The Problem of Complicity
Effective referral and physician participation in euthanasia, assisted
suicide, abortion, execution and torture
15 March, 2016
Full Text
Introduction
It appears that most people are willing to grant that a health care
worker who has serious moral objections to a procedure should not be
compelled to perform it or assist directly with it. However, many people
find it more difficult to understand why some health care workers object to
even indirect forms of involvement. They fail to see why physicians
might refuse to help patients obtain a morally contested service or
procedure by referring them to a more willing colleague who will provide it.
There are increasingly strident demands that this response - what has
come to be called "effective referral" - should be forced upon unwilling
healthcare workers. Notably, a Canadian parliamentary committee recently
recommended that physicians unwilling to kill patients or help them commit
suicide should be forced to make an "effective referral": forced to help
find someone willing to do so.1
These politicians seem to be following a trail blazed by the American
College of Obstetrics and Gynecology (ACOG) Committee on Ethics in 2007.
Committee members were puzzled by physicians who refuse to refer for or
otherwise facilitate what they believe to be wrong, like abortion.
"The logic of
conscience, as a form of self-reflection on and judgement about whether
one's own acts are obligatory or prohibited," states the Committee, "means
that it would be odd or absurd to say, 'I would have a guilty conscience if
she did X.'"2
The Canadian politicians and ACOG Committee members seem to think that
someone who merely arranges for X - be it abortion or euthanasia - is
absolved of moral responsibility, perhaps in the belief that only someone
who actually does or has an abortion or gives or receives a lethal injection
can be morally responsible for it. Alternatively, they may believe that
responsibility arising from effective referral is morally insignificant.
This reasoning is based on unexamined faith-assumptions shared by
Committee members about the nature of the procedures in question and/or
moral complicity and culpability. These are contested beliefs, not
incontrovertible moral or ethical principles, and the recommendations of the
respective committees would impose those beliefs upon those who think
differently through a requirement for "effective referral."
Complicity in torture
Newsweek columnist Jonathan Alter took this position in the
weeks following the terrorist attacks on the United States in September,
2001. Alter argued that it was time to think about torturing terrorist
suspects who might know about plans for such horrendous crimes. He
acknowledged that physical torture is "contrary to American values," but
argued that it is sometimes appropriate. He proposed a novel 'compromise:'
that the United States turn terrorist suspects who won’t talk over to "less
squeamish allies,"3
a practice known as "extraordinary rendition." The allies would then do what
Americans would not, without compromising American values.
Some months later, Canadian citizen Maher Arar, returning home from
Zurich through New York, was detained, interrogated and "rendered" to Syria
by U.S. authorities.4 In Syria he was
imprisoned for almost a year, "interrogated, tortured and held in degrading
and inhumane conditions."5
A subsequent "comprehensive and thorough" investigation "did not turn up
any evidence that he had committed any criminal offence" and disclosed "no
evidence" that he was a threat to Canadian security."6
A commission of inquiry was appointed to investigate "the actions of
Canadian officials" in the case.7
What was of concern to Mr. Arar, the Canadian public and the Canadian
government was whether or not Canadian officials had caused or contributed
to the imprisonment and torture of Mr. Arar. Even though he was deported by
the United States and imprisoned and tortured by Syrian officials, the key
issue was whether or not the actions of Canadian officials had made Canada
indirectly complicit in torture.
Concern about Canadian complicity surfaces repeatedly in the report of
the commission of inquiry: in briefing notes to the Commissioner of the
RCMP,8 in the testimony of the Canadian
Ambassador to Syria,9 in references to the
possibility of RCMP complicity in his deportation,10
about the perception of complicity if CSIS agents met Mr. Arar in Syria,11
in the suggestion that evidence of complicity could show "a pattern of
misconduct,"12 and in the conclusions and
recommendations of the report itself.13
The issue of complicity arose again in 2007 when a report in Toronto's
Globe and Mail alleged that prisoners taken in Afghanistan by Canadian
troops and turned over to Afghan authorities were being mistreated and
tortured.14"Canada is hardly in a position to
claim it did not know what was going on," said the Globe. "At best, it tried
not to know; at worst, it knew and said nothing."15
On this view, one can be complicit in wrongdoing not only by acting, but by
failing to act, and even by silence. The Globe editorial brings to mind the
words of Martin Luther King and Mahatma Gandhi.16
Thus far, government officials. But the problem of complicity does not
relate only to government officials. The Lancet, among others, has asked,
"How complicit are doctors in the abuse of detainees"17
and other journal articles have explored the answer with some anxiety.18
Vicarious moral responsibility
The Arar Inquiry, the concerns raised by the Globe and Mail story about
Afghan detainees and the alarm raised about physician complicity in torture
make sense only upon the premise that one can be morally responsible -
guilty, in fact- for acts actually committed by another person. If one can
be morally responsible for acts actually committed by another, there may be
differences of opinion about what kind of action or omission incurs such
responsibility.
