Submission to the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Alberta
Re: Informed Consent (Draft)
28 October, 2015
Full Text
Abstract
The Project finds the proposed policy on conscientious objection generally
satisfactory. Pursuant to Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care,
it distinguishes between providing information (required) and facilitating
access to morally contested procedure (not required). This preserves physician
freedom of conscience and religion without interfering with patient access to
services. The wisdom of this approach has become particularly obvious since the
Carter ruling.
It is also clear that refusal according to the terms of the policy does not
constitute abandonment, which is entirely satisfactory. The policy prudently
puts physicians in the position of responding to patient requests for euthanasia
or assisted suicide rather than requiring the procedures to be presented as
options.
The claim that the provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide is a
Charter right is excessive. The ruling provides physicians with an
exemption from prosecution for murder and assisted suicide in the specific
circumstances contemplated in the judgement. It does not require the state or
"the medical profession as a whole" to provide these services.
The policy limits the role of physicians to establishing the existence of an
irremediable medical condition, leaving the patient to decide all questions
related to the existence and nature of suffering. It envisages the provision of
euthanasia and assisted suicide address suffering caused by "depression" or a "psychiatric or psychological disorder." These
provisions illustrate the importance of
particularly robust protection of conscience policies and laws.
This submission makes recommendations concerning three issues not addressed
by the policy that have implications for physician freedom of conscience.
The first is the possibility of failed euthanasia/assisted suicide attempts
that incapacitate a patient. This also raises questions about a physician's
contractual responsibility and criminal liability with respect to killing an
incompetent patient.
The second is the possibility that unexpected deterioration in a patient's
condition may occur before a scheduled euthanasia or assisted suicide procedure.
In the absence of the responsible physician, this may precipitate demands that
objecting physicians or health care workers kill the patient.
The third is the possibility of discrimination against medical school
applicants, medical students and physicians who refuse to provide or facilitate
euthanasia for reasons of conscience.
In addition, this submission recommends that demeaning statements directed at
objecting physicians should be deleted or moved to the general section on
informed consent and made applicable to all physicians in all circumstances. In
addition, the terms "legally permissible" and "publicly-funded" should be
deleted because they are gratuitous as well as misleading.
III.3 Statement (1):
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care
III.4 Statement (2):
Providing information
III.5 Statement (3):
Arranging access OR offering information
III.6 Abandonment
III.7 Demeaning
statements
III.8 Discrimination
against objecting physicians, medical school applicants and students
IV.1 Rights claim
IV.2 "legally
permissible and publicly funded health services"
V.1 Suffering
V.2 Euthanasia/assisted
suicide for chronic depression, psychiatric or psychological disorders
VI.1 Introduction
VI.2 Willingness of
physicians to provide assisted suicide vs. euthanasia
1) Discrimination
2) Obligations of responsible physicians
I. Introduction
I.1 The Protection of Conscience Project is a non-profit, non-denominational initiative that
advocates for freedom of conscience among health care workers. It does not take a
position on the acceptability of morally contested procedures. Comments and
recommendations concerning the draft standard of practice
Informed Consent
(including
Appendix "A" - The Special Case of Physician Assisted Dying)
are limited to issues directly or indirectly related to the protection of
physician freedom of conscience.
II. Outline of this submission
II.1 The Project finds the proposed policy on conscientious objection generally satisfactory,
while taking issue with demeaning statements directed at objecting physicians (Part III).
II.2 The Project takes issue with the claim of rights advanced in the document and its
references to public funding (Part IV).
II.3 Observations are made concerning the documents treatment of the
Carter criterion of
suffering, and the inclusion of chronic depression as grounds for euthanasia and assisted
suicide (Part V).
II.4 Observations are also made with respect to the practical and possible legal consequences
of failed euthanasia/assisted suicide procedures (Part VI).
II.5 The need to take additional steps to ensure freedom of conscience for objecting
physicians and health care workers in urgent situations is discussed in
Part VII.
