'Bioethics' -- What It Really Means for Prolife Nurses
Presentation to the National Association of Pro-life Nurses Annual
Meeting1
Hyatt Regency in Crystal City, Washington, D.C. Copyright July 2, 2004
Reproduced with permission
Dianne N. Irving, M.A., Ph.D.
*
I. Introduction
THIS is what "bioethics"
means . . . It is not "ethics per se", but rather
"federal ethics". It is neither "neutral", nor just
a "communal conversation". It is incapable of
resolving conflicts among its very curiously
defined, utilitarian "principles", and even its
Founders agree that it just can't work. It is,
instead, a "will to power". . .
I'd first like to thank the National Association
of Pro-life Nurses very much for inviting me to be
here with you this evening. It is an honor to have
been invited, and to be able to share with you some
thoughts that concern me about the difficult
struggle you find yourself in as vital members of
the "healing professions".
To begin, let me share with you something
recently said to me by a very special prolife nurse
- we'll just call her, "Jennifer":
"Nurses are by their very nature,
compassionate people. But it is difficult to
keep that in focus with ethical issues when we
see suffering up close and personal, sometimes
on a daily basis."
Quite a very perceptive statement this good nurse
made, and it probably reflects to some extent the
sentiments of each of you good nurses here this
evening. Her reference point was the direct killing
of human patients under the guise of what is known
as "mis-placed compassion". But what I see in her
concern and confusion really goes much deeper -- a
deep-seated tension between her personal and
her professional lived-experiences on the one hand,
and "ethics" on the other. And herein is the exact
problem I want to talk with you about this evening.
When you find yourself in a situation where you and
your deepest gut instincts are so pitted against
some "theory" - any "theory" - then perhaps it is
time to stop and to question this "theory"? The
specific "theory" in question here is not really
"ethics", but, I would suggest -- "bioethics".
What is bioethics? How did it come about? How
sound is this "theory"? What impact has it had on
the practice of medicine and medical research,
especially its influence on medical professionals -
at the bedside, up-front and personal? How has
bioethics attacked the fundamental concept of
"personhood", especially as formulated in bioethics
as "preference" utilitarianism? How has it so
profoundly affected our understanding of who is a
person to the extent that we don't even know one
when we're staring one in the face - at the bedside?
II. Different ethics, different conclusions
First, just what IS "bioethics"? Most people
would say that it IS "ethics" -- just the
application of traditional philosophical and
theological principles to current technological
issues in medicine and medical research, right?
Not really. There is no such thing as "ethics per se". In the real world there are dozens of
different ethical theories, using very different
ethical norms and principles, thus arriving at
fundamentally and even contradictory ethical
conclusions - and thus different "medical ethics"
and "research ethics" conclusions. Consider that the
traditional Hippocratic medical ethics focuses on
the physician's duty to the individual patient,
whose life and welfare are always primary. The focus
of bioethics is fundamentally utilitarian, centered
on "maximizing total human happiness", or, as we
shall see, maximizing total "preferences" and
"interests" for society is primary.
To put my endeavor into sharp focus, consider for
a moment the strikingly different conclusions
reached by secular bioethics and those of a
traditional medical ethics on an array of issues.
Secular bioethics generally considers the following
as "ethical": abortion, contraception, the use of
abortifacients, prenatal diagnosis with the intent
to abort defective and disabled babies; destructive
human embryo and human fetal research; human
cloning; the formation of human chimeras
(cross-breeding with other species); human embryonic
and fetal stem cell research; "brain birth"; purely
experimental high risk research with the mentally
ill; euthanasia; physician-assisted suicide; and
living wills documenting absolute "autonomous"
consent to just about anything. In contrast,
traditional medical ethics considered all of these
unethical.
Therefore, there is no such thing as a "neutral"
ethics -- including bioethics. All ethical theories
are normative -- i.e., they take a stand on
what is right or wrong. Wouldn't it make common
sense, therefore, to wonder why any "ethical theory"
should be forced on any members of a pluralistic,
multicultural, democratic society as the basis for
public policy making?
III. The transition from traditional medical
ethics to bioethics
Given the startling differences between
traditional Hippocratic medical ethics and current
bioethics, how did we get here - historically? Well,
just after World War II, new medical research and
technologies began to complicate patient care,
thanks to massive federal funding of the health
sciences. The crucial bonds of the physician-patient
relationship were beginning to fray. Traditional
Hippocratic medicine was breaking down rapidly,
seemingly impotent in the face of pressing new
questions brought on especially by advances in
science and technology.