These differences need not be thoroughly canvassed here. It is sufficient
to ask if physicians who believe a procedure to be immoral can reasonably
conclude that helping patients to obtain that procedure is morally
significant participation that they should refuse.
Physician complicity in executions and torture
The issue of culpable participation in a morally controversial procedure
has been considered by the American Medical Association in its policy on
capital punishment.19 It forbids physician
participation in executions, and defines participation as an action which
(1) would directly cause the death of the condemned;
(2) would assist, supervise, or contribute to the
ability of another individual to directly cause the death of the
condemned;
(3) could automatically cause an execution to be carried
out on a condemned prisoner.
Among the actions identified by the AMA as "participation" in executions
are prescribing or administering tranquillizers or other drugs as part of
the procedure, directly or indirectly monitoring vital signs, rendering
technical advice or consulting with the executioners, and even (except at
the request of the condemned, or in a non-professional capacity) attending
or observing an execution. The attention paid to what others might consider
insignificant detail is exemplified in the provision that permits physicians
to certify death, providing that death has been pronounced by someone else,
and by restrictions on the donation of organs by the deceased.
The AMA also prohibits physician participation in torture. Participation
is defined to include, but is not limited to, "providing or withholding any
services, substances, or knowledge to facilitate the practice of torture."20The
Canadian Medical Association, while not faced with the problem of capital
punishment, has voiced its opposition to physician involvement in the
punishment or torture of prisoners. The CMA states that physicians "should
refuse to allow their professional or research skills to be used in any way"
for such purposes.21
Complicity and referral
While referral is not mentioned in the AMA policy on capital punishment,
nor in the Canadian or American policies on torture, the kind of
action involved in effective referral is the same kind of action
that is understood in those policies as illicit participation. This
demonstrates that, in principle, at least, it is not unreasonable for
physicians to refuse to provide effective referrals for patients for
procedures to which they object for reasons of conscience, on the grounds
that doing so would make them complicit in a wrongful act.
The point here, of course, is not that executions or torture are morally
equivalent to euthanasia, abortion or assisted suicide. The point is that,
when governments or professional associations are convinced that an act is
seriously wrong - even if it is legal - they are willing to refuse all forms
of direct and indirect participation in order to avoid moral complicity in
the act. This is precisely the position taken by many conscientious
objectors in health care with respect to morally contested procedures.
Complicity and dirty hands
Having considered the problem of complicity, it is now worth asking why
the subject of complicity in wrongful acts is not only of grave concern to
ethical physicians, medical journals, and professional associations, but why
it can so thoroughly arouse the public, the media, and politicians: why
commissions of inquiry will so meticulously investigate the possibility of
complicity, producing hundreds upon hundreds of pages of detailed analysis
of the evidence taken, at no little cost to the public purse.
A jaded few will respond that reports of scandal will always sell
newspapers, that scandal always energizes the self-righteous (both the
religious and the politically-correct varieties) and that scandal is one of
the traditional weapons used against opponents by politicians of all
stripes. There is some truth to this, but, going deeper into it, why is
complicity in wrongdoing scandalous?
The answer must be that there is something about complicity in wrongdoing
that triggers an almost instinctive reaction in people, something about it
that touches some peculiar, deep and almost universal sense of abhorrence.
One says "almost" instinctive and "almost" universal because, of course,
there have always been exceptions: Eichmanns, Pol Pots, Rwandan machete men,
for example. And the degree of sensitivity varies from person to person,
from subject to subject, and from one culture to another. Nonetheless,
complicity in wrongdoing can be a source of scandal, a political weapon and
the subject for public inquiries only because it has some real and profound
significance.
