'Pulling the plug' isn't euthanasia
The Ottawa Citizen
19 March, 2010
Reproduced with permission
Margaret Somerville*
Recently, I saw an illustration that accompanied
an article about euthanasia. It showed the
silhouette of a patient lying on a bed. There was an
electrical outlet on the wall behind the bed and an
unplugged connecting cord hanging down over the side
of the bed.
Except in very rare circumstances - for instance,
if the treatment were withdrawn without the
necessary consent or against the patient's wishes -
withdrawal of life-support treatment is not
euthanasia. Yet many people, including the artist
who penned this illustration and many health-care
professionals, mistakenly believe that it is.
In my experience, they are confused with respect
to the ethical and legal differences between
withdrawal of treatment that results in death and
euthanasia, and why the former can be ethically and
legally acceptable, provided certain conditions are
fulfilled, and the latter cannot be. This is a
central and important distinction in the euthanasia
debate, which needs to be understood.
Failure to understand it leads, among other
problems, to physicians responding affirmatively to
surveys that ask them whether they or their
colleagues have carried out euthanasia, when in fact
they have not, and members of the public saying they
agree with euthanasia, because they agree with
people's rights to refuse medical treatment.
First, the primary intention is different in the
two cases: In withdrawing life-support treatment the
primary intention is to respect the patient's right
to refuse treatment; in euthanasia it is to kill the
patient. The former intention is ethically and
legally acceptable; the latter is not.
Patients have a right to refuse treatment, even
if that means they will die. They have a right not
to be touched, including through medical treatment,
without their consent - a right to inviolability.
This right protects a person's physical integrity
and can also function to protect physical and mental
privacy. The right to inviolability is one aspect of
every competent adult's right to autonomy and
self-determination.
Pro-euthanasia advocates use recognition of this
right to refuse treatment even when it results in
death to argue that, likewise, patients should be
allowed to exercise their right to autonomy and
self-determination to choose death through lethal
injection. They say that there is no morally or
ethically significant difference between these
situations, and there ought to be no legal
difference.
They found their argument by wrongly
characterizing the right to refuse treatment as a
"right to die," and then generalize that right to
include dying through euthanasia and
physician-assisted suicide. But the right to refuse
treatment is not a "right to die" and does not
establish any such right, although death results
from respecting the patient's right to
inviolability. The right to refuse treatment can be
validly characterized as a "right to be allowed to
die," but this is quite different from a right to be
killed that euthanasia would establish.
Moreover, a "right to be allowed to die by
refusing treatment," is a "negative content" right -
a right against one's integrity being breached
without one's consent. In contrast, a "right to die"
through access to euthanasia would be a "positive
content" right - that is, a right to something. In
general, the law is very much more reluctant to
recognize positive content rights, than negative
content ones.
This pro-euthanasia line of argument is yet one
more example of promoting euthanasia through
deliberate confusion between interventions, such as
valid refusals of treatment, that are not euthanasia
and those that are.
This brings us to the issue of legal causation,
which also differentiates
refusals-of-treatment-that-result-in-death from
euthanasia. In the former, the person dies from
their underlying disease - a natural death. The
withdrawal of treatment is the occasion on which
death occurs, but not its cause. If the person had
no fatal illness, they would not die. We can see
that when patients who refuse treatment and are
expected to die, do not die. In contrast, in
euthanasia death is certain and the cause of death
is the lethal injection. Without that, the person
would not die at that time from that cause.
The fact that the patient dies both in refusing
treatment and in euthanasia is one of the sources of
the confusion between the two. If we focus just on
the fact that in both cases the outcome is death, we
miss the real point of distinction between death
resulting from refusing treatment and from
euthanasia.
The issue in the euthanasia debate is not if we
die - we all eventually die. The issue is how we die
and whether some means of dying, such as euthanasia
and physician-assisted suicide, should remain
legally prohibited. In order to maintain that they
should, we need to be able to show how currently
accepted practices, such as respect for patients'
refusals of treatment, are not euthanasia and differ
from it and assisted suicide.