterion by which to condemn the sorts of
conscientious refusals that have stirred contemporary controversies.
Rather, as biomedical science has expanded, it has made possible many
uses of medical technology that are not so obviously directed to preserving
and restoring health. Examples include terminal sedation, growth hormone for
short children - or, as we have learned, for professional athletes -
cosmetic surgery, most assisted reproductive technologies, elective
abortion, and others. Yet the paradigmatic example of such interventions and
the one that continues, not surprisingly, to animate disputes about
conscientious refusals, is contraception.
In 1979, twenty years after the FDA approved the first oral
contraceptive, Mark Siegler and Anne Dudley Goldblatt wrote the following:
"The oral contraceptive medication was the first prescription drug that was
and is, in effect, a self-prescribed treatment. Patients - i.e., medical
consumers desiring elective medication - demanded that physicians prescribe
the contraceptive pill. Other popularly self-prescribed medications soon
followed and came to be seen as appropriate solutions for treatments for
problems previously considered individual or social concerns, but in any
case not biological abnormalities or specific diseases."
It is not surprising that physicians became the purveyors of these
technologies. They had the scientific expertise and the legal authority to
manipulate the body. However, from the beginning many within the profession
have argued that physicians have no business pursuing ends other than
health, and despite the widespread use of these technologies some have
always refused to provide them. For a long time such refusals were
uncontroversial. The medical profession has traditionally given wide
latitude to physician discretion in areas of disagreement. Professional
codes have consistently stated that physicians are not obligated to satisfy
patients' requests for interventions that the physician does not believe are
in the interest of the patient's health. In this respect, and
notwithstanding claims to the contrary, physicians who refuse to provide
such technologies today are not claiming new freedom from old professional
obligations.
Physician refusals have become newly controversial, I would argue,
because the emergence of a new technology - in this case postcoital
contraceptives - has intensified an old concern about patients having access
to reproductive services. For better and worse, physicians do have exclusive
license to administer technologies by which millions of Americans have come
to order their lives - and, in all fairness, have come to order their lives
in a conscientious fashion. With respect to most of these technologies, if
one physician will not provide what a patient seeks, the patient can go to
another physician who will. The patient incurs relatively modest costs as a
result of the physician's refusal.
Postcoital contraception is different. It works only if administered
within a brief window of time. If a woman seeks emergency contraception
after intercourse and her physician refuses to prescribe it or her
pharmacist refuses to dispense it, she may get pregnant when she would not
have otherwise. In response to reports of such refusals, a chorus of
different writers has argued that doctors and pharmacists must provide or
facilitate access to all legal and professionally accepted medical
technologies, notwithstanding their moral objections.
Now, here I'm going to part ways with my colleagues here in that these
arguments lean heavily on a moral distinction and tension between the
personal and the professional. That's right in the title, for example, with
Professor Brody 's talk. Whether this tension is posed as personal moral
values versus professional ethical obligations or personal conscience versus
professional conscience or, in the case Professor Brody described, duties
related to personal versus professional integrity.
Health care professionals who refuse to provide what patients request,
the arguments go - or, to be fair, refer for or facilitate access to those
things at patients' request - thereby allow their personal considerations to
trump their professional obligations.
Unfortunately, this pitting of personal versus
professional tends to beg the relevant moral question, because unless and
until we can specify our professional obligations, we cannot know whether
they are being violated, nor can we know which obligations are merely
personal.
Unfortunately, this pitting of personal versus professional tends to beg
the relevant moral question, because unless and until we can specify our
professional obligations, we cannot know whether they are being violated,
nor can we know which obligations are merely personal.
In these debates, it seems to me, everything turns on how we define the
substance of our professional obligations, because at the heart of every
controversy about physician refusals lies a debate about what medicine is
for. As biomedical science generates technologies that people desire to use
that they highly value, questions are raised as to whether those uses are
really directed at health objectively defined. If not, then some argue for a
broadening of the concept of health to justify the use of the new technology
or they argue that physicians are obligated to pursue other goals in
addition to health.
In his 1975 essay "Regarding the End of Medicine and the Pursuit of
Health," Leon Kass noted, "It is ironic, but not accidental, that medicine's
great technical power should arrive in tandem with great confusion about the
standards and goals for guiding its use. When its powers were fewer, its
purpose was clearer." Several years later, the President's Commission for
the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral
Research - quite a mouthful; I'm glad that's been revised - echoed this
observation. Citing Siegler, the Commission wrote in 1982:
Judgments of conscientious persons have become
divergent and perplexed and societal consensus does not exist. No longer are
the proper ends and limits of health care commonly understood and broadly
accepted; a new concept of health care, characterized by changing
expectations and uncertain understanding between patient and practitioner,
is evolving. The need to find an appropriate balance of the rights and
responsibilities of patients and health care professionals in this time of
change has been called the critical challenge facing medicine in the coming
decades.