The Conferences
The "hot" questions we debate today in bioethics
are not that new. Starting in the 1960's there were
a series of conferences around the country on pop
control, thought control, sterilization, cloning,
artificial insemination, and sperm banks. One of the
first, the "Great Issues of Conscience in Modern
Medicine Conference" at Dartmouth College in 1960,
hosted an array of scientific and medical savants,
including the microbiologist Rene Dubos of the
Rockefeller Institute, the physician Sir George
Pickering of Oxford University, and Brock Chrisholm,
a leading medical light of the World Health
Organization, together with such famous humanists as
C. P. Snow and Aldous Huxley.
The hottest topics then too were genetics and
eugenics. Dubos declared that the prolongation of
the life of aged and ailing persons and the saving
of lives of children with genetic defects -- two
benefits of post-World War II advances in medicine
-- had created "the most difficult problem of
medical ethics we are likely to encounter within the
next decade." Geneticists worried that the gene pool
was becoming polluted because the early deaths of
people with serious abnormalities were now
preventable. The Nobel Prize-winning geneticist
Muller offered his own solution to that problem: a
bank of healthy sperm that, together with "new
techniques of reproduction," could prevent the
otherwise inevitable degeneration of the race that
might ensue thanks to medical advances that allowed
the defective to reproduce."
At another conference, "Man and His Future,"
sponsored by the Ciba Foundation in London in 1962,
the luminaries included Muller; Lederberg, winner of
the Nobel Prize in medicine; the geneticists Haldane
and Crick, and the scientific ethicist Bronowski. As
at Dartmouth, concerns about human evolution,
eugenics, and pop control were primary. The
biologist Sir Julian Huxley declared, "Eventually,
the prospect of radical eugenic improvement could
become one of the mainsprings of man's evolutionary
advance." Huxley proposed a genetic utopia that
would include strict government controls over
physiological and psychological processes, achieved
largely by pharmacological and genetic techniques.
They would also include cloning and the deliberate
provocation of genetic mutations "to suit the human
product for special purposes in the world of the
future."
Other conferences of the 1960's delved further
into the implications of science for medial ethics.
One was a series of Nobel meetings in Minnesota in
which many Nobel Prize winners participated. At the
first of them, in 1965, whose theme was "genetics
and the Future of Man," the Nobel physicist Shockley
presented his maverick views on eugenics. He
suggested that, since human intelligence was largely
genetically determined, scientists would embark on
serious efforts to raise the human race's
"collective brainpower" by various means, including
sterilization, cloning, and artificial insemination.
Also evolving during this time were new concepts of
scientific and of medical ethics - "secular" ones
that would be arrived at by "consensus" for purposes
of public policy making - as if "consensus" would be
somehow "neutral" and thus useful in our
pluralistic, multicultural democratic society. This
sort of thinking would become a major characteristic
of the new field of bioethics yet to be formalized.
The think tanks
As the 1970's approached, the debates and their
participants moved from conferences at universities
to permanent think thanks. Callahan and Gaylin set
up The Hastings Center outside New York City in
1969. There, such pioneers of bioethics as Dubos,
Ramsey, Gustafson, Renee Fox, Arthur Caplan, Robert
Veatch, even Senator Mondale and New York Times
journalist Peter Steinfels brainstormed.
The first "research groups" at The Hastings
Center likewise addressed such issues as death and
dying, behavior control, genetic engineering,
genetic counseling, pop control, and the conjunction
of bioethics and public policy. In 1971, the first
volume of the Hastings Center Report
appeared, a publication that was to become "the
Bible" of secular bioethics, just then acquiring its
name. As Al Jonsen, a pioneer of bioethics, noted in
his 1998 book, The Birth of Bioethics
(Oxford), "The index of the Hastings Center
Report over the next years defined the range of
topics that were becoming bioethics and constituted
a roll call of the authors who would become its
proponents."
