Conscientious objection and the worrying implications of the Glasgow
midwives case
Christian Medical Fellowship
Blogs
17 December, 2014
Reproduced with permission
The right for health professionals to exercise their
conscientious objection to participating in abortion – or indeed to
choose on occasion to limit the areas in which they work in order
not to be ethically compromised – has been under
assault worldwide for some time now. It is increasingly
perceived as a
major obstacle to unfettered, whole scale reproductive 'rights'.
Now the right for health professionals to exercise their
conscientious objection has been put under even more pressure in the
UK after
the Supreme Court today rejected an appeal for conscientious
objection for senior midwives who refused to supervise abortions
performed on a labour ward. It has also delivered a controversial
ruling on referrals for abortion.
A significant number of doctors already refuse to participate in
carrying out abortions, including an
increasing number of younger doctors, so the
job is increasingly being given to nurses and midwives to carry
out instead, under the loose direction of doctors.
But many nurses and midwives are also not willing to participate
in abortions, directly or indirectly.
Therefore, two midwives from Glasgow took a case to Court in
order to define the scope of conscientious objection under the 1967
Abortion Act.
Mary Doogan and Concepta Wood were employed as Labour Ward
Coordinators at the Southern General Hospital in Glasgow. They
were concerned that the reorganisation of maternity services
would result in an increased number of abortions being carried out
on the labour ward, and that their objections to playing any part at
all in these procedures would not be respected and accommodated:
The outstanding issue was their continued objection to
"delegating, supervising and/or supporting staff to participate
in and provide care to patients throughout the termination
process..
However the health board maintained that the Abortion Act 1967
did not give the midwives any right to refuse to
delegate, support or supervise staff providing nursing care for
women going through abortions
The first
Court ruling said their right of conscientious objection was not
unqualified and their duties did not require them to provide
treatment to terminate pregnancies directly.
However this was
overturned by the Scottish Court of Appeal, who found their
Trust to be in the wrong. Instead, it ruled that their right to
conscientious objection meant they could refuse to delegate,
supervise or support staff involved in abortions:
In our view the right of conscientious objection extends
not only to the actual medical or surgical termination but to
the whole process of treatment given for that purpose.
The Trust duly appealed this, sending the case to the UK Supreme
Court, which has now upheld their appeal against the Scottish Court
ruling.
In essence, the legal dispute centres on the extent of the 1967
Abortion Act conscientious objection clause, particularly the
scope and meaning of the word 'participate'.
Section 4 of the Abortion Act 1967 allows an individual to
refuse to participate in any treatment under the Act to which he has
a conscientious objection:
(1) Subject to sub-section (2) of this section, no person
shall be under any duty whether by contract or by any statutory or
other legal requirement to participate in any treatment authorised
by this Act to which he has a conscientious objection.
Whilst it is clear that this covers those directly
involved in the abortion itself, it has not been clear
whether anything that occurs outside the operating theatre falls
outside the ambit of s4(1), including referrals for abortion,
particularly since Article 9 of the European Convention on Human
Rights provides that: 'Everyone has the right to freedom of
thought, conscience and religion; this right includes… freedom …to
manifest his religion or belief in worship, teaching, practice and
observance.' However the
Supreme Court did not consider this Article relevant.
The Scottish Appeal Court judgment had been a significant victory
for the midwives and others in their position. It allowed for the
conscientious exemption clause to extend not only to the actual
medical or surgical termination itself but also to the whole
process, covering participation in all aspects of
abortion 'treatment'.
But it has now been decided that the clause does not cover those
who are asked to delegate, supervise or support staff carrying out
abortions because
Lady Hale ruled that:
The conscience clause does not cover making bookings or
aftercare for patients who have undergone a termination. Nor
does it cover fetching the drug before it is administered.
"Participating" is limited to direct participation in the
treatment involved. It does not cover administrative and
managerial tasks.
This controversial ruling applies to more than 'just' midwives.
It obviously creates real difficulties for anyone with a
moral objection put in this position, many of whom would view
delegation, supervision or support as 'participation'.
Of particular concern is that the Supreme Court ruled (para 40)
on another grey area, that any medical professional who refuses to
provide an abortion must arrange for a referral to someone
else who will do so. This seems to go far beyond the scope
of the Abortion Act, and furthermore is not even an issue there was
any need for the Court to decide in this case.
This new ruling conflicts with
2013 GMC guidance that doctors are
not obliged
to refer patients seeking abortion to other doctors who will do it
but must 'make sure that the patient has enough information to
arrange to see another doctor who does not hold the same objection
as you '.
Freedom of conscience is not a minor or peripheral issue. It goes
to the heart of medical practice as a moral activity. The right of
conscience helps to preserve the moral integrity of the individual
clinician, preserves the distinctive characteristics and reputation
of nursing and midwifery as a profession, acts as a safeguard
against coercive state power, and provides protection from
discrimination for those with minority ethical beliefs. There are
plenty of
notorious examples of the moral corruption of a medical
profession where freedom of conscience has been ignored or
forbidden.
Imagine if these midwives had been working in another country and
been asked to 'supervise' activities that were legal there but that
most people in Britain would regard as highly unethical? For
example, euthanasia of people with dementia, amputation for
stealing, female circumcision, or the torture of prisoners. Most
would agree people should not be forced to participate in
such activities. Most Britons (I hope) would back their right to
refuse.
And to 'participate' should not just involve direct action. Many
would consider that a referral is participating in abortion. If I do
not physically take part in a robbery, but knowingly provide the
thieves with information or equipment to enable them to perform the
crime, or provide the getaway car or help conceal or dispose of the
loot, I should be guilty under the law as if I had been on the
premises myself.
It is only because abortion is regarded as mundane and routine in
Britain that a case like this does not generate huge public outrage
and concern. But that reveals as much about the weakened conscience
of the British public as it does about morality of abortion.