II.6 A number of recommendations are made concerning the obligations of physicians who
provide euthanasia and assisted suicide (Part VIII). The recommendations are intended to
minimize the likelihood of conflicts of conscience among other physicians and health
care workers.
III. Conscientious objection
III.1 From the Project perspective, the critical parts of the policy are the following statements,
numbered here for ease of reference in this submission:
1) Physicians may decline to provide PAD if doing so would violate their
freedom of conscience, as per the CPSA standard of practice Moral or Religious
Beliefs Affecting Medical Care.
2) The physician is expected to provide sufficient information and resources to
enable the patient to make his/her own informed choice and access all options for
care, even if providing such information conflicts with the physicians deeply held
and considered moral or religious beliefs.
3) This means arranging timely access to another physician or resource or offering
the patient information and advice about all medical options available.
III.2 These statements are supplemented by a decision flow chart:
III.3 Statement (1):
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care
III.3.1 The reference to
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care in statement (1) is
important. The key provision in that document states:
When moral or religious beliefs prevent a physician from providing or offering
access to information about a legally available medical or surgical treatment or
service, that physician must ensure that the patient who seeks such advice or
medical care is offered timely access to another physician or resource that will
provide accurate information about all available medical options.
1
III.3.2 This document originated in the revision of CPSA
Standards of Practice in 2008. The
original draft Standards included a section concerning the termination of pregnancy. The
Registrar of the College stated:
Most respondents take exception with the draft, believing that the College will
require physicians to refer patients for termination of pregnancy, or at the very
least to be compliant in arranging a patients abortion, contrary to the physicians
personal beliefs. This is not true. . . .
. . . The Colleges current policy (in place for the past decade) states:
While recognizing the varied personal convictions of physicians it
must still be the responsibility of physicians to ensure that pregnant
women who come to them for medical care are provided with or are
offered access to information or assistance to enable them to make
informed decisions on all available options for their pregnancies
including termination.
The points I wish to make are these: A Standard of Practice on this subject will
not
change the obligations of physicians that have been accepted by this College since
1991. The words are a little different, but the intent is not, as the principles underlying
the standard have not changed over the past 20 years. (Emphasis in the original)
2
III.3.3 The section concerning termination of pregnancy was deleted from the final version of
the Standards and the policy Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care
adopted.
The development and wording of the policy make clear that it is intended
to ensure that a
patient has all of the information necessary to make an informed decision about treatment
options. It does not imply that objecting physicians have a duty to facilitate morally
contested procedures like abortion or contraception by referral or other means.
III.3.4 Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care
effectively distinguishes between
providing information necessary for medical decision-making (required) and facilitating
access to morally contested procedure (not required). This
preserves physician freedom
of conscience and religion, but it does not interfere with patient access to services. This
is demonstrated by the fact that there is no evidence that anyone in the province of
Alberta has ever been unable to access health care as a result of conscientious objection
by a physician.
III.3.5 The wisdom of the approach taken in
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care
has become particularly obvious since the
Carter ruling.
III.4 Statement (2): Providing information
III.4.1 In the Projects experience, physicians who object to a procedure or service do not
normally object to providing the kind of information required in statement (2),
particularly in response to a patient request.
III.4.2 The draft policy does not impose a requirement that physicians offer patients the options
of euthanasia or assisted suicide. This is prudent, for two reasons.
III.4.3 First: even physicians willing to provide or refer for the procedures might sometimes
consider it harmful or even abusive to offer them as options: the case of a patient just
blinded or paralysed by an industrial accident comes to mind.
III.4.4 Second: the
Carter decision did not strike down the law against counselling suicide
[241(a) Criminal Code], so the gratuitous suggestion of physician assisted suicide even to
patient who meets the Carter criteria may expose physicians to criminal prosecution.
III.5 Statement (3): Arranging access OR offering information
III.5.1 The options offered in statement (3), supplemented by the explanatory flow chart, are
consistent with the approach taken in
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical Care.
Physicians who object to euthanasia or assisted suicide for reasons of conscience are
obliged to facilitate the exercise of informed medical decision making, but they are not
obliged to facilitate the procedures. This is entirely satisfactory.
