From Expectation to Demand: A Coming Conflagration?
Presented to Medical Students' Forum sponsored by Canadian Physicians
for Life
Ancaster, Ontario (23 November, 2008)
Full Text
Introductory Remarks
On behalf of the Protection of Conscience Project
I thank Physicians for Life for honouring the
Project with the invitation to come to this forum.
More than that, I thank you for being here. I'll
echo Dr. John Patrick's words last night; the good
news is here. You have no idea how important you are
and how much it means to me to see you.
People of my generation and even my parents'
generation have tended to be of the opinion that our
society and political institutions are, if not the
ultimate expression of the goods that democracy has
to offer, at least the next best thing to it. But
the oldest modern democracy is only a little over
200 years old. And if you think that slavery is
incompatible with true democracy, then true
democratic government emerged less than 150 years
ago. Finally, if you think that true democracy
demands universal adult suffrage, a few of the
patients you'll encounter are older than true
democracy in Canada.
Perhaps some of your professors or preceptors are
as well.
My point is that, in historical terms, modern
democracy is still in diapers. We like to think that
we're experts in the field, that the rest of the
world ought to look to us to see democracy in its
most perfect and final form.
But - a question. Is it not possible that, as a
nation, we are toddlers who have not yet developed
the kind of moral balance demanded by the nature of
democratic government? We have an appetite for
freedom, to be sure, but what kind of freedom? For
what purpose? As CS Lewis observed, the kind of
things that citizens in a democracy naturally like
are not necessarily the things that will best
preserve democracy.1
What kind of freedom do we seek? For what
purpose? You have to seek the answers to those
questions, among others.
Now, that obligation falls to every generation.
But there are times when that obligation has special
significance. I believe that we are living in one of
those times. I believe that this obligation has come
to you in a special way, all unlooked for, as the
ring came to Frodo Baggins, and that, like him, you
will be asked to shoulder unexpected burdens, and go
off on unexpected adventures.
Are you up for it? I think you are.
Now, to business.
Caveat
First, I want to emphasize that everything I say
about the preservation of personal integrity and
protection of conscience in health care presumes the
kind of caring physician-patient relationship and
dialogue that were recommended and modelled for you
yesterday by Doctors Reynolds and Genuis.
Next, you should be aware that the Project is not
out to restrict or eliminate abortion or anything
else. We do not take a position on the objective
morality or desirability of a procedure or service.
Instead, the Project simply acknowledges that some
activities are morally controversial, and argue that
people should not be forced to participate in them,
or discriminated against because they refuse to do
so for reasons of conscience. For this reason, the
Project cannot be described as a pro-life
initiative, though that is often how it is
perceived. It differs in that way from Physicians
for Life.
However, like Physicians for Life, the Project is
a non-denominational initiative that operates within
a secular framework. The Advisory Board includes
scholars from different countries, rom Judaeism,
Christianity and Islam.
Presentation topics
I am going to touch on some developments
especially relevant to freedom of conscience in
health care, with a focus on the last two years, and
then deal briefly with the positions of Colleges of
Physicians and Surgeons in Canada.
A World Tour: 2006 to 2008
So what of the last couple of years?
In January, 2006 the Washington Post reported
that debate about freedom of conscience in health
care was "gaining new prominence" and "intensifying"
in the United States. More than a dozen states were
considering protective legislation, and about half
that number had drafted laws specifically for
pharmacists.2
By the end of 2007, one bioethics site noted that
freedom of conscience in healthcare had been "a hot
bioethical topic" during the year. It predicted that
it would "remain in the spotlight for 2008."3
As everyone here knows, it has certainly been in the
spotlight in Ontario, courtesy the Ontario Human
Rights Commission and the College of Physicians and
Surgeons.4
But that controversy is only part of a bigger
picture that I hope to outline for you.
You may notice I said the Ontario controversy
"is" part of the picture. The spotlight caught the
College and the OHRC like deer in the headlights in
August and September, but the controversy is far
from over. An American observer, Wesley Smith,
believes that issues of conscience will "likely . .