And if today's forum is any indication, it seems the challenge remains.
Those who frame conscientious refusals, I would
argue, as a conflict between personal values and professional obligations
thereby take one side in a debate they rarely acknowledge.
Those who frame conscientious refusals, I would argue, as a conflict
between personal values and professional obligations thereby take one side
in a debate they rarely acknowledge. For example, Chervenak and McCullough,
two very prominent ethicists in the area of obstetrics and gynecology, claim
that conscientious refusals violate physicians' duty to protect and promote
the health-related interests of patients. Professor Brody and Susan Night in
their essay in the booklet claim that pharmacists who refuse to make
arrangements for patients to receive emergency contraception violate their
professional duty to dispense medications that are, in the authors' terms,
medically indicated for the patients' condition. The ethics committee of the
American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists also criticizes those
who fail to provide medically indicated treatments. Unfortunately, these
claims beg the question they propose to answer, because they do not address
disagreements about whether the interventions in question are really
health-related. To put it another way, we cannot know whether something is
medically indicated unless we know what medicine is for, whether, for
example, the patients' condition is one which medicine properly treats.
In these critiques, if authors do not beg physicians' obligations, they
often assert obligations that are themselves highly disputed. For example,
Chervenak and McCullough criticize physicians who disclose the reasons for
their conscientious refusals to patients. They argue that such disclosures
violate an ethical consensus that physicians should be nondirective in their
counsel to patients. Yet, we can see that no such consensus exists by
turning to the paper on enhanced autonomy by Professor Brody and Timothy
Quill who there argue that physicians fail to use their power appropriately
when they withhold their guidance and that this failure reflects a
misunderstanding about the moral requirements of respecting patient
autonomy.
Now, the ACOG Ethics Committee opinion also interprets uncontroversial
physician commitments, I would argue, in novel and controversial ways. For
example, the Committee invokes respect for patient autonomy but without
explanation amplifies it to imply respect for the choices patients make and
a "fundamental duty to enable patients to make decisions for themselves."
Moreover, the Committee replaces the objective references for the concepts
of health and harm. It asserts that harm cannot merely be measured with
reference to bodily health but also with reference to "well-being as the
patient perceives it." It does not attempt to demonstrate that physicians
must provide particular interventions if they are to preserve and restore
patients' health. Rather, and in a telling use of language, the Committee
asserts that physicians are obligated to provide - and here again I'll quote
several of these phrases: "to provide reproductive technology..., health
resources..., professional services..., standard reproductive services that
patients request..., and safe and legal reproductive services..."
A comprehensive treatment of the merits and
weaknesses of each of these claims is beyond the scope of my comments. It's
perhaps enough to point out that there is even less consensus about these
purported physician obligations than there is about the controversial
practices which the physicians are refusing to provide.
A comprehensive treatment of the merits and weaknesses of each of these
claims is beyond the scope of my comments. It's perhaps enough to point out
that there is even less consensus about these purported physician
obligations than there is about the controversial practices which the
physicians are refusing to provide. Moreover, and I think more
problematically, these purported obligations depend on a provider-consumer
ideal for the doctor-patient relationship that has been widely criticized as
being insufficient for, and even corrosive of, the practice of medicine.
Siegler and Goldblatt drew the connection in 1979, warning that the
demanding patient presents a serious danger to clinical medicine. They
continued: "The demanding patient denies that the physician's
responsibilities and expertise have any relevance except insofar as this
coincides with the patient's desires. The demanding patient inverts the
traditional model and makes the physician a passive agent. The patient
proposes; the physician provides. The physician becomes a technician
practicing under the direction and control of his or her client."
In 1982, the President's Commission report titled Making Health Care
Decisions echoed Siegler and Goldblatt's concern, and over the ensuing
three decades a series of influential clinicians and ethicists who disagree
on a great many other substantive moral questions have agreed that the
pendulum has swung too far away from physician paternalism toward an
emphasis on patient autonomy that amounts to what the President's Commission
called "patient sovereignty."
In the patient sovereignty model, or what Quill and
Professor Brody called the independent choice model, the patient proposes,
the physician provides. The physician has effectively lost both moral agency
and responsibility. . . Arguments for reining in conscientious refusal
depend on this latter model being the right one.
In the paternalism model, the physician ordered, the patient obeyed.