III.6 Abandonment
III.6.1 The draft document states that a physician who declines to provide euthanasia or assisted
suicide for reasons of conscience must not abandon a patient who makes this request.
Activists often attempt to coerce physicians who refuse to provide or facilitate a service
or treatment for reasons of conscience by accusing them of patient abandonment.
However, it is clear that refusal according to the terms of the policy does not constitute
abandonment. This is entirely satisfactory.
III.7 Demeaning statements
III.7.1 The draft document states that a physician who declines to provide euthanasia or assisted
suicide for reasons of conscience must treat the patient with dignity and respect. This is
a salutary reminder, but the draft document goes further:
Physicians must not provide false, misleading, intentionally confusing, coercive or
materially incomplete information, and the physicians communication and
behaviour must not be demeaning to the patient or to the patients beliefs, lifestyle
choices or values.
III.7.2 This additional paragraph implies that physicians who act in accordance with their moral
convictions by refusing to do something they believe to be wrong are likely to lie or
deceive patients or denigrate them. The statement arguably demeans such physicians or
their beliefs, lifestyle choices or values.
III.7.3 The tone of the paragraph reflects its origin. It has been taken almost
verbatim, without
attribution, from a proposed policy drafted by the Conscience Research Group (CRG).3
This group intends to compel physicians and other health care workers to do what they
believe to be wrong, such as facilitating euthanasia. Most of the principles enunciated in
the draft document have also been copied from the CRGs proposed policy. One of the
authors of the CRGs proposed policy, Professor Jocelyn Downie, is a member of the
Provincial/Territorial Expert Advisory Group on Physician-Assisted Dying.
III.7.4 If College Council believes, nonetheless, that the paragraph is appropriate, it should be
moved to the general section on informed consent and applied to all physicians with
respect to all consent discussions with patients about all procedures, since
all physicians
act in accordance with their moral convictions, including those who provide
morally
contested procedures. Its presence in the section on conscientious objection gives the
appearance of unacceptable prejudice, particularly against religious believers.
III.7.5 Even if the paragraph is moved to the general section on informed consent, some caveats
are in order.
III.7.6 Objecting physicians or health care workers who are explaining their own position to
patients may make statements to the effect that they do not consider euthanasia and
assisted suicide to be forms of medical treatment or palliative care. In the course of such
conversations, they may also ethically distinguish between withdrawal/refusal of
treatment and killing patients or helping them to kill themselves. Euthanasia/assisted
suicide activists may take exception to statements or explanations of this kind, calling
them false, misleading, intentionally confusing, coercive. Such complaints must be
dismissed as unacceptable attempts to suppress contrary views.
III.7.7 It is reasonable to believe that the communication of an objecting physicians position
will cause patients to infer (correctly) the beliefs of the physician concerning euthanasia
and assisted suicide. Patients may thus believe that the physician is 'demeaning their
beliefs, lifestyle choices or values, even if the physicians views pertain to the morality
of the procedures rather than the personal culpability of the patient. The policy should
not be used to punish objecting physicians simply because a patient has been upset by the
expression of views contrary to his own.
III.8 Discrimination against objecting physicians, medical school applicants and students
III.8.1 The policy does not address the issue of discrimination against medical school applicants,
medical students and physicians who refuse to provide or facilitate euthanasia for reasons
of conscience.
IV. Rights claim, public funding
IV.1 Rights claim
IV.1.1 The draft document states that the
Carter ruling establishes physician-assisted death
(PAD) as a Charter right.
IV.1.2 This claim is excessive. The ruling provides physicians with an exemption from
prosecution for murder and assisted suicide in the specific circumstances contemplated in
the judgement. It prevents the state from prohibiting assisted suicide or euthanasia in
such circumstances, but it does not require the state or the medical profession as a
whole to provide these services. The text of the ruling states, "nothing
in the declaration of invalidity which we propose to issue would compel
physicians to provide assistance in dying." (Emphasis added). This
indicates that striking down the criminal prohibition did not, in the Court’s
view, create any obligation on the part of physicians (individually or
collectively) to provide assisted suicide or euthanasia, although individuals or
groups might undertake to do so voluntarily.