Under the leadership of the Dutch
fetal-development researcher Andre Hellegers, the
Kennedy Institute of Ethics opened at Georgetown
University in 1971 (originally named the Kennedy
Center for the Study of Human Reproduction and
Development). [[I walked through its doors in 1979,
as a member of the First Generationers - the first
graduate student class in bioethics.]] Its mission
was to study the ethical issues involved in
reproductive research in a Catholic context. Such
scholars as Richard McCormick, and later, Ed
Pellegrino, worked out of the Kennedy Institute at
various times. Also in the 1970's, a Protestant
counterpart to the Kennedy Institute opened, the
Institute on Human Values, sponsored by the United
Ministries in Education, a partnership of the
Methodist and Presbyterian churches - with
Pellegrino serving as its first Director.
Many of the conference participants of the 1960's
and the think-tank scholars of the 1970's were among
those testifying before the Mondale and Kennedy
congressional hearings that led to the passage of
the National Research Act of 1974. Many in this army
of secular scholars also sat on the committee that
later issued the Belmont Report with its
three bioethics principles. Those scholars were
indeed, as Jonsen puts it, the midwives at the
formal "birth of bioethics" that the 1974
congressional act had mandated. They were also the
first formally designated "bioethicists."
IV. The formal birth of bioethics
Bioethics as understood and practiced today was
actually "created" out of thin air by a
Congressional mandate, with the passage of that
National Research Act of 1974. The Act mandated that
the Secretary of DHEW appoint a National Commission
to: [1] "identify the basic ethical principles
that should underlie the conduct of biomedical and
behavioral research involving human subjects", and
[2] to "develop guidelines that should be
followed in such research." As Jonsen, a member of
that National Commission, later perceptively noted,
"No legislation had ever before charged a government
body to identify basic ethical principles as
did Public Law 93-348."
Thus, in 1974, Secretary Weinberger appointed an
eleven-member National Commission that in 1978
issued a document called The Belmont Report,
which identified and defined these "ethical
principles": respect for "persons" (immediately
deconstructed to mean absolute "autonomy"),
"justice", and "beneficence." To this day, those
principles are called "the Belmont principles", the
"Georgetown mantra", "principlism", "federal
ethics", or simply "bioethics." Obviously, as we
have seen, deducing from these different normative ethical principles of autonomy,
justice and beneficence - especially as so curiously
defined in The Belmont Report-- will lead to
quite different conclusions about what is right or
wrong in health care, as compared to deducing from
other ethical principles.
Also, as Congressionally mandated, in 1981 the
Belmont Report immediately became the explicit
foundation for the guidelines that the U.S. federal
government was to use when assessing the ethics of
using human subjects in research. These Belmont
principles, as originally, and curiously, defined,
also underlie a host of other federal regulations
and guidelines for medicine and medical research,
and have worked their way into the private and
international sectors as well.
V. Evaluation of Bioethics
There are several misconceptions about bioethics
I would like to clarify.
1. First,
bioethics is not really just the "general
moral consensus of the people", but rather it is an
idiosyncratic systematic academic theory of
ethics alongside many other such academic
ethical theories or systems competing for
recognition in the universities -- bioethics simply
being the one that was recently made up by an
11-member, politically appointed National
Commission.
2. Second,
bioethics should not be equated with the
entire field of "ethics" per se, as often
seems to be the implication today, but again, it is
only a sub-field of ethics.
3. Third,
bioethics is not a "neutral" ethical theory
at all, but defines itself as "normative" - i.e., it
takes a stand on what is right or wrong. In fact,
there is no such thing as a "neutral" ethics - and
that includes utilitarianism, consensus ethics,
Kantianism, cultural relativism, emotivism,
casuistry, communitarianism or any religious-based
"ethics" as well.
4. Each of the three principles of the new
bioethics was defined by bioethics as prima facie:
i.e., no one principle could overrule any of the
other two. However, bioethics theory itself does not
provide a way to resolve any conflicts that arise
among its principles. In dealing with real-life
medical and scientific problems, the bioethicist was
supposed to reconcile the values of all three
principles.
5. Because the Belmont principles were derived
from bits and pieces of fundamentally contradictory
philosophical systems, the result was theoretical
chaos. More problematically, when people tried to
apply the new theory to real patients in medical and
research settings, it didn't work because,
practically speaking, there was no way to resolve
the inherent conflicts among the three principles -
other than arbitrarily.