. become one of the most heated bioethical
controversies in the years to come." Just last week,
he warned: "Expect the fight over conscience to
become a political conflagration."5
From a certain perspective, this can be seen as
one of those good-news, bad-news stories. The good
news is that I am not a medical student or health
care professional. The bad news is that you are. You
can take that as a feeble attempt at humour, or as
the frank opinion of an increasing number of highly
influential people.
Won't prescribe contraceptives or facilitate
abortion because of your moral or religious view?
Then it's bad news that you are medical students.
Scum like you - that's the word used by a University
of Toronto professor - scum like you, he said,
should resign from medicine and find another job.6
Resign, and get another job. I've heard that
statement, over and over again, often from people
reputed to be progressive, tolerant and enlightened
citizens of the true north strong and free.
Using a few items from the Breaking News section
of the Project site, I'll take you on a quick world
tour to see what might have contributed to Wesley
Smith's grim prognosis.
First, and most recent: Australia.
Catholic hospitals in the Australian state of
Victoria may close as a result of a new law that
makes referral for abortion mandatory.7
Crossing the Pacific to North America, many of
you will have heard about the California case in
which a lesbian sued two Christian doctors who
refused to artificially inseminate her. What you may
not know is that the physicians not only referred
her for the treatment, but paid some of the expenses
incurred as a result. Her argument is that referral
was not good enough because race and sexual
inclinations are equivalent. Since physicians cannot
refuse to treat kidney disease in a patient because
of his race, they cannot refuse to inseminate a
woman in a lesbian relationship. Even referral is
held to be a violation of human rights.8
Here, in Canada, St. Elizabeth's Hospital in
Humboldt, Saskatchewan stopped contraceptive tubal
ligations because they were contrary to Catholic
teaching. Two physicians then resigned in protest.9
A woman complained to the provincial Human Rights
Commission that denial of tubal ligation was
discrimination based on gender and religion. The
Saskatchewan Catholic Health Corporation had to pay
almost $8,000.00 to settle the complaint.10
Ultimately, the hospital's Catholic affiliation was
ended and control of the hospital was transferred to
a regional health authority.11
Across the Atlantic, the opposition to abortion
that is a feature of indigenous African culture is
in conflict with documents like the Maputo Plan of
Action and the Maputo Protocol, all of which are
intended to establish abortion (and other things) as
legal rights.12
Last year, the Committee for the Elimination of
Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW) asked Polish
representatives "[h]ow many doctors had been
suspended or fired because they refused to perform
abortions?" The question appeared to reflect an
expectation that such practices should be the norm.13
In Portugal, abortion up to ten weeks gestation
was legalized in 2007.14
As a result of widespread conscientious objection,
the Portuguese Health Minister ordered the
Portuguese Medical Association to remove the
prohibition of abortion from its code of ethics.15
He insisted that it was unacceptable for codes of
ethics to "go against the general law of the
country."16
The Association eventually deleted direct reference
to abortion in the code. The new language affirms
that life is the highest value and cannot be
interrupted after it begins, but the Association has
adopted a neutral position as to when life begins.17
Just next door, the Spanish Socialist Workers'
Party's platform includes plans to restrict freedom
of conscience for medical professionals.18
In northern India a judge gave a deadline to
employees of the Medical Health Department to bring
ten people in to be sterilized. Catholic teachers
were ordered to promote sterilization among their
pupils and their families.19Nurses
at a convention in Bangalore reported that they were
being forced to pariticpate in abortions, and that
some who refused had been forced to resign.20
A young nurse in Pakistan who refused to perform
an abortion on two women was gang raped by three men
from their families. The Punjab Health Association
stated that this was not the first such incident.21
Other contexts
As you can see, conflicts of conscience most
commonly arise within the context of reproductive
health care. But that is hardly the only context.
Belgium. In 2007, the ruling party announced that
it would force every hospital in the country to
provide euthanasia or to refer patients to
facilities that would do so. The party was willing
to tolerate conscientious objection by physicians on
condition that they refer them for euthanasia
provided by more willing colleagues.22
The party was merely following the lead of the
Flemish GP's association and the Universities of
Ghent and Louvain, which had jointly recommended
mandatory referral for euthanasia.23
By the way, the reasoning in their joint statement
precisely parallels the reasoning of preceptors who
failed a medical student on an obstetrics rotation
because he was unwilling to refer for abortion or
the morning after pill.