The nature of that significance is suggested by a number of expressions:
"poisoned" fruit doctrine, "tainted"evidence, money that has to be
"laundered," and "dirty" hands. A senior Iraqi surgeon, commenting on the
complicity of physicians in torture under Saddam Hussein, said that "the
state wanted them to have 'dirty hands'."22 In
contrast, some writers refer approvingly to a "dirty hands principle":
Philosopher Sidney Axinn tells us the Dirty Hands principle "holds
that in order to govern an institution one must sometimes do things that
are immoral." He goes on to say that advocates would claim that "we do
not want leaders who are so concerned with their own personal morality
that they will not do `what is necessary' to ... win the battle.... We
have an inept leader if we have a person who is so morally fastidious
that he or she will not break the law when that is the only way to
success" (Axinn, 1989: 138).23
But whichever view one takes of "dirty hands," all of these expressions
convey an uncomfortable sense that something is felt to be soiled by
complicity in wrongdoing. What is that something? And what is the nature of
that cloying grime?
The answer suggested by the Project is that the "something" is not a
"thing" at all, but the human person, and that the sense of uncleanness or
taint associated with complicity in wrongdoing is the natural response of
the human person to something fundamentally opposed to his nature and
dignity.
Notes
1. Parliament of Canada,
Medical Assistance in Dying: A Patient-Centred Approach. Report of the
Special Joint Committee on Physician Assisted Dying (February,
2016)
2. American College of Obstetrics and Gynecology,
Committee on Ethics Opinion No. 385,
The
Limits of Conscientious Refusal in Reproductive Medicine (emphasis
added) (Accessed 2008-09-11)
3.
Alter, Jonathon, "Time to Think About Torture."
Newsweek, 5 November, 2001, p. 45.
4. Maher's Story.
Accessed 2008-09-08
5. Commission of Inquiry into the Actions of Canadian
Officials in Relation to Maher Arar,
Report of the Events Relating to Maher Arar: Analysis and Recommendations.
(hereinafter, "Arar Inquiry: Analysis and Recommendations") p. 9 (Accessed
2008-09-08)
6. Arar Inquiry:
Analysis and Recommendations, p. 35-36 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
7.
Deputy Prime Minister Issues Terms of Reference for the Public Inquiry into
the Maher Arar Affair. (Accessed 2008-09-08)
8. Re: briefing note for RCMP Commissioner
Zaccardelli: "Assistant Commissioner Proulx states [in the note] that the
RCMP can be considered complicit in Mr. El Maati's detention in Syria.
However, Mr. Proulx testified that it was the media and public who would
consider the RCMP's actions to be complicit. He did not personally believe
that the RCMP was complicit, nor was he referring to complicity in the
criminal sense." Commission of Inquiry into the Actions of Canadian
Officials in Relation to Maher Arar,
Report of the Events Relating to Maher Arar: Factual Background, Vol. 1,
(hereinafter "Arar Inquiry: Vol. I") p. 64 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
9. "The Ambassador did not consider that seeking the
fruits of the Syrian interrogation made Canada complicit in obtaining
information that might have been the product of torture. He reasoned that he
did not ask the Syrians to continue interrogating Mr. Arar so that Canada
could obtain information. Furthermore, the Ambassador did not have any
evidence that Mr. Arar was being tortured or held incommunicado. Arar
Inquiry:Vol.
I, p. 271 (Accessed 2008-09-08.)
10. "Superintendent Killam was aware that Secretary
Powell had given Minister Graham the clear impression that the RCMP was
complicit in Mr. Arar's deportation. However, Superintendent Killam
testified that, even without making further inquiries in response to the
media reports, he was able to exclude the possibility that the allegation of
complicity might be true, because the allegation was inconsistent with the
RCMP position."Arar Inquiry:Vol.
I, p. 299 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
11. "Mr. Solomon prepared a draft memorandum for the
Minister . . .which dealt with the upcoming CSIS trip to Syria and stated .
. . "there are concerns as to whether a visit to Arar by Canadian
intelligence officials may make Canada appear complicit in his detention and
possible poor treatment by Syrian authorities." Arar Inquiry:Vol.
I, p. 309 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
"Mr. Livermore testified that the original statement about the
reliability of the confession and the possible complicity by Canada if CSIS
was to meet with Mr. Arar was "very much on the speculative side" and "it
was anticipating something that we later ironed out with CSIS, namely that
they would not seek access to Mr. Arar." Arar Inquiry:Vol.