IV.1.3 The text of the ruling states, "nothing in the
declaration of invalidity which we propose to issue would compel
physicians to provide assistance in dying." (Emphasis added) The Court
here referred to "physicians" (plural), not "a physician"(singular). This
suggests that striking down the criminal prohibition did not, in the Court’s
view, create any obligation on the part of physicians (individually or
collectively) to provide assisted suicide or euthanasia, although
individuals or groups might undertake to do so voluntarily.
IV.1.4 Unlike the Supreme Court's 1988
Morgentaler decision, which struck down the abortion
law entirely, the Carter decision did not invalidate murder and assisted suicide laws
altogether, but only to the extent that the laws prevent homicide and assisted suicide by
physicians in accordance with the guidelines laid down by the Court.
IV.1.5 Thus, a physician accused of failing to follow the
Carter guidelines is still liable to be
charged for murder or assisted suicide, just as, prior to 1969, physicians who provided an
abortion under guidelines based on the case of R. v. Bourne
4 were liable to be charged if
the abortion was not necessary to preserve the life of the mother.
5
IV.2 "legally permissible and publicly funded
health services"
IV.2.1 The principles concerning the Colleges advice on physician assisted suicide and
euthanasia include the following:
The medical profession as a whole has an obligation to ensure people have access
to the legally permissible and publicly-funded health services. (Emphasis added)
Physicians have an obligation not to interfere with or obstruct the publics access
to legally permissible and publicly-funded health services. (Emphasis added)
IV.2.2 These statements were taken almost
verbatim, without attribution, from the policy
proposed by the CRG (III.7.3).
6
IV.2.3 Neither individual physicians nor the medical profession as a whole have an obligation to
ensure that people have access to illegal health services. Any actual obligation can refer
only to legal services.
IV.2.4 Many kinds of elective surgery are
not publicly funded. Diabetic supplies like insulin
needles or pumps may not be publicly funded or may be publicly funded only after
payment of an annual deductible. The fact that a health service is or is not
"publicly-funded" has nothing to do with whether or not individual physicians or the
medical profession as a whole have an obligation to ensure that people have access to it.
IV.2.5 Physicians may not interfere with or obstruct a patient's right to access legally permissible
services whether or not they are health services and whether or not
they are publicly
funded.
IV.2.6 "Public funding" provides a benefit for a patient, but it confers no privileged status on a
procedure, nor does "public funding" establish definitively that a procedure is morally or
ethically acceptable, any more than "public funding" can establish that a war is justified.
IV.2.7 The descriptors "legally permissible" and "publicly-funded" are intended in the CRG
policy to provide a rhetorical pretext for the suppression of freedom of conscience. Since
the Colleges draft document is not intended to suppress freedom of conscience, the terms
legally permissible and publicly-funded should be deleted because they are gratuitous
as well as misleading.
V. Suffering, depression and euthanasia/assisted suicide
V.1 Suffering
V.1.1 One of the requirements for exemption from criminal prosecution under the terms of the
Carter ruling is that the patient be experiencing suffering that is intolerable to the
individual.
V.1.2 Intolerable suffering is an entirely subjective phenomenon. With respect to those
opposed to assisted suicide and euthanasia, Joseph Arvay, counsel for the appellants, told
the Supreme Court of Canada that "it is wrong, indeed, it is arrogant . . . to impose their
views of what suffering is acceptable and tolerable for others, because suffering is a very
personal, subjective and contextual concept."
For some, the suffering will be purely physical, as a result of their medical
condition. For others, it will be a combination of physical, psychological,
psychosocial, which may be a function of both their medical condition and their
own sense of what it means to lead a dignified life.