Several articles in a 2006 number of the Journal
of Medical Ethics discuss the use of patients in
persistent vegetative states as experimental
subjects. Some authors asserted that they would be
especially useful in studies of the long-term
effects of animal organ transplants.24
What to do if a patient wants a prostitute and
isn't able to arrange for one himself? The Douglas
hospice in Oxford, England, made the necessary
connections. The hospice foundress explained: "It is
not our job to make moral decisions for our guests."
No paternalism here, to be sure, but certainly the
suggestion that a physician who truly respects
patient autonomy will help him to find a 'sex trade
worker.'25
But what if the patient is urgently in need of
the kind of sexual health care provided by
prostitutes, and timely access to a prostitute is
not possible? What duty of care does the physician
owe to the patient in such circumstances? The
mantra, "patient centred care" suggests an answer.
So, too, does the refer-or-provide-it-yourself model
that the establishment favours for other kinds of
reproductive health care. That is part of the noble
calling of a physician, isn't it? To sacrifice
oneself for the good of the patient?26
Responses to contentious services
You will have noticed the frequent reference to
"rights" in this whirlwind sampling. It's now time
to see something of what lies behind all of this.
People commonly respond to a morally contentious
service in one of three ways:
1. The first is to consider it
a legitimate medical service without restriction or
qualification, like palliative care.
2. The second is to consider
it a medical service that is legitimate in some
circumstances but not in others.
3. The third is to reject it
absolutely, as something that should never be done.
Two of the three possible responses can give rise
to conscientious objection by health care personnel.
Hence, one ought to heed the advice of the British Medical Journal; when legalization of a
contentious medical procedure is contemplated, it
would be prudent to first consider how many health
care professionals are willing to assist with it.27
Failure to take this advice has consequences, and
these consequences have become especially evident in
the case of abortion, which we might take as an
exemplar of contentious procedures. We have seen
what happened in Portugal. Spain has found few
physicians willing to perform the procedure.28
That there are not enough physicians willing to
provide abortions is a frequent complaint of
American abortion rights activists.29
The reluctance of many health care workers to
participate is complicated by the fact that many of
those who are willing to provide the service in some
circumstances are unwilling to do so in others. The
response to what they consider late term abortions30
is frequently adverse,31
so that women wanting late term abortions may have
to travel from one country to another.32
Late term abortions can even lead to resignations33and
threats of legal action.34
Further: gestational age is only one of the factors
that can give rise to conscientious objection.35
And even after legalization, opposition to abortion
does not necessarily diminish over time.36
Four stage progression
First Point: expectation vs. reality
I suggest that this demonstrates that the British Medical Journal was right. An
expectation that medical personnel will provide or
facilitate abortions runs up against the fact that a
not insignificant number of them - in some
circumstances, even a majority - are unwilling to do
so for reasons of conscience.
This is the first point I want to draw to your
attention: that there is a fundamental conflict
between the expectation that health care workers
will provide abortions, and the reality that many of
them may be unwilling to do so.
Second Point: expectations rise
My second is that this expectation is not static;
it tends to rise. It is fuelled by continuing
pressure to legalize abortion, liberalize existing
abortion laws and expand abortion services, so it is
continually colliding with resistance and opposition
to abortion, especially in countries that have
strong cultural and religious traditions against the
practice.37
Third Point: expectation to demand
My third point is that rising expectation that
health care workers will provide abortions tends to
evolve into a demand that they do so: that they
should have no choice in the matter.
38Now, advocates of safe and legal abortion have
campaigned for years using slogans like 'freedom of
choice.' They describe themselves as 'pro-choice'
rather than 'pro-abortion,' and protest vigorously
against what they perceive as attempts to 'impose
morality.' So one would think that these activists
would be among the first to defend freedom of choice
for health care workers. In principle, it should not
be at all difficult to move from,"If you are against
abortion, don't have one," to, "If you are against
abortion, don't do one."
