Tube Feeding: Medical Treatment or Basic Care?
Catholic Medical Quarterly, August, 1998
Reproduced with permission
Adrian Treloar
* & Philip Howard
*
Abstract
Tube feeding is now legally regarded as
medical treatment. The provision of nutrition
through nasogastric or gastrostomy feeding tubes is
not part of basic care according to several recent
court decisions. Despite this, doctors have
misgivings about the removal of feeding tubes and
feel that cessation of tube feeding can be a direct
cause of death. We argue that feeding tube placement
is a medical procedure and as such requires
consideration of the benefits and risks as for any
other medical treatment. However, the day-to-day use
of feeding tubes, to provide hydration and
nutrition, constitutes ordinary care that does not
require medical supervision. Withdrawal of tube
feeding raises major ethical and legal questions, as
it removes a simple channel for the provision of
nutrition. With rare exceptions, cessation of tube
feeding is done with the intention of causing death
through dehydration or starvation.
We conclude that the placement of feeding
tubes constitutes medical treatment from an ethical
standpoint. However following tube placement, a
different moral situation pertains: the provision of
feeding through such means constitutes ordinary
care. This analysis of the moral and legal
distinction between tube placement and usage
challenges the validity of some court judgements.
KEY WORDS. Tube feeding, PEG feeding, Bland
judgement.
Acknowledgements: None
Disclaimers: None
Sources of support: None
Introduction
There has been considerable debate about the
ethical nature of tube feedings: landmark judgements
in both Britain and the United States (Bland, Conroy
and Cruzan) have concluded that tube feeding is
medical treatment.(1,2,3) Since the Bland case,
several patients have had their feeding tubes
removed after judicial review. Recently the court
has agreed that a feeding tube should not be
replaced after it had fallen out in a patient who
was not in the persistent vegetative state.(4)
Nevertheless, Craig(5) has argued that death through
dehydration can be onerous for both the patient and
relatives and that there is a need to satisfy
thirst.
Despite these legal judgements, there is
persistent concern amongst doctors about the
withdrawal of nutrition as a means of deliberately
ending life.(6,7) The Law Commission8 stipulated
that 'basic care' could not be refused to mentally
incompetent patients. However, 'basic care' was
defined as the preservation of bodily cleanliness,
alleviation of severe pain and provision of direct
oral hydration and nutrition. We doubt that such
limited standards of basic care would be acceptable
in Nursing Homes or Hospitals. Some ethicists hold
that the provision of tube feeding is basic
care.(9,10) A review of the Jewish ethical
position(11) shows a consensus that tube feeding,
once instituted, may not be withdrawn. Ethical
analyses do not however appear to distinguish the
insertion and removal of feeding tubes as distinct
from their daily use to administer nutrition.We
provide two brief case histories that illustrate
some of the difficulties in providing tube feeding
before considering the ethical implications in more
depth.
Case Studies
Case 1. A thirteen year old boy with
severe cerebral palsy due to an inborn error of
amino-acid metabolism was poorly nourished. Assisted
feeding by his parents took several hours per day
with the ever present risk of aspiration.
Percutaneous gastrostomy (PEG) tube placement was
discussed with the parents. In particular, the risks
of sedation for such a severely disabled person, who
was also underweight and had a severe kyphosis, were
carefully explained. It was felt that there was a
small though definite risk of death from the
procedure, estimated at between 1 % and 5 %.
The procedure was uncomplicated. Nutrient can now
be administered either via a pump or by bolus
injection with a syringe. Tube feeding has proved
easy, and the patient is now able to go out for the
day. His nutritional status has improved
substantially. The mother describes the tube feeding
as "bliss" and sees no difference between the
administration of nutrition through the tube and any
other aspect of his basic care. Over the 18 months
since tube insertion, his respiratory difficulties
and muscular spasms have worsened. As a result it
would now be even harder to feed him without a PEG
tube. Removal of the tube or cessation of feeding
would lead to death from dehydration or starvation.
If the tube were to fall out, the mother would be
able to insert it within the first few hours (before
the stoma starts to close). If the tube became
dislodged or blocked and required replacement, the
same principles that pertained to the original
decision to insert the tube would apply, though the
risks would then be greater.
Case 2. A twenty year old woman with
cerebral palsy, severe kyphoscoliosis and asthma was
considered for PEG feeding because of chronic
under-nutrition and repeated chest infections
related to aspiration. A general anaesthetic was
deemed necessary for tube placement because of her
marked skeletal deformity and to control her airway
during the procedure. It was also felt that the
patient would not tolerate the procedure under
sedation. There was an estimated.30% - 40% risk of
dying from the anaesthetic. The parents considered
the risks were unacceptably high, and the Consultant
anaesthetist was not prepared to offer elective
post-procedural ventilation if the patient could not
be weaned from the anaesthetic. It was therefore
agreed by all not to proceed with tube insertion.