7
V.1.3 In view of this and the text of the ruling, it was
to be expected that evaluation of suffering would be problematic, and that
establishing the de facto existence of intolerable suffering as a legal
criterion for providing assisted suicide and euthanasia would ultimately prove
to be impossible. This may be why the policy limits the role of physicians to
establishing the existence of an irremediable medical condition, leaving the
patient to decide all questions related to the existence and nature of
suffering.
V.1.4 In doing so, however, the policy sets one of the
legal criteria that physicians must ensure are met outside the purview of
physicians, despite the fact that the Supreme Court made the existence of
intolerable suffering one of the criterion that must be met to qualify for
exemption from prosecution for murder and assisted suicide.
V.1.5 It would thus not be unreasonable for physicians
to insist that they must somehow be satisfied that a patient is experiencing
intolerable suffering, particularly since, if a physician were charged for
murder, the patient would not be available to testify. This applies equally
to physicians who object to the procedures and those who do not. How this
might be consistently done is an open question.
V.2 Euthanasia/assisted suicide for chronic depression,
psychiatric or psychological disorders
V.2.1 The policy envisages the provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide to put an end to
suffering caused by depression or a psychiatric or psychological disorder, on the
condition that physicians establish that the depression or disorder is not causing
impaired judgement.
V.2.2 This is consistent with an exchange between Mr. Justice Lebel and Mr. Arvay during the
Supreme Court hearing emphasized that "suffering" could be either physical or
psychological:
Lebel: And your test is, essentially, about someone who is undergoing intense
suffering . . .
Arvay: Yes.
Lebel: Psychological or physical. . .
Arvay: Yes. And there is no dispute in the record, by the way. Dr. Chochinov, who
was one of Canadas main witnesses, was very strong about how horrible
psychological suffering is and equal to if not exceeds physical suffering.
8
V.2.3 The policy permits euthanasia and assisted suicide in such cases if an additional
assessment confirms that the illness itself does not impair the patients ability to make
and informed and reasoned decision. Thus, the College appears to have adopted the
position laid before the Supreme Court by Sheila Tucker, the appellants co-counsel, who
stated that the evidence indicated that someone who has "major depressive disorder"
(clinical depression) can "still be competent as a medical decision maker."
What the further question was, if you are to make the further judgement about
whether or not, even though youre competent, the major depressive disorder is
influencing your decision about wanting to end your life, that thats a very fine
judgement. And so, the recommended answer to her from the witness, and which
she agreed with, was, its too fine of a judgement. Simply exclude people who are
actively suffering from major depressive disorder. . . because you cannot rely on
their decision. . . But thats a very high threshold . . . of major depressive disorder,
and she also said, because its expressed in the context of actively suffering. She
said such people should be treated, with a course of medication for major
depressive disorder, and if they could recover enough to reliably make the
decision because they werent actively suffering it to the same degree, then they
should be allowed to make the decision.
9
V.2.4 On the other hand, the Court remarked, in passing,
that the parameters they would propose would not apply to "persons with
psychiatric disorders." (para. 111) The parameters actually laid out do
not explicitly exclude mental illness, so, on this point, the ruling is
ambiguous. It appears from the text of the draft policy that the College has
elected to resolve the ambiguity in favour of providing euthanasia and assisted
suicide for the mentally ill.
V.2.5 The broader the criteria for assisted suicide and euthanasia, the greater the likelihood of
conflicts of conscience among physicians and health care workers. Killing patients or
helping them commit suicide because they are suffering from depression or psychiatric or
psychological disorders is particularly contentious. Among physicians
responding to a Canadian Medical Association survey after the Carter ruling,
while 29% indicated that they were willing to "consider" providing either
assisted suicide or euthanasia (the question did not distinguish between
them), the number dropped to about 6% when the reason for doing so was
"purely psychological suffering."10
V.3 Summary
V.3.1 The policy provisions concerning suffering and
euthanasia and assisted suicide for depression or psychological or
psychiatric disorders underscores the importance of maintaining robust
protection of conscience policies and laws for physicians and other health
care workers.
