New genetics functions as eugenics
National Post (Canada), 10 October, 2002.
This address was delivered at the McGill University conference on
Pluralism, Religion and Public Policy.
Reproduced with permission
In the past, respect for life required respect
for the life of each individual and respect for
human life in general. This basic obligation
continues, but the new technoscience is raising
unprecedented challenges even to it. And what does
respect for life require in relation to its
transmission and essence, the human germ cell line
-- the genes passed from generation to generation?
In our secular, pluralistic society we cannot, as we
did traditionally, use a shared religion to uphold
respect for life in the public square. But this
value remains essential to the protection of both
individuals and society and must be implemented at
both levels.
We have adopted intense individualism. In
relation to decision-making about reproduction,
intense individualism leads to claims of rights to
"absolute reproductive freedom," that is, claims
that decisions about reproduction are no one else's
business -- especially not the state's business to
interfere with through law -- and one should be
absolutely free to reproduce in whatever way and
reproduce whatever kind of child one wishes. That is
an adult-centred reproductive decision-making model.
But should the decision-making be, rather, future
child-centred, especially when there is a conflict
between what is best for the future parents and for
the future child?
For instance, if, as may become possible, adults
want to clone themselves or have a child made from
two ova or two sperm, should their interests in
doing so prevail over a child's right not to be
created in such ways? Is it wrong to transmit human
life other than by sexual reproduction? What does
respect for the transmission of human life require
of us?
Likewise, at the other end of life, intense
individualism supports the argument that how one
dies is simply a private matter in which no one else
-- again, especially not the state -- should
interfere, and, therefore, people must be free to
choose euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide.
But how each of us dies also matters to society
and societal values, especially that of respect for
life. Moreover, euthanasia or physician-assisted
suicide necessarily involves society's compliance
and physicians' participation. It cannot be just a
private matter.
One effect of intense individualism in the
context of reprogenetics is that the accumulation of
individual decisions are resulting in an overall
outcome that would never be acceptable as public
policy. In short, the new genetics is functioning as
eugenics, but that fact is not identified. Decisions
by individuals based on preimplantation genetic
diagnosis (PGD) of IVF embryos, or prenatal
screening of fetuses, mean we will eliminate certain
groups of people, for example, Down's syndrome
children, from our society. In short, an outcome
that would never be acceptable as public policy is
being implemented through the accumulation of
individual choices.
It is argued, in rebuttal, that individual choice
regarding the nature of one's child is not a eugenic
decision, that eugenics is only practised when a
choice is made in relation to a group or class or by
someone who is not the future parent. But is that
just sophistry?
And apart from concerns about the ethics of
eliminating any individual embryo or fetus, does
screening to eliminate Down's syndrome children
threaten our respect for human life as a society,
even though we justify each decision as being only
the choice of an individual who has the right to
make this choice?
And which other groups might be eliminated? Would
they include, for instance, achondroplastic (dwarf)
children, or profoundly deaf or manic depressive
ones? That would also be to eliminate two special
cultures and many of our most creative people.
And, likewise, would legalizing euthanasia and
physician-assisted suicide threaten our respect for
life as a society, even though we justify each
decision as being only the choice of an individual
who has the right to make this choice?
It merits noting that the unprecedented new
challenges to respect for human life we are facing
are being played out in relation to the youngest
and, often, the oldest members of our community --
genetics for the very young, euthanasia for the very
old. Perhaps that is no accident, because we often
test our principles, values, attitudes and beliefs
at the margins, and here we are doing so at the two
margins of life. We should remember, however, that
the ethical tone of a society is set by how it
treats its weakest, most in need, most vulnerable
members, not those who are powerful, able and can
protect themselves.
What ethical tone will we hand on to our near and
far-distant descendants, especially regarding
respect for human life? Our responses to the ethical
issues raised by reprogenetics and euthanasia will
play a major role in deciding that.