Taking (Conscience) Rights Seriously
Originally appeared 11 June, 2012
In
Public Discourse:
Ethics, Law, and the Common Good
Online journal of the
Witherspoon Institute of
Princeton, NJ
Reproduced with permission.
Melissa Moschella*
The key to understanding conscience rights correctly is to
recognize that there is a world of difference between a law that
makes me do something I don't want to do, and a law that
makes me do something I have an obligation not to do.
As a pluralistic liberal democracy, we should craft our laws so that
individuals will never be unnecessarily coerced into violating their
consciences.
Recently Catholics stood up in a united protest against the
Department of Health and Human Services' mandate that requires
employers to provide insurance coverage for contraception,
sterilization, and abortion-inducing drugs, filing 12 lawsuits on
behalf of 43 Catholic entities across the country. They claim that
the mandate runs afoul of the First Amendment and the 1993 Religious
Freedom Restoration Act by requiring them to pay for or to
facilitate access to products and services in violation of their
sincerely held religious beliefs. They joined a
broader
interfaith coalition that now includes 53 groups filing 23
lawsuits.
To many, including the
editors of the
New York Times, opposition to the
mandate seems like an attempt to impose Catholic views about
contraception on the rest of the society, or an unjustified request
for special treatment. Why should a minority of Catholics (together
with some other Christians who object to the abortion-drug aspect of
the mandate) determine public policy for the entire country? Yes,
the government could provide free access to contraceptives without
conscripting employers to do it for them through their health plans,
but why should we bend over backwards to adapt our policies to the
religious or moral sensibilities of a minority?
These common objections invite a broader reflection about why, as
a pluralistic liberal democracy, we should indeed bend over
backwards to craft our laws so that individuals will never be
unnecessarily coerced into violating their consciences.
Unnecessarily, as we'll see, is the key word, for conscience rights
aren't absolute trumps; they are conditioned by the needs of public
order and others' rights. Given their fundamental importance,
however, the common good requires respecting conscience rights
unless it is absolutely necessary for the achievement of a truly
compelling state interest-as it would be, for example, if a religion
required its members to engage in human sacrifice, or to act
violently toward nonbelievers.
The key to understanding conscience rights correctly is to
recognize that there is a world of difference between a law that
makes me do something I don't want to do, and a law that
makes me do something I have an obligation not to do. The
former is an annoyance, the latter an assault on my moral integrity.
I may not want to follow the speed limit, but that doesn't
give me a claim to be exempted from the law. On the other hand, if I
believe that killing animals is morally wrong, no law should force
me to serve meat in my business's cafeteria, or give my employees
gift certificates to a steakhouse, even if encouraging people to eat
more high-protein foods would promote public health.
Likewise, I may think that taking a hallucinogenic drug such as
peyote will improve my overall health and happiness, but only if I
believe I have an obligation to use that drug-as do members
of the Native American Church in some sacramental contexts-do I have
a special claim to an exemption from laws that forbid me to do so.
That's why, after the Supreme Court concluded it was unable to grant
Native Americans in Oregon such an exemption in Employment
Division v. Smith, lawmakers rightfully responded at
the state level by adding an exemption to the Oregon drug law, and
at the national level with the Religious Freedom Restoration Act,
prohibiting the government from substantially burdening the free
exercise of religion unless there is no other way to achieve a
compelling state interest.
My point is not that the Supreme Court decided Smith
incorrectly; analyzing the Smith decision would require
also considering the scope and limits of judicial authority to
overturn laws duly enacted by the elected representatives of the
people, and that is not my subject here. Rather, my point is that,
as a matter of principle, members of the Native American Church,
like others in a similar situation, have a right to an exemption
from laws that prevent them from practicing their faith. The
accommodations granted to them for the sacramental use of peyote
were neither a case of unjustified special treatment, nor a case of
the Native American Church imposing its views on everyone else.
Rather, those accommodations were based on the recognition that a
burden on individuals' ability to follow their deeply held
beliefs-not just desires or preferences, but beliefs about how they
are obligated to live-is a unique and uniquely threatening
type of limitation on individual freedom.
Yet one might ask, as Brian Barry does in Culture and
Equality, why we should treat a religious belief, or any
perceived moral obligation, differently from a mere desire or
preference. Why should the law distinguish between, for example,
those who sincerely believe that smoking marijuana from time to time
will enhance their overall quality of life, and those who, like the
plaintiffs in the Smith case, believe that they have a
religious obligation to ingest peyote in sacramental contexts?
Laws exist to promote the common good, which includes, as a
constitutive element, the integral well-being of all members of
society. Integral human well-being is perfectly compatible with
(indeed, often requires) acting against one's preferences or
desires. Even reasonable preferences often need to be set aside if
one is to form and follow a coherent plan of life, remain faithful
to one's commitments, favor and foster the common good of one's
communities, treat others fairly, and generally abide by the moral
norms that structure and guide practical decision-making in
accordance with the requirements for genuine human flourishing. Thus
when following the law-which serves the common good by, among other
things, solving coordination problems-requires one to act against
one's preferences, no harm to one's integral well-being is involved.