VI. Failed assisted suicide and euthanasia
VI.1 Introduction
VI.1.1 According to the draft, the patient must be informed of the risks of taking the prescribed
medication and the probable outcome/result of taking the medication. It is not clear
that this includes discussion about the possibility that the drugs may not kill the patient.
VI.1.2 Euthanasia and assisted suicide drugs do not always cause death as expected.
11 It is for
this reason that Quebec euthanasia kits are to include two courses of medication.
12
VI.1.3 Discussion with patients should include discussion of options available in the event that a
lethal injection or prescribed drug does not kill the patient, and the patient should be
asked to provide direction on this point.
VI.1.4 As will be seen presently, this issue has
implications for the advice given in the draft document, and it also appears to
have legal implications with respect to a physician's criminal responsibility
and is related to protection of physician freedom of conscience.
VI.2 Willingness of physicians to provide assisted suicide vs. euthanasia
VI.2.1 A 2014 survey of Canadian Medical Association members indicated that more physicians
were willing to participate in assisted suicide (27%) than euthanasia (20%).
13,
14,
15,
16
VI.2.2 However, a physician who agrees to help a patient commit suicide would seem to have
accepted an obligation to do something that will result in the patients death, and to do it
according to accepted standards. This obligation seems implicit in the agreement.
VI.2.3 In the case of a failed physician-assisted suicide that incapacitates a patient, it is likely
that the responsible physician will be expected to fulfil his commitment to help bring
about the death of the patient by providing a lethal injection or finding someone willing to
do so. The expectation would be stronger if the patient had sought assisted suicide to
avoid the kind of incapacitation caused by the failed suicide attempt.
VI.2.4 Here the issue of physicians willing to assist in suicide but unwilling to provide
euthanasia becomes acute. Those willing to assist with suicide but not euthanasia may be
reluctant or unwilling to ask another colleague to kill the patient. Moreover, the
Carter
ruling limits the provision of euthanasia to competent patients. Thus, to ask physicians to
kill a patient who has been rendered incompetent by a colleagues failed attempt would
seem to expose them to prosecution for first degree murder or, at least, assisted suicide.
VI.2.5 In addition, the draft document appears to rule out
euthanasia if a patient is incapacitated but not killed by an assisted suicide
or euthanasia attempt.
9. Ongoing capacity
A patient must maintain mental capacity for PAD to
proceed. If at any time during the progression of the patient's condition, the
patient loses the mental capacity to rescind his/her decision, PAD ceases to be
an option.
VII. Urgent situations
VII.1 Some authorities have stated that a physicians obligation to provide treatment urgently
needed to prevent imminent harm to patients does not extend to providing assisted suicide
or euthanasia.17 This presumes that, since the procedures require extensive preliminary
consultation and preparation before they can be authorized, they can never be urgently
required. The silence of the draft document on this point suggests a similar presumption
in Alberta.
VII.2 That presumption is challenged by testimony taken by the Quebec legislative committee
studying what later became the provinces euthanasia law (An Act Respecting End of Life
Care). Representatives of the College of Pharmacists of Quebec agreed that the provision
of euthanasia would not seem to involve the same urgency as other kinds of procedures,
and that arrangements could normally be made to accommodate conscientious objection
by pharmacists because the decision could be anticipated.18 However, they also stated
that situations may evolve more quickly than expected, and that (for example) palliative
sedation might be urgently requested as a result of respiratory distress precipitated by
sudden bleeding.
19
VII.3 The pharmacist representatives distinguished between making a decision that euthanasia
or assisted suicide should be provided - a decision which might take days or weeks - and
a decision that a drug should be urgently provided to deal with an unanticipated and
critical development in a patients condition.
20
VII.4 Under the terms of the
Carter ruling and the draft document, it is possible that a
responsible physician might agree to provide euthanasia or assisted suicide on a given
date and time, to accommodate (for example) the desire of geographically distant family
members to be present at the patients death. Between the time that decision is made and
the appointed time, however, a sudden deterioration of the patients condition may cause
him to ask for immediate relief from pain or suffering by euthanasia or assisted suicide.