After the patients' rights movement, the physician proposed, the patient
chose or gave consent. In the patient sovereignty model, or what Quill and
Professor Brody called the independent choice model, the patient proposes,
the physician provides. The physician has effectively lost both moral agency
and responsibility.
Arguments for reining in conscientious refusal depend on this latter
model being the right one. Only if the physician-patient relationship is one
of provider-consumer or technician-client can patients' legal right to seek
biomedical interventions imply that physicians have a professional
obligation to provide what patients seek. Only then can respect for autonomy
imply nondirective counseling and a fundamental duty to enable patients to
make decisions for themselves. Only then can informed consent be redefined
as informed choice. Only then can physicians' obligation to care for the
sick be exchanged for an obligation to provide health care services toward
the goal of maximizing well being as the patient perceives it.
Some would welcome the prospect of physicians answering to their patients
regarding what is good for them. After all, if these controversial
technologies are not directly related to restoring health, they are at least
medical commodities - health care services, to use the prevalent language -
and physicians have no particular expertise or standing to determine how
autonomous individuals put non health-related commodities use. An
independent choice model for the doctor-patient relationship would improve
access to these services while reducing patients' risk of surprise and
embarrassment. The model would bring simplicity, efficiency, choice and
control. If some physicians do not like providing these services, they can
quit or find another clinical specialty.
That is one option. We have a choice which will be made through all of
the instruments of politics.
My point here is that it is a consequential choice. The profession can
continue to ask its members to commit themselves to an objective goal,
namely health, that is not subject to wholesale revision. If this route is
taken, the profession must allow, from my understanding, conscientious
refusals where there is reasoned dispute about whether an intervention is
consistent with that goal. Or the profession may constrain the scope of
conscientious refusals and move toward a provider-consumer model in which
physicians' moral and clinical judgment is irrelevant to their task of
providing what patients lawfully seek. We cannot have it both ways.
. . .any policy that constrains the scope of
conscientious refusals thereby erodes the possibility of conscientious
practice.
And to close I'll describe three logical - I think logical, if unintended
- consequences of taking the latter route to argue that if we choose it we
may lose more than we gain. First, any policy that constrains the scope of
conscientious refusals thereby erodes the possibility of conscientious
practice. It seems obvious that patients want their physicians to be
conscientious insofar as possible. Few would respect or desire the care of
physicians who are in the habit of doing things they know to be unethical.
Fortunately, individuals from virtually all moral traditions and communities
can conscientiously and enthusiastically commit themselves to caring for the
sick. That is one reason why the profession of medicine has been able to
maintain both prestige and a semblance of unity in a society made up of many
different moral communities. Yet if physicians must be willing also to
participate in contraception and sterilization, those who believe what the
Roman Catholic Church has taught for centuries about the human body and
sexuality, and those who believe that physicians should aim at health and
nothing else, will no longer be able to practice conscientiously.
If physicians are required to refer patients to abortionists - to those
who provide abortions - when requested, those who believe that such referral
makes them complicit in a gravely immoral action will have to quit. And so
the process goes.
Every time the scope of conscientious refusal is narrowed, the pool of
people who can be conscientious physicians is reduced. Eventually, the only
ones left will be those who are willing to make all legal medical technology
available to be used by patients according to their own judgment.
. . . by requiring physicians to do what patients
request, we set physicians and patients at odds with one another.
Second, by requiring physicians to do what patients request, we set
physicians and patients at odds with one another. Professor Brody and
Timothy Quill argue that in the independent choice model, the physician as a
person with values and experience has become an impediment to rather than a
resource for decision making. I would add that the patient also becomes a
moral threat to the physician, particularly if restrictions on conscientious
refusals take on the force of professional or legislative policy. Physicians
will then wonder when their patients might, with the backing of legal
sanction, ask them to act against their own understanding and do that which
they believe is unethical.
Third, patients will lose the basis for trusting that their physicians
are committed to their good. Benjamin Franklin once said, "If we restrict
liberty to attain security we will lose them both." A similar dynamic is at
work with respect to the practice of medicine. If we restrict professional
autonomy and physician discretion to preserve patients' interests, we will
lose both. Why would that be?
Well, under the old model of paternalism, patients could trust that
physicians had committed themselves to the patients' best interests, albeit
in a limited way - only insofar as those interests included restoring and
preserving health. The patients' rights movement and the rise of the
doctrine of informed consent qualified and delimited physicians' commitment
to pursue health. Out of respect for persons, it was decided - I think
rightly - that physicians are to act only with the permission of the
patient. Because health is a relative and not an absolute good, patients are
authorized to relativize that good to other concerns such as not being
overburdened by medical technology. Yet within these limits, physicians
remain committed to health. In the enhanced autonomy model of Quill and
Brody, the deliberative model of Emanuel and Emanuel, and the physicians'
conscience model of David Thomasma , physicians are responsible for
thinking, using discernment, making judgments, providing counsel, and even
seeking to persuade patients to make the choice the physician believes is
best.