I, p. 310 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
12. ". . . the intervenors suggest that the
circumstances under which these individuals ended up in Syrian detention
raise troubling questions about whether Canadian officials were complicit in
their detention. The evidence of what happened to them could possibly show a
pattern
of misconduct by Canadian officials." 770 Commission of Inquiry into the
Actions of Canadian Officials in Relation to Maher Arar,
Report of the Events Relating to Maher Arar: Factual Background, Vol. II,
p. 770 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
13. "Canadian officials did not participate or
acquiesce in the American decisions to detain Mr. Arar and remove him to
Syria. I have thoroughly reviewed all of the evidence relating to events
both before and during Mr. Arar's detention in New York, and there is no
evidence that any Canadian authorities - the RCMP, CSIS or others - were
complicit in those decisions."
Arar Inquiry: Analysis and Recommendations, p. 29
(http://epe.lac-bac.gc.ca/100/206/301/pco-bcp/commissions/maher_arar/07-09-13/www.ararcommission.ca/eng/AR_English.pdf)
Accessed 2008-09-08
"Although decisions to interact must be made on a case-by-case basis, they
should be made in a way that is politically accountable, and interactions
should be strictly controlled to guard against
Canadian complicity in human rights abuses or a perception that Canada
condones such abuses."
Arar Inquiry:
Analysis and Recommendations, p. 35 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
"If it is determined that there is a credible risk that the Canadian
interactions would render Canada complicit in torture or create the
perception that Canada condones the use of torture, then
a decision should be made that no interaction is to take place." Arar
Inquiry:Analysis
and Recommendations, p. 199 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
"Even if one were to accept that Canadian officials were somehow complicit
in those arrests, that would not change my conclusion, based on the evidence
at the Inquiry, that Canadian officials
did not participate or acquiesce in the American decision to send Mr. Arar
to Syria from the United States." Arar Inquiry:
Analysis and Recommendations, p. 271 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
"Information should never be provided to a foreign country where there is a
credible risk that it will cause or contribute to the use of torture.
Policies should include specific directions aimed at eliminating any
possible Canadian complicity in torture, avoiding the risk of other human
rights abuses and ensuring accountability." Arar Inquiry:
Analysis and Recommendations, p. 345 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
"Clearly, the prohibition against torture in the Convention against Torture
is absolute. Canada should not inflict torture, nor should it be complicit
in the infliction of torture by others." Arar Inquiry:
Analysis and Recommendations, p. 346 (Accessed 2008-09-08)
14. Smith, Graeme,"From
Canadian custody into cruel hands." Globe and Mail, 23 April,
2007 (Accessed 2008-09-07)
15. Editorial,"The
truth Canada did not wish to see." Globe and Mail, 2 April, 2007.
(Accessed 2008-09-08)
16. "We will have to repent in this generation, not
merely for the hateful words and actions of the bad people, but for the
appalling silence of the good people." King, Martin Luther,
Letter from
Birmingham Jail, 16 April, 1963. (Accessed 2005-08-02)
"Non-cooperation with evil is as much a duty as is cooperation with
good." Gandhi, Mahatma,
Statement before Mr. C. N. Broomfield, I. C. S., District and Sessions Judge.
Ahmedabad, 18 March, 1922. (Accessed 2005-08-02)
Editorial, "How complicit are doctors in the abuse
of detainees?" The Lancet, Vol 364, August 17. 21, 2004, p. 725-729
18. Miles, Steven H., "Abu Ghraib: its legacy for
military medicine." The Lancet, Vol 364, August 21, 2004, p. 725-729;
Lifton, Robert Jay, Doctors and Torture. N Engl J Med 351;5
19. American Medical Association Policy E-2.06:Capital
Punishment (Accessed 2013-06-24)
20. American Medical Association Policy E.2.067:Torture.
(Accessed 2008-09-08)
21. Canadian Medical Association Policy resolution
BD80-03-99 - Treatment of prisoners. Status: Approved, 1979-Dec-08. Last
Reviewed, 2004-Feb-28: Still relevant.
22. Elahi, Maryam and Kushner, Adam"Doctors
With 'Dirty Hands.'" Physicians for Human Rights Library
(Accessed 2008-09-09). Originally published in the Washington Post, 8 June,
2003
23. Hartle, Anthony E.,"Atrocities
in war: dirty hands and noncombatants - International Justice, War Crimes,
and Terrorism: The U.S. Record." Social Research, Winter, 2002
(Accessed 2008-09-08)