6. The very definition of the bioethics
principles is problematic. For example, while the Belmont Report gave a nod to the traditional
Hippocratic understanding of BENEFICENCE as doing
good for the patient, it also included a second
definition of beneficence that was essentially
utilitarian: doing "good for society at large." The
report even declared that citizens have a "strong
moral obligation" to take part in experimental
research "for the greater good of society". This
obviously contradicts the Hippocratic interpretation
of beneficence, and it also violates time-honored
international research guidelines, such as the Nuremberg Code and the
Declaration of
Helsinki, which bar physicians from
experimenting on their patients unless it is for the
patient's direct benefit.
The Belmont principle of JUSTICE was also defined
along utilitarian lines, in terms of "fairness":
i.e., allocating the benefits and burdens of
research fairly across the social spectrum. This
Rawls-influenced definition is obviously very
different from the classic Aristotelian definition
of justice as treating people fairly as individuals.
Even the Belmont principle of respect for persons
- or AUTONOMY -- ended up serving utilitarian goals.
Supposedly derived from Kant's respect for persons
in which respect for the individual is absolute, the
Belmont Report blurred that idea with Mill's
utilitarian views of personal autonomy. In Mills'
view, only "persons" -- that is, fully conscious,
rational adults capable of acting autonomously --
are defined as moral agents with moral
responsibilities. However, those incapable of acting
autonomously -- infants, the comatose, those with
Alzheimer's - were to become defined in bioethics
theory as non-moral agents -- and thus as
"non-persons", with quite different "rights" than
"persons. It is only a short step from this kind of
reasoning to that underlying Princeton ethicist
Peter Singer's "preference" utilitarianism, in which
animals have more rights as persons than young human
children, and non-person humans can be used as
objects for the greatest good of society.
Eventually, discontent began to smolder within
the brave new discipline. Even the founders of
bioethics have recently admitted that the Belmont
principles present grave problems as guidelines for
health care workers and researchers. The Hastings
Center's Callahan baldly conceded that after 25
years, bioethics simply has not worked. But not to
worry, he said, we'll try communitarianism now (yet
another utilitarian theory): "The range of questions
that a communitarian bioethics would pose could keep
the field of bioethics well and richly occupied for
at least another 25 years", Callahan cheered!
Gilbert Meilaender has noted "how easily the
[reality and worth of the individual human] soul can
be lost in bioethics." National Commissioner Al
Jonsen recently wrote that principlism should now be
regarded as "a sick patient in need of a thorough
diagnosis and prognosis." And, I would argue that
until that is accomplished, our sick culture will
remain confusing and contradictory.
7. Another reason for the theoretical and
practical chaos surrounding bioethics these days is
that almost anyone can be a bioethicist - slightly
irritating to we bioethics graduate students who had
to pass at least 60 graduate credits with an "A"
average, pass three 8-hour written comprehensives,
and write a doctoral dissertation defended
university-wide! Few "professional" bioethics
experts -- the doctors, researchers, and lawyers who
sit on hospital and government bioethics committees
-- have academic graduate degrees in the discipline,
and even for those very few who do there is no
uniform or standardized curriculum to which their
degrees conform. Most professors of bioethics have
only taken a community seminar or two, don't know
the historical or philosophical roots of the subject
they teach; the courses vary wildly from institution
to institution; there are no local, state, or
national boards of examination for bioethicists; and
there are no real professional standards. There is
not even a professional code of ethics for
bioethicists.
Because of these criticisms, many nervous
bioethicists now prefer to say that their field is
more a form of "public discourse" than an academic
discipline, a kind of "consensus ethics" arrived at
by democratic discussion rather than by formal
principles. The problem with this line of reasoning
is that (1) there is no "level playing field" out
there, and (2) the ethical principles used in the
"discourse" are still exactly the same bioethics
principles with the same curious definitions, and
those who typically reach the "consensus" are the
bioethicists themselves, not the patients, their
families, or society at large, so the process is not
exactly neutral or democratic. And if bioethics is
just a "discourse," then why are its practitioners
regarded as "ethics experts" - even in the court
rooms?
VI. Erroneous science used by early bioethics
8. The use of false science propagated in
bioethics pervades many medical ethics and medical
research issues as well, and surely precludes health
care workers from accurately forming their
consciences about abortion, the use of
abortifacients, genetic pre-selection, euthanasia,
and a host of other related issues. Right from the
start bioethics has propagated its own "science" and
"medicine" in order to advance its own agenda. If
the facts don't fit the agenda, just change the
facts. Indeed, it is the erroneous "science" used so
successfully in the issues at the beginning of life
that grounded their erroneous concept of "person" -
which concept was then simply transferred without
fanfare to issues involving adults at the end of
life. In order to prevent public scrutiny of this
"conceptual transfer", bioethics relied brilliantly
on the political strategy of making any and all
public or academic discussions and debates on the
"abortion" issue politically incorrect - off-base.