At the time of writing, the patient continues to
struggle with oral feeding, remains underweight and
is at risk from further aspiration pneumonia.
Ethical Analysis
The decision to insert a PEG feeding tube should
follow a clear discussion with the patient and/or
carers. The procedure itself carries risks that
ought to be balanced against the benefits that may
accrue for the well-being of the patient. Good
medical practice requires the consent of the
patient, or a near relative or carer in the case of
mental incapacity. Whilst the consent of a relative
of a mentally incapacitated adult is not recognised
in law(12), it is regarded as sound medical practice
to seek the views of relatives and/or carers in such
instances. (It seems likely that the procedure would
be covered by the common law plea of necessity in
the event of a legal dispute).Hydration and
nutrition are essential to all human existence.
Therefore, access to food and water is a basic human
right. Doctors, relatives and carers have a
corresponding duty to provide patients with such
sustenance. This basic form of care is not
considered ethically obligatory where:
(a) the patient is actually
dying, when the provision of tube feeding might be
considered unduly intrusive and unnecessary. (Death
from dehydration may take a few weeks, which is
immaterial to the patient facing imminent death).
(b) where the means of
providing adequate nutrition might be unduly
hazardous, as in the second case report.
Nevertheless, neither of these exceptions removes
the duty to care for the dying or severely
handicapped and to relieve mental and physical
distress.
Once the feeding tube is in place and the
provision of nutrition has been thereby facilitated,
a new ethical situation applies. There now exists a
simple means of providing life-sustaining nutrition
without due risk or burden to the patient. There is
usually no reason to withdraw feeding other than to
cause the death of the patient. Consent to feeding
via the tube is implicit in the initial agreement to
tube placement. Where the tube is deliberately
removed or feeding stopped in the knowledge that the
patient is unable to swallow, the action amounts to
causing death through starvation and could
constitute criminal negligence.
Conclusion
We agree with the Jewish position that, once
initiated, tube feeding is ethically difficult to
stop. Cessation of feeding would normally constitute
a deliberate intention to end life, unless the
patient is already in the process of dying and
further provision of hydration and nutrition is
materially irrelevant to the outcome. Patients with
feeding tubes in situ have a right to basic
nutrition and hydration: given their ease of use, we
propose that tube feeding constitutes basic care.
This conflicts with legal judgements about the use
of feeding tubes. It appears that the Bland
judgement and other similar cases have confused the
nature of tube feeding. The Bland judgement is based
upon the assumption that the use of the tube, once
placed, constitutes medical treatment and that its
use is no different from either tube insertion or
removal. Patients have died as a result of
deliberate removal of this basic form of care. We
hold that removing the feeding tube is the proximate
cause of death from dehydration or starvation. If
insertion of the tube is regarded as medical
treatment and tube feeding as ordinary care, the
ethical issues surrounding tube withdrawal and the
cessation of feeding become clearer.
References
1. Airedale NHS Trust v Bland [1993] AC 789
2. Cruzan v Director, Missouri Dept of Health,
110 Sct 2841 (1990)
3. Strasser W: The Conroy Case: An overview. In
Lynn J (ed): By No Extraordinary Means: The Choice
to Forgo Life-Sustaining Food and Water.
Bloomington, IN, Indiana University Press, 1989, p
245.
4. Doctors ask to cut life support. Re: Miss D.
The Guardian newspaper 21st March 1997.
5. Craig G M. On withholding nutrition in the
terminally ill: has palliative medicine gone too
far? Journal of Medical Ethics 1994; 20:139- 43.
6. Soloman M Z, O'Donnell L, Jennings B, et al.
Decisions near the end of life: Professional views
on life sustaining treatments. American Journal of
Public Health 1993; 14: 83.
7. Personal communication
8. Mental Incapacity. Law Commission No 231. para
5.34. Pub HMSO 1998.
9. Mellander G. On removing food and water;
Against the Stream. Hastings Centre Report
14:11,1984.
10. Callahan D. On feeding the dying. Hastings
Centre Report 13: 22, 1983.
11. Schostak R Z. Jewish ethical guidelines for
resuscitation, artificial nutrition and hydration of
the dying elderly. Journal of Medical Ethics 1994;
20: 93-100.
12. Mental Incapacity. Law Commission No 231.
para 2.18. Pub HMSO 1995.