Remarkably, this is not
the case. What others call "conscience clauses" they
call "refusal clauses,"39
"denial clauses"40
or "patient abandonment clauses;"41
conscientious objection, in their view, is "denying
access to medical care."42
They want all medical students trained in the
procedure,43and,
at a minimum, demand that health care workers who
object to abortion refer patients to someone who
will provide the service.44They
lobby vigorously against freedom of conscience
legislation,45
and tactics can extend to misrepresenting the
ethical and legal obligations of health care
workers.46
They will even incite complaints against
conscientious objectors.47
In short, many "pro-choice" activists do not
support freedom of choice, unless it is a choice of
their choosing. Instead, they contribute
substantially to the dynamic by which expectation
evolves into demand. Such groups are typically
well-funded, well-connected within the professions
of health care and law, command the attention of
politicians and policy makers, and have a
significant impact in the media.48
Unfortunately, their views are often supported by
state institutions and the media.49
Fourth Point: from demand to right
Recall my first point: an expectation that health
care workers will provide abortion vs. the reality
that many are unwilling to do so.
My second: rising expectation collides with
opposition.
Third: rising expectation evolves into demand.
We have not yet done with the progression; there
is one more stage. When the demand is resisted - as
it continues to be - demand evolves into a claim of
rights.50
I am not now talking about the earliest use of
rights language. When the National Association for
the Repeal of Abortion Laws opened its doors in the
United States in 1969, the claim that abortion was a
right was directed only at the repeal of laws
against abortion, so that women would be free to
seek abortions and physicians free to provide them.51
At that time there were repeated assurances that
"nobody would be forcing abortion procedures on
anyone else."52
I am not now talking about "rights language" from
this early period, but about current claims of
rights that, contrary to early activist promises,
are meant to force health care workers and
institutions to provide or at least facilitate
abortions. One of the most important 'movers and
shakers' in this field is the Center for
Reproductive Rights,53
an American advocacy group described in internal
documents as an organization "comprised largely of
economically advantaged white women."54
Center for Reproductive Rights
Actually, as the name of the Center implies,
current rights claims involve more than abortion;
the Center's agenda includes, among other things,
the legal enforcement of what it describes as
inalienable sexual rights.55
In this it is allied with the International Planned
Parenthood Federation, which recently issued a
declaration on sexual rights.56
The ultimate goal of the Center, Planned
Parenthood and their allies is to establish what the
Center calls "hard norms" - treaty-based
international laws57
- that recognize access to abortion as a fundamental
human right.58
It plans to develop a "culture of enforcement" that
will compel governments to respect this 'right'59
and enforce it against third parties - you.60
Even as it works toward this end, it is cultivating
"soft norms" in the form of statements by
international, regional, and intergovernmental
bodies.61
Should the Center be successful it acknowledges
that it will have effected "profound social change."62
It will also have destroyed almost all hope of
respect for freedom of conscience in health care.
For if refusal to facilitate abortion were to
become, in law, an offence like racial
discrimination, conscientious objection would be
prohibited, just as racial discrimination is now
prohibited.63
Since the stakes are so high, I want to draw your
attention to some key features of the Center's
strategy, notably its focus on securing a following
among social, political, academic and professional
elites.64
The medical profession is one of the "key sectors"
that figures prominently in this strategy;65
so, too, does the legal community.66
The approach is summed up in a question ,"How can we
influence the people who influence the legal
landscape around reproductive rights?"67
The courtship of the elites occurs in academic,
professional and bureaucratic communities, largely
out of the public eye, thus avoiding what one memo
calls "nasty opposition."68
This is especially important if professionals and
academics may be more sympathetic to the CRR agenda
than ordinary people.69
An internal memo values the "stealth quality to the
work," through which the Center achieves
"incremental recognition of values without a huge
amount of scrutiny from the opposition."70
Despite an admission that a 'right' to abortion
cannot be found in existing international
instruments, the Center and its allies argue that it
is implicit in other internationally recognized
rights, such as the right to life, liberty and
security, and rights to privacy and freedom from
discrimination.71
They hope to secure "hard norms" by having binding
treaties or protocols interpreted in this way,72
in the expectation that other adjudicators will find
such rulings persuasive.73
The Center's cultivation of "soft norms" is a
very similar process, but takes place not only in
adjudicative bodies but in international conferences
that produce non-binding but persuasive opinions.74
As "soft norms" quietly accumulate it becomes easier
for the Center to claim that they represent an
emerging consensus that should be codified in
binding "hard norms."75
The development of "soft norms" is of great moment
for freedom of conscience in health care because
they will likely have the most immediate impact on
conscientious objectors.