No debates, no scrutiny, no problems. But the
disturbing issues concerning the end of life simply
cannot be thoroughly addressed without at least
taking a look at this "conceptual transfer".
Of note, for example, the National Commission
used several "odd" scientific definitions in its
individual reports, e.g., in its Report on Fetal
Research (1975) Even the Commission acknowledged
this: "For the purposes of this report, the
Commission has used the following definitions which,
in some instances, differ from medical, legal or
common usage. These definitions have been adopted in
the interest of clarity and to conform to the
language used in the legislative mandate" [referring
to the National Research Act of 1974!]. Among
such "unique" scientific definitions used by the
Commission was that of the "fetus" as beginning at
implantation (i.e., 5-7 days post-fertilization).
Before that there was only a "pre-embryo". The terms
"human being" and "human embryo" were never defined.
Similarly, the OPRR federal research regulations,
based explicitly on the Commission's Belmont
principles, contain two "unique" scientific
definitions. "fetus" and "pregnancy" are both
defined as beginning at implantation! Again, no
definitions of either "human being" or of "human
embryo".
Of course, such "definitions" are rather bizarre,
as the single dissenting report by National
Commissioner Louisell pointed out. Science has known
since the 1880's, with the publication of Wilhelm
His' three-volume tome, Human Embryology,
that fertilization was the beginning of the
existence of the human being, the human embryo,
using sexual methods of reproduction. Normal
pregnancy also begins at fertilization in the
woman's fallopian tube. And the "fetal period"
doesn't even begin until the 9th week
post-fertilization.
Clearly, such "odd" scientific definitions -- or
re-definitions -- in the National Commission's
Report and in the OPRR federal research regulations
would simply serve the purpose of allowing the
removal of "flushed" human embryos, and artificially
produced human embryos (through 8-weeks-post
fertilization), from any sort of governmental
protection or oversight in the future -- especially
given the growing interests in viable human embryos
as biological materials for use in IVF "research"
and "therapy". They would be especially prized for
used in human cloning, human chimera, and all human
genetic engineering research. But such "odd"
scientific definitions would also be used as the
basis for bioethics' "conceptual transfer" of
"personhood" at the beginning of life to issues at
the end of life - and all stages in-between. If, by
using such false science, a human embryo or fetus -
even a young child - is not a "person", then neither
are adult disabled human beings, or those at the end
of life.
VII. Erroneous 'personhood' theories used by
bioethics
9. The issue of "personhood" is not a scientific,
but is rather a philosophical issue. Nurses might
keep in mind that the key to understanding any
philosophical theory is to identify its
"anthropology"-- or definition of "a human being"
or "person". Different anthropologies lead to
different ethical theories - which lead to different
medical ethics theories. Some anthropologies match
reality; others don't. Reality check:
Bioethics tries to claim that its theory really
has no "anthropology". Bioethics is "just" about
"ethics". However, almost all bioethics arguments
incorporate a "personhood" claim on issues at both
the beginning and at the end of life.
Philosophically, such a claim is per se a
claim about "anthropology", and historically a very
weak and academically indefensible one at that. It
requires, e.g., that the soul and the body are two
separate and independently existing substances. But
think about it. If there is a real split or
gap between the "mind" (or "soul") entity, and the
"body" (or "matter") entity -- which is required
if there is any "delay" in "personhood" at the
beginning of life -- then one simply cannot
successfully explain any causal
interaction whatsoever between these two
separate entities, either before or even after
"uniting". Nor is there any scientific data to
verify such a "split", nor any such "delay".
A lengthy response is not practical here, but
solid arguments to refute such "delays" have been
advanced for many centuries. E.g., if, the "rational
soul" always contains virtually the sensitive
and vegetative powers of the soul; if there is no
split among the several powers of the soul itself;
if there is no split between the soul and the body;
if the body and soul must exist together as one
single substance; and if there is scientific
evidence that the "vegetative" power of the human
rational soul is present immediately at
fertilization (which there is), then the whole
rational soul must be immediately present at
fertilization - when "the matter is appropriately
organized.
