Confronting Conscientious Objection
Engaging Bioethics
The Hoya, 31 January, 2013
Reproduced with permission
Maggie Little*
What is the role of conscience in medicine? Following the public debate
last year over mandating insurance providers to cover contraception, some
have argued that it is time to expunge the category of conscientious
objection from medicine altogether. After all, it is said, medicine is not
just any business. It is a licensed monopoly, and with such licensure comes
greater responsibility. Patients in rural areas or in emergency situations
often lack the ability to choose who should care for them. And those who do
have options often have to find - or suddenly shift to - providers who can
meet what the profession itself regards as a legitimate need. Given these
issues, patients need to be protected from the harms that refusal can
engender by making provision of all basic, core services a condition of
professional licensure.
I certainly agree with the importance of preserving patient access to
basic medical services. More than that, I am among those who believe that
contraception and legal abortion should be understood as belonging to that
core. Having the option to control whether to give birth is of central
importance to women in maintaining bodily integrity and authorship over
their lives. Data shows that access to medically controlling reproduction
can have profound effects on women's health, outpacing the importance of
even such basics as anti-hypertension medication. The fact that
contraception and abortion are not approved of or sought by every woman does
not deny their importance to those women who do.
Yet I do not agree with those who would eliminate protection for
conscientious refusal. Provision of a need under one guise is commitment of
a profound moral wrong under another. By its very nature, medicine
intersects with some of the deepest issues in life and some disagreement is
inevitable. Medicine itself would be impoverished if dissenting
practitioners were not allowed into the guild.
For one, it would radically reduce the number willing to go into
specialties that already face critical shortages. Areas such as obstetrics
and gynecology can ill afford to lose compassionate, talented and skilled
providers - some of whom have profound moral misgivings about services the
profession as a whole endorses. Including those views is important to
sustaining the field of medicine as a dynamic one, with open
dialogue by its
practicing members about morally complex issues. Finally, patients who share
moral objections to certain interventions may deeply value being cared for
by a like-minded practitioner. We risk alienating not just providers, but
patients themselves, with policies mandating that medicine be practiced only
by those who share a particular perspective.
How, then, do we adjudicate the conflict? For one thing, we should insist
on high standards of conscientious objection. Properly understood, genuine
conscientious objection reflects a deeply considered position, not a mere
aversion, that provision of the service would be a grave wrong or deep
threat to integrity. It is premised on a scientifically accurate view of the
facts, not unproven assumptions. And it is based on a position that we can
understand as deserving our respect. This last is a substantive matter:
arbitrating its contours is as difficult as it is inescapable in a pluralist
society.
Conscientious objection, then, is not something lightly invoked. Its
legitimate exercise brings with it strong obligations. Objecting providers
must disclose their limitations early and often to minimize patient burdens.
And they must convey those restrictions with compassion and respect.
Communication of conscientious objection is, first and foremost, a message
about the provider, not the patient and her circumstances - and for good
reason. The very premise of protecting conscientious refusal, after all, is
that deeply good and reasonable people disagree on the issue.
Finally, there are limits to the right of conscientious objection. To
give just one example, specialists who care for high-risk pregnancies -
so-called maternal-fetal specialists - will predictably encounter women for
whom continued pregnancy is as likely to lead to maternal death as it is
not. If someone cannot, in good conscience, personally perform an abortion
in such a circumstance, then one needs to partner with willing providers
identified ahead of time - or choose a different specialty.
The requirements for and limitations to conscientious objection are
surely complex. But medicine does best when it confronts them, because needs
in medicine intersect with conflicts over values not just incidentally or
occasionally, but deeply and persistently. Those conflicts - as vexing as
they are - need to be faced with care and mutual respect.