VII.5 No problem will arise if the responsible physician is immediately available to fulfil the
request. However, there is likely to be a problem if the responsible physician is absent or
unavailable, and other physicians willing to kill the patient or assist in suicide cannot be
conveniently found. This situation is more likely to arise if the originally appointed time
for euthanasia/assisted suicide is some days later than the decision to provide the
procedure.
VIII. Recommendations
VIII.1 The section of the policy dealing with conscientious objection is satisfactory with respect
to the expectation that objecting physicians will provide patients with sufficient
information to permit informed medical decision making, while making it clear that they
are not obliged to facilitate euthanasia or assisted suicide. It does not, however, address
the issue of discrimination against medical school applicants, medical students and
physicians who refuse to provide or facilitate euthanasia for reasons of conscience.
VIII.2 The issues raised in Parts IV and
V suggest that it is important to ensure robust protection
of conscience provisions in policy and law.
VIII.3 Part VI and VII demonstrate a need to include in the policy some additional guidance in
order to avoid conflicts of conscience and concerns about criminal responsibility in
particularly difficult circumstances, and to avoid conflicts of conscience among health
care workers who may be involved in other aspects of the care or treatment of a patient.
VIII.4 The following recommendations address these concerns. To avoid ambiguity, the term
"responsible physician" is used in this part to mean a physician who has agreed to assist
with the patients suicide or provide euthanasia, distinct from (for example) a family
physician who has declined to do so, but who continues to be responsible for other
aspects of patient care in accordance with section 14 of the draft document
(Conscientious objection).
1) Discrimination
No discrimination should be directed against applicants for medical school or
doctors who do not perform, assist with or facilitate euthanasia or assisted suicide.
Respect for freedom of conscience in this area must be stressed, particularly for
doctors training in general practice, palliative care and anesthesia.
2) Obligations of responsible physicians
a) Physicians should not undertake to provide assisted suicide unless they are also
willing to provide euthanasia.
b) In all cases, the responsible physician should, as
part of the informed consent discussion preliminary to decision making, advise
the patient of the possibility that the drugs might not cause death and discuss
the options available.
c) Immediately prior to
administering or providing the lethal medication, the responsible physician
should obtain written direction from the
patient as to what action should be taken if the prescribed or administered drugs
fail to cause death. (NB. In the case of patients incapacitated by failed
euthanasia/assisted suicide, it is not known if this would be legally sufficient to
invoke the exemption from prosecution provided by Carter.)
d) The responsible physician should personally administer the lethal drug or be
personally present when it is ingested, and remain with the patient until death ensues.
e) A responsible physician who has agreed to provide euthanasia or assisted
suicide must be continuously available to do so from the time the agreement is
made to the time that the procedure is performed, unless the patient withdraws the
request.
f) A responsible physician who has agreed to provide euthanasia or assisted
suicide must also arrange for a second responsible physician to provide the
procedure in the event that he is unable to be continuously present or is unable to
act.
g) The second responsible physician must be continuously available to act in the
place of the primary responsible physician.
Notes
1. College of Physicians and
Surgeons of Alberta,
Moral or Religious Beliefs Affecting Medical
Care.
(Accessed 2015-10-20)
2. "Registrars Report: Draft standard for termination of pregnancy." The Messenger, April,
2009, p. 3 (Accessed 2015-02-12)
3. Compare: "Physicians must not provide false, misleading, intentionally confusing, coercive,
or materially incomplete information to their patients" (College draft document) and ". . . physicians must not
communicate or otherwise behave in a manner that is demeaning to the patient or to the patients
beliefs, lifestyle, choices, or values." (Downie J. McLeod C. Shaw J. "Moving Forward with a
Clear Conscience: A Model Conscientious Objection Policy for Canadian Colleges of Physicians
and Surgeons." Health Law Review, 21:3, 2013) (hereinafter Downie et al)
(Accessed 2015-02-24).