Personhood must begin when the human being
begins. There is no frog, or carrot or tomato
produced at fertilization -- and we know that
empirically! Nor can this "delay" be legitimately
reversed at the end of life - first the "rational"
soul leaves, then the "sensitive" -- leaving only a
"human vegetable". Empirically there is no such
thing as a "human vegetable" - they exist only in
bioethics text books.
It is long past time for us to recognize,
acknowledge, and deal with the concrete reality that
all human beings, at all stages of life, are human
persons -- simply by virtue of their inherent human
NATURE - not because of the active exercising of
adult functions (which, BTW, must be caused by that
human nature that is already there).
To choose not to acknowledge or deal with this
information has already led to the acceptance, now
almost habitual, of a two-tiered caste of human
beings -- some of whom are "persons" and some of
whom are not. If nothing else, the Nazi "science",
rationalizations, propaganda, and concrete
experiments -- and the on-going scourge of slavery
and genocide -- should have taught us something
about the inevitable real life consequences of such
a human "caste" system.
The unheralded words of the single dissenting
National Commissioner Louisell ring ominously clear:
"American society is itself at risk -- the risk of
losing its dedication to the proposition that 'all
men are created equal.' We may have to learn once
again that when the bell tolls for the lost rights
of any human being, even the politically
weakest, it tolls for all."
VIII. International bioethics' attack on the
"sanctity of life ethic"
Although bioethics is unquestionably
predominantly a "utilitarian" ethical theory, there
are in fact many different kinds of
"utilitarianism". Probably the most common in
bioethics today is "preference" utilitarianism,
actually a deconstruction of the classical
utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill. A small sampling
of some of the most articulate in the field could
serve to indicate, in general, some of the main
dogmas they hold in common -- which dogmas nurses
currently meet on a daily basis, face to face, as
"ethics" - but never recognize their "faces".
In "preference" utilitarianism an action is
ethically correct if it satisfies the "preferences"
of those affected -- and has the best
consequences for the greatest number of "people".
Modern utilitarianism, Bernard Williams explains, is
supposed to be a system that is neutral (!) among
the preferences that "people" actually have -- a
"preference" being a reflection of the state of mind
of the agent, and not to be judged by some standard
of reasonableness other than whether it accords with
the best utilitarian theory. Therefore, all
preferences go into the melting pot, with no
preference to count for more than any other; there
must be "equal consideration of interests", as
Singer puts it. But of course ultimately, these
individual "interests" will be weighed UNEQUALLY
against the total "good" or consequences for society
as a whole -- a point about any utilitarian theory
that is often overlooked or underestimated.
Of interest is the definition of "people" or
"person" used in preference utilitarianism.
"Persons" are those who have preferences, interests,
desires, etc. For these utilitarians, not all human
beings are "persons", while some animals are
"persons".
Preference utilitarians especially need to attack
those who hold the "sanctity of life ethic" ((which
states that only human beings are "persons")), as
simply prejudiced and racist tenets of "speciecism".
As Oderberg explains the origins of this attack:
"The charge was made famous by Peter Singer and is
leveled by virtually all the followers of
Singerian bioethics". They prefer instead a
"quality of life" ethic. One way that "preference
utilitarianism" attacks the "sanctity of life ethic"
is by literally deconstructing or redefining it --
usually by means of "soft", meandering, but very
clever "thought experiments" and pseudo "logical
dialogues" that supposedly "evaluate" the "pros" and
"cons" of the "sanctity of life ethic" - all in
order to support a "quality of life" position.
Jonathan Glover:
One of the major theoreticians of "preference
utilitarianism" for many decades has been Oxford
philosopher/bioethicist/eugenicist Jonathan Glover.
In his 1977 book, Glover literally redefines the
"sanctity of life ethic" by means of redefining its
major premise. Once that major premise is corrupted,
of course, then all conclusions which flow from it
will be corrupted as well.
The "sanctity of life ethic" is generally
correctly stated as: "It is always a morally evil
act to intentionally and directly kill an innocent
human being." From that major premise it
follows, e.g., that since human embryos and fetuses
are innocent human beings, and since human disabled
and terminally ill adults are also innocent human
beings, to intentionally and directly kill them
would be morally evil actions per se --
regardless of any "personhood" status, circumstances
or intentions.