This does not mean that justice places no limits on the extent to
which, or the manner in which, law restricts the pursuit of
reasonable preferences. In order to serve its function of promoting
the common good, the law should avoid unreasonably
restricting individual liberty with regard to the pursuit of
reasonable preferences, and should also try to avoid unfairness in
distributing the benefits and burdens of common life, among which
are inevitable restrictions on freedom.
Unlike failing to act on a reasonable preference, failing to
fulfill a perceived obligation-failing to follow one's conscience-is
always incompatible with integral human well-being. This is
true even when one is objectively wrong about the content of
one's obligations.
Unlike failing to act on a reasonable preference, failing to
fulfill a perceived obligation-failing to follow one's conscience-is
always incompatible with integral human well-being. This is
true even when one is objectively wrong about the content of one's
obligations. For moral acts are not mere physical chunks of
behavior, but are specified by what one's will is choosing in
choosing to perform an action. An action is good insofar as one's
will, in choosing that action, is in line with a will toward
integral human well-being. Now, if one believes that, for example,
ingesting peyote in a sacramental context is morally obligatory, in
choosing not to do so one is, among other things, choosing not to
fulfill a moral obligation. Because fulfilling one's moral
obligations is a basic and constitutive aspect of human well-being,
a direct choice not to fulfill an obligation is out of line
with a will toward integral human well-being. The exact content of
the obligation is irrelevant; what matters is that, from the
perspective of the acting agent, the agent is choosing not to
fulfill an obligation.
Of course, in the face of laws that prohibit one from acting in
accordance with a perceived obligation, one can still choose to
fulfill that obligation and face the legal penalty. Especially when
the penalty is severe, such a choice is heroic. But laws, which aim
to foster the common good, which includes the good of each
individual, should not create powerful incentives for individuals to
act against their genuine well-being. Laws should not, in other
words, force us to be heroic in order to maintain our moral
integrity.
Further, laws that forbid individuals to act in accordance with
the dictates of their consciences place a burden on those
individuals that differs not only in degree, but in kind, from the
sort of burden involved in forbidding someone to act in accordance
with mere preferences, however strong. Such laws-even when, like the
Oregon drug laws at issue in Smith, they are otherwise
reasonable-fail to distribute the benefits and burdens of social
cooperation fairly. Individuals whose conscience rights are burdened
by a law therefore have at least a prima facie claim of
justice to an exemption from that law, although that claim may be
defeated in cases where granting it would be incompatible with the
protection of others' fundamental rights or the preservation of the
public order.
This brings us back to my point about unnecessarily
burdening conscience. One might make the counterargument-returning
to the HHS mandate debate-that others' fundamental rights are
at stake in this controversy. Many believe that what is really
at issue is a woman's right to control her own body. Further, some
individuals believe themselves to have an obligation to use
artificial birth control, and thus their conscience rights are at
stake as well. Yet even if we take both of these to be valid rights
claims, it takes only a moment's reflection to realize that
rescinding the HHS mandate would violate neither.
Rescinding the mandate would not make contraception illegal.
Those who want to use it, or believe themselves to have an
obligation to use it, remain free to do so at, I might add, rather
negligible financial cost. Even if one has a fundamental right to do
something, that does not imply that one has a fundamental right to
have someone else foot the bill. Catholics have the obligation, and
therefore the right, to attend Mass on Sundays, but that does not
mean that the government is required to pay for their transportation
costs. Further, even if the government believes that promoting
artificial birth control use is such a compelling state interest
that it ought to be promoted by removing all possible
disincentives (including financial ones), that goal could easily be
pursued in ways that do not burden the conscience rights of other
citizens.
Finally, for those more convinced by pragmatic considerations
than abstract arguments about the requirements of justice, let's not
forget that as a political community we also have good practical
reasons to avoid making laws that undermine religious practice,
because religion in general makes a crucial contribution to civil
society. Religion combats individualism-which, as Alexis de
Tocqueville famously pointed out in Democracy in America, is one of the great dangers to the health and survival of democratic
nations-by producing in people a sense of gratitude and a desire to
serve others. That's why, as Robert Putnam and David Campbell show
in American Grace, religious people across the board have
much higher rates of civic participation and volunteerism than
non-religious people. Catholic Charities, for example, provides some
6.5 million meals to the hungry each year, along with many other
social services to the poorest and most vulnerable in our society.
Do we really want to force these charities either to limit their
ministry to fellow Catholics in order to qualify for the HHS
mandate's extremely narrow religious exemption-the narrowest ever in
the history of federal law-or to pay crippling fines that will leave
them with no choice but to cut their services?
We live in a highly pluralistic society that includes people of
many different faiths and of no faith at all. If we are to live
together peacefully and cooperate for the common good, we should
seek all possible alternative routes before choosing a path toward
public goals that rides roughshod over conscientious beliefs, even
beliefs with which we strongly disagree.