4. R. v. Bourne (1939) 1KB 687
5. This was one of the reasons offered by the Canadian Medical Association for its
recommendation to legalize abortion. "'We don't like being lawbreakers,' Dr. Aitken told the
committee in partial explanation of the C.M.A's motivation in supporting the move to expunge
the Criminal Code's prohibition of abortion. Dr. Gray commented that while he knew of no
doctor having been prosecuted for performing an abortion openly in a hospital, there was still the
uncertainty about transgression of the law. Dr. Cannell reported there were 262 therapeutic
abortions performed in Canadian hospitals between 1954 and 1965." Waring G. "Report from
Ottawa." CMAJ Nov. 11, 1967, vol. 97, 1233
6. Compare: "The Canadian medical profession as a whole has an obligation to ensure that
people have access to the provision of legally permissible and publicly funded health services"
(College draft document) and, "Physicians have an obligation not to interfere with or obstruct peoples access to legally
permissible and publicly funded health services." (Downie et al)
7. Supreme Court of Canada, 35591, Lee Carter, et al. v. Attorney General of Canada, et
al.(British Columbia) (Civil) (By Leave)
Webcast of the Hearing on 2014-10-15:
Oral submission of Joseph Arvay (hereinafter "Arvay"), 76:17/491:20 to 77:13/491:20
(Accessed 2015-10-28).
8.
Arvay, 90:09/491:20 to 90:38/491:20
9. Supreme Court of Canada, 35591, Lee Carter, et al. v. Attorney General of Canada, et
al.(British Columbia) (Civil) (By Leave)
Webcast of the Hearing on 2014-10-15:
Oral submission of Sheila M. Tucker, 144:35/491:20 to 145:59/491:20
(Accessed 2015-10-28)
10. Canadian Medical Association Annual General
Council 2015, Education session 2: Setting the context for a
principles-based approach to assisted dying in Canada.
Webcast-.15:23
- 15:39 (Accessed 2015-10-23)
11. Groenewoud JH, van der Heide A. Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD Willems DL van der Maas PJ,
van der wal G., "Clinical Problems with the Performance of Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted
Suicide in the Netherlands." N Engl J Med 2000; 342:551-556 February 24, 2000
12. Ubelacker S. "Quebec MDs to get euthanasia guide to prepare for legalized assisted death:
Unclear whether other provinces and territories will adopt a similar practice."The Canadian
Press, 1 September, 2015
(Accessed 2015-09-03).
13. Moore E.
"Doctor is hoping feds will guide on assisted suicide legislation." Edson Leader,
12 February, 2015.
(Accessed 2015-07-16).
14. Rich, P.
"Physician perspective on end-of-life issues fully aired." Canadian Medical
Association, 19 August, 2014
(Accessed 2015-06-22).
15. Ubelacker S.
"Medical professionals try to answer burning questions on doctor-assisted
death." Associated Press, 13 February, 2015
(Accessed 2015-07-04).
16. Kirkey S.
"How far should a doctor go? MDs say they 'need clarity' on Supreme Courts
assisted suicide ruling." National Post, 23 February, 2015
(2015-07-04)
17. A request for physician assisted death will not be
considered an emergency in the context of this policy, and is therefore not a
service or intervention that physicians will be required to provide, contrary to
their conscience or religion. College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario,
Professional Obligations and Human Rights: Frequently Asked Questions.
(Accessed 2015-10-17)
18. Consultations & hearings on Quebec Bill 52, College of Pharmacists of Quebec:
Dianne Lamarre, Manon Lambert. Tuesday 17 September 2013 - Vol. 43 no. 34,
T#49,
T#58.
19. Consultations & hearings on Quebec Bill 52, College of Pharmacists of Quebec:
Dianne Lamarre, Manon Lambert. Tuesday 17 September 2013 - Vol. 43 no. 34,
T#33.
20. Consultations & hearings on Quebec Bill 52, College of Pharmacists of Quebec:
Dianne Lamarre, Manon Lambert. Tuesday 17 September 2013 - Vol. 43 no. 34,
T#76,
T#87,
T#88