But Glover doesn't hold those actions to be "morally
evil
per se"; besides, he says, that would
impede the advancement of global "positive eugenics"
and genetic engineering which he, and most
preference utilitarians, strongly advocate. So he
redefines the major premise of the "sanctity of life
ethic" itself as follows: "It is always
intrinsically wrong to destroy
a life that is
worth living." Such a life would not be "mere
biological life", but rather, as Glover vaguely
describes it, the
quality of life of one who
consciously possesses preferences, plans, projects,
desires, feelings, memories, a sense of identity,
etc. -- what later came to be grouped together in
bioethics and labeled "rational attributes" and/or
"sentience". Only a "person" possesses a life that
is worth living. Since unborn, born, and young human
children, as well as many ill or disabled adult
human
beings,
do not have this
"quality of life", they do not have a "life that is
worth living". They are not "persons" -- and
therefore the direct and intentional killing of
these human non-persons would not necessarily be a
morally evil act. Voila! The "sanctity of life
ethic" now
is the "quality of life ethic"!
R. M. Hare:
Glover, in turn, was the academic mentor of
Oxford philosopher/eugenicist R. M. Hare. For Hare,
the early human embryo, fetus and even young child
are not "persons". They are not "real people"; they
are just "possible people" (that is, they don't
exist yet) -- and thus have no serious "interests"
or "preferences" to be respected. We do, however,
have "some" duties" toward "them". So, applying a
sort of mathematical trigonometry set theory to the
problem, his international public pop policy
proposals go like this: "The maximum duty that is
imposed is to do the best impartially for all the
'possible people' there might be by having an
optimal family planning or population policy, which
means necessarily excluding some possible people."
Indeed. Hare asserts that the best policy will be
the one which produces that set of people, of all
"possible sets" of people, which will have in sum
the best life, i.e., the best possible set of future
possible people." [[And I ask you, would you buy
a used car from this man?!]] Hare's bioethics
interests lie largely in translating the Gloverian
theory of "preference" utilitarianism into British
law and global pop policies via the UN. One of
Hare's most prominent students at Oxford was Peter
Singer.
Peter Singer:
Most bioethicists today -- to one degree or
another -- agree that a "person" is to be defined in
terms of such "rational attributes" or "sentience".
What are really "morally relevant" are "quality of
life" characteristics, "preferences", or
"interests". So too argues Peter Singer, currently
Professor of Bioethics at Princeton University's
Center for Human Values. Like Glover and Hare
before him, Singer -- the founder and first
President of the International Bioethics
Institute at the U. N., as well as the founder of
"animal rights" -- argues that the higher primates,
e.g., dogs, pigs, apes, monkeys -- even prawns -- are
persons, because they actively exercise
"rational attributes" and/or "sentience". However,
some human beings, even normal human infants,
as well as disabled and ill human adults, are not
persons.
American philosopher/bioethicist Richard Frey,
pushing Singer's logic, actually published an
article in a major international bioethics and
health care textbook that, since many adult human
beings are not persons (e.g., Parkinson's patients,
the mentally ill and retarded, the frail elderly,
etc.), and since many of the higher primates are
persons, then these adult human non-persons should
be substituted in purely experimental destructive
research in place of the higher primates who are
persons.
Interestingly enough, Singer - as a preference
utilitarian - does not believe in "rights" or
"absolute autonomy" - unless their exercise
increases the "greatest happiness for the greatest
number of people" in the world! For example, Singer
"allows" for a couple to "autonomously choose" to
kill their unborn or born human child. But if the
parents refuse, and if such an autonomous refusal
would not be in the interests of "the greatest
number of people", then he calls for the government
to step in, do its "duty", and legally require them
to do so! The same reasoning applies, BTW, to
"living wills" and euthanasia.
Recently, Singer applied his form of "preference
utilitarianism" to bestiality. He concluded that
bestiality can be an "ethically correct" action, as
long as it is not cruel, if it satisfies the
preferences (e.g., sexual pleasure)
of those
affected (i.e., the human person and the
animal),
and if it has the best consequences
for the greatest number of people involved (i.e.,
the total amount of "pleasure" experienced in the
world would be increased). And, of course, since
Singer defines many animals as "people", then "the
greatest number of people" for Singer would include
some human beings and some animals. Therefore,
bestiality can indeed be "ethical". This is surely
"theory" run amok!
Others:
Or consider the words of bioethics Founder Tris
Engelhart, "Persons in the strict sense are moral
agents who are self-conscious, rational, and capable
of free choice and of having interests. This
includes not only normal adult humans, but possibly
extraterrestrials with similar powers."