Patients gain technicians, it seems to me -
technicians who are committed to cooperation, and they lose healers
committed to health. They gain control over physicians, but thereby divest
physicians of responsibility. As a result, physicians can wash their hands
of patients' decisions so long as the physician gives accurate information
and provides technically proficient health care services.
Models that support constraining conscientious refusals differ in a
fundamental way. In them patients not only relativize the good of health to
other concerns but also define which goods physicians will seek. Patients
gain technicians, it seems to me - technicians who are committed to
cooperation, and they lose healers committed to health. They gain control
over physicians, but thereby divest physicians of responsibility. As a
result, physicians can wash their hands of patients' decisions so long as
the physician gives accurate information and provides technically proficient
health care services.
So one cannot merely constrain the scope of conscientious refusals and
leave all else the same. Policies that devalue conscientious practice and/or
make it more difficult reduce that which makes the practice of medicine its
own reward: the confidence and conviction that what one is doing is very
good. This morning Dr. McHugh described working long hours for little pay
and yet being very happy at it. Dr. Hurlbut described watching his father
spend a portion of each week caring for patients who could not pay for that
care and finding that work immensely rewarding and satisfying. If I remember
his comments correctly, Dr. Hurlbut you said it stirred in you a sense of
the nobility of the practice of medicine.
It seems to me that if physicians surrender their commitment to do only
that which they believe is good for their patients' health, they will also
surrender the nobility, joy, and other intrinsic rewards of medical
practice. Their morale will decline, and I would argue has already declined
precisely because the practice of medicine has been literally demoralized.
Where there is ambiguity or dispute about whether a
particular practice belongs in medicine, physicians and patients have a
respectful and candid discussion so that they can negotiate an accommodation
that does not require either to do what they believe is unethical.
There is a better way, I think, that has been iterated again and again by
the clinicians and ethicists that I have already mentioned. That way
involves conscientiousness and candor on the part of physicians. Where there
is ambiguity or dispute about whether a particular practice belongs in
medicine, physicians and patients have a respectful and candid discussion so
that they can negotiate an accommodation that does not require either to do
what they believe is unethical. In this model, physicians would not feign
moral neutrality but instead would tell their patients frankly what the
options are, which ones the physician is willing to provide, and why the
physician recommends one over another.
The scope of permissible accommodations will have to be set through the
political process. But I would echo the conclusion reached by the
President's Commission in 1982, which is that considerable flexibility
should be accorded to patients and professionals to define the terms of
their own relationships. This model would encourage policy accommodations
that provide reasonable access to controversial technologies without asking
physicians to provide interventions to which they object. For example,
before the FDA approved over-the-counter sales of postcoital contraceptives,
some states had bypassed the need for a cooperating physician by allowing
pharmacists to dispense the drug without a prescription. In a forthcoming
essay in Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, Armand Antommaria argues for
and provides numerous other examples of policy accommodations that promote
patients' interests and access to medical technologies without diminishing
physicians' interests in maintaining moral integrity.
. . . unless and until consensus is forged regarding
the ends of medicine, refusals of controversial practices cannot be shown to
violate physicians' professional obligations. In the meantime, the practice
of medicine should be open, I think, to anyone who is willing to
unreservedly commit herself to caring for the sick so as to preserve and
restore their health.
In conclusion, unless and until consensus is forged regarding the ends of
medicine, refusals of controversial practices cannot be shown to violate
physicians' professional obligations. In the meantime, the practice of
medicine should be open, I think, to anyone who is willing to unreservedly
commit herself to caring for the sick so as to preserve and restore their
health. In light of deep moral disagreements in our society about the scope
and limits of medicine, the profession should invite differences in practice
so long as physicians are candid about their practices so that patients can
effectively participate in medical decisions. Conscientiousness, when
accompanied by candor and respect, gives a limited ground for patients to
trust physicians as they work out accommodations in the face of genuine
disagreement about how to apply medical science toward the patient's good.
Thank you.
CHAIRMAN PELLEGRINO: Thank you very much, Dr. Curlin,
and thank you also to the other panelists for being so very, very punctual
and bringing us to the point of our break. We're going to break now and then
on return at 3:45 we will hear from Dr. Robby George, who will open the
discussion for the rest of the Council members. [. . .
R.P. George]
Notes
The
President's Council on Bioethics
was appointed by President George W. Bush and operated from 2001 to 2009.
Source: Archived transcript of the session.