Professional associations, educational and
regulatory authorities and influential individuals
can support the CRR's work by developing "soft
norms" closer to home. Colleagues, academics, med
school professors and preceptors will argue that the
provision of abortion or, at least, referral for
abortion, is an expected or even legally required
standard of care.76
Ethicists and professional journals not infrequently
express opinions hostile to freedom of conscience,77as
do individual health care practitioners.78
If such claims are repeated often enough by
influential persons - even if the claims are false
or exaggerated - they gradually assume the character
of a new norm. This new norm will be implemented by
the disciplinary apparatus of self-governing
professions as a standard of care: first, by
pressure, in the form of pointed suggestions,
informal cautions and official guidance. Many
objectors, fearing more serious consequences, may be
reluctant to dispute or resist. Medical students are
most vulnerable to this kind of pressure.
Eventually, an objector will be charged for
professional misconduct.79It
is quite likely that members of the professional
tribunal hearing the case will, by that time, have
already been convinced of the new rights-based
standard of care, or will have been prepared to
accept the claims of experts called to testify to
it. Should they ratify it by ruling against the
objector they will create a new "soft norm" that the
CRR can use in other fora in its continuing quest
for international "hard norms."
What can be done?
Well, what can be done about this?
I suggest three things: resist, counter and
protest.
Resist pressure to conform to expectations that
contradict your fundamental beliefs. This implies
that you must know what you believe, why you believe
it, and what practical implications flow from it.
For example: if you refuse to prescribe
contraceptives to unmarried patients, you must be
prepared to explain what you mean by "married."
Christian marriage? Religious marriage?
Non-religious marriage? Marriage before a marriage
commissioner? Common law marriage?
Resist, and counter.
Counter the pressure. This implies that you must
understand the arguments being made against your
position, and that you can respond with arguments
that make a plausible case for accommodating it.
Resist, counter and protest.
Protest the pressure. Speak out. Write letters.
Use petitions. Make submissions. The strategy
employed by the Center and its allies depends, to a
significant degree, on creating the false impression
that there is a 'soft norm' supported by a consensus
among People Who Matter. Use every opportunity to
demonstrate that no such consensus exists.
As an example of what can be done, and of the
kind of work the Project does to support you, I will
close with an extract from the submission to the
College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario. But
first, Colleges of Physicians in Canada.
Policies of Canadian Colleges of Physicians
As I remarked last night, even Henry Morgentaler
supports freedom of conscience for physicians with
respect to actually performing abortion,80
so you won't find any of the Colleges requiring
that. Their attitudes are conveniently demonstrated
by their policies on referral.
The Project has corresponded with Colleges of
Physicians in British Columbia, Alberta,
Saskatchewan, Manitoba, Ontario, New Brunswick and
Nova Scotia on issues relevant to freedom of
conscience for physicians. We have been unsuccessful
in engaging Colleges in Prince Edward Island and
Newfoundland, and cannot correspond with Quebec
authorities because what French I have would only be
useful in starting a fight in a bar.
Briefly, only Quebec and Nova Scotia require
objecting physicians to facilitate or refer for
procedures to which they object for reasons of
conscience. The situation in Quebec may be
influenced by civil jurisprudence that is based on
the Code Napoleon rather than common law. The
referral requirement in Nova Scotia was set out in a
bulletin that predated the adoption of the Canadian
Medical Association's Code of Ethics by the Nova
Scotia College. Since the CMA position on referral -
that it is not required81
- is not set out in the CMA Code, it would be useful
to seek clarification of the College's present
position. For this purpose, it would be helpful if a
medical student or physician in Nova Scotia were to
write to the College, or ask that the Project do so
on his behalf.
Project Submission
Returning to the advice to resist, counter and
protest, what follows is an example of the work done
by the Project, in the form of an extract from the
Project submission to the College of Physicians and
Surgeons of Ontario.