Or, those of Winston Duke in 1972 in an article
on the new biology in Reason Magazine:
"It is quite possible that the
advances in human biology in the remainder of the
twentieth century will be remembered as the most
significant scientific achievement of the animal
species known as Homo sapiens. But in order to
become a part of medical history, parahuman
reproduction and human genetic engineering must
circumvent the recalcitrance of an antiquated
culture. ... Fit the parts of the puzzle together:
nucleus transplant, test tube growth to blastocyst
and uterus implant -- the result is clonal man. ...
An Eugenic Age is just around the corner. ... Under
scientific management, the result can be human
parts-farming: the methodical production of precious
organs such as eyes, hands, livers, hearts, and
lungs. ... The foremost philosophical problem
presented by the new biology is semantical: What is
a human being? ...Humanity per se is based on
cognitive abilities. A philosophy of reason will
define a human being as one which demonstrates
self-awareness, volition and rationality. Thus it
should be recognized that not all men are humans.
The severely mentally retarded, victims of
lobotomies, the fetus, blastocysts, androids, etc.,
are not human and therefore obtain no human rights.
... It would seem ... to be more "inhumane" to kill
an adult chimpanzee than a newborn baby since the
chimpanzee has greater mental awareness. Murder
cannot logically apply to a life form with less
mental power than a primate. ... It certainly
follows that the practice of abortion is not
immoral. And it is furthermore conclusive that
experiments with fetal material and the engineering
of non-thinking Homo sapiens tissues are not
immoral. A clear definition of humanity in terms of
mental acuity, rather than physical appearance,
should be encouraged. And libertarians should
continue to defend as absolute the prerogative of
humans to conduct their own lives independent of
societal norms, whether that conduct involves
euthanasia, suicide, abortion, organ transplant, or
ownership of genetic material. ... Likewise, the
incentive for developing a rational philosophical
framework including a psychology of self-esteem will
be magnified. ... [I]t would be increasingly obvious
that a philosophy of reason is needed to meet the
test of present day living, and that it is the only
orientation able to readily absorb the ever
developing spectrum of scientific discovery."
Finally, hear Dan Wikler, as representative of
the World Health Organization, declared that "The
state of a nation's gene pool should be subject to
government policies rather than left to the whim of
individuals, ... The completion of the human genome
project would also make it possible to promote some
genetic qualities such as intelligence and lower the
incidence of others. ... It may be conceivably
required by justice itself," - i.e., "justice" as
defined for bioethics by John Rawls.
IX. What bioethics means to prolife nurses
THIS is what "bioethics" means - or should mean -
to prolife nurses. It is not "ethics per se", but
rather "federal ethics". It is neither "neutral",
nor just a "communal conversation". It is incapable
of resolving conflicts among its very curiously
defined, utilitarian "principles", and even its
Founders agree that it just can't work. It is,
instead, a "will to power", an evolution from
eugenic-minded post-war savants of science, to
eugenics we now hear echoed daily around the world
as "global health care" by like-minded bioethicists.
It advocates the violation of just about everything
traditional medical ethics held dear, and for the
deconstruction of our most genuine inherent human
rights - including, and especially, the right to
life of even the most vulnerable. Indeed, many have
argued that "bioethics" per se is not
"ethical"!
Yet THIS is the "ethics" that greets prolife
nurses at the bedside - up-front and personal, on a
daily basis --, the "ethics" that informs them which
medical actions they take are right or wrong - or
"compassionate" -- for their individual patients. It
sanctions physician and even nurse killing of the
terminally ill in the name of patient autonomy, the
use of the mentally ill in high risk destructive
medical research in the name of "beneficence", and
pop control, involuntary sterilization and abortion
in the name of "justice" - whichever principle works
- and because none of these humans are "persons".
And this is "compassion"???
No wonder you are confused and conflicted,
"Jennifer" - but the problem is not you. It is the
"ethics" that is being forced on you against your
deepest intuitions.
Listen ..... to ..... them.
Thank you.
Notes
1. Based on Irving, "What is
'bioethics?'", UFL Proceedings of the Conference
2000, in Joseph W. Koterski (ed.), Life and
Learning X: Proceedings of the Tenth University
Faculty For Life Conference (Washington, D.C.:
University Faculty For Life, 2002), pp. 1-84.