The Right (and Wrong) Answers
Observing Bioethics
by Renee C. Fox and Judith P. Swazey
Oxford: University Press, 2008
The New Republic (On-line
review)
Reproduced with permission
Sally Satel*
American bioethics was born out
of a desire to be relevant. The philosopher Daniel
Callahan has said that he and his colleagues founded
the Hastings Center-the premier bioethics think
tank-in 1969 because they wanted to give philosophy
"some social bite, some relevance." Whether
bioethics has achieved its goal is the urgent
question at the core of this useful book,
co-authored by Renée C. Fox, a highly distinguished
sociologist, and Judith P. Swazey, a respected
historian of medicine. Between them, Fox and Swazey
have spent many decades as participant observers in
the house of medicine. Their intensive involvement
with physicians, theologians, and philosophers has
given them ringside seats to the development of
modern bioethics. Through enjoyable interviews with
major figures in the field and a rich trove of
personal observations, the book perceptively, if
densely, chronicles the growth of bioethics as a
profession.
If success is measured by breadth of
institutional footprint, then bioethics has indeed
succeeded. Major universities house bioethics
centers that offer a plethora of both graduate and
undergraduate programs. Bioethicists serve on
hospital ethics committees and on research review
boards. In many hospitals, bioethicists are "on
call" to offer guidance on whether certain
life-prolonging treatments should be initiated or
withdrawn. In the public policy arena, bioethicists
are appointed to presidential commissions and state
and federal task forces that formulate guidelines
and advise politicians.
By other measures of relevance, however,
bioethics certainly falls short. Though clearly fond
of the bioethicist-physicians,
bioethicist-philosophers, and bioethicist-legal
scholars they interviewed, Fox and Swazey describe
themselves as "critical of what we regard as the
field's deficiencies and blind spots." They identify
these as the use of dumbed-down teaching formulae,
an insensitivity to cultural differences, and the
tendency of American bioethicists to emphasize
"individual rights, and rationality" instead of
"community, and common good," which are the values
that Fox and Swazey favor.
The matter of ethical expertise-what it looks
like, who can claim it-is a profound one. Bioethics'
place in the academy, in the clinical realm, and in
society turns on it. For most of us, the very idea
of "right" answers to complex moral and
philosophical dilemmas such as euthanasia, embryonic
stem cell cloning, or organ remuneration is absurd
on its face. After all, deriving an "answer" depends
upon which type of moral theory one favors.
Fox and Swazey have faith that expertise in
ethics does exist, but they believe that such
expertise will not be fully realized until
bioethicists take on matters of social justice.
Disconcertingly, they are not concerned that a
social justice agenda risks blurring the lines
between disinterested ethical analysis (the
authentic expertise of bioethicists) and outright
political activism. This oversight is made even more
peculiar because the authors seem quite
appropriately exasperated by some of the day-to-day
perversions of ethics "expertise." Ask almost any
hospital physician about bioethicists and you will
get, in reliable sequence, an eye roll, a sigh, and
then an earful of anecdotes about swaggering cowboys
posing as arbiters of right and wrong ("Wizards of
Oughts," as one critic put it). In the media, the
coverage of almost any biomedical controversy is
sure to contain a quotation from a bioethicist with
oracular pretensions. The unmistakable message of
ethics punditry is clear: anyone who disagrees with
us is thoughtless or unethical.
Such arrogance discomfits some bioethicists as
well, as Fox and Swazey note. Erik Parens regrets
the popular view of the ethicist as "priggish or
foolish enough to lay claim to how other people
should lead their lives." Fed up with Homo
bioethicus, Carl Elliott, a physician and
bioethicist, has remarked that "Many people working
in and around bioethics wince if someone called them
a 'bioethicist.'… Some resist the aura of
professionalism and moral expertise that the term
bioethics seems to imply. Others are just
embarrassed by the incivility and glibness of our
public spokespeople. Others just don't want to be
viewed as the ethics police."
This raises a larger question. Is it politically
desirable for society to credit bioethicists with
expertise in resolving the most difficult moral
questions? Fox and Swazey say yes, but only if
bioethicists revise their mission. Instead of
concentrating on issues surrounding biomedical
technology, such as cloning, sex selection,
nanotechnology, and so on, bioethics should address
"inequalities in health and in access to health care
in American society." The field should become "more
centrally and deeply involved with [global]
suffering and … issues of social justice.
Ruth Macklin, a self-described "liberal,
humanitarian bioethicist," told the authors, "I
acknowledge that my chief concern is in striving for
greater social justice within and among societies,
and reducing disparities in health, wealth, and
other resources among populations in the world."
These are noble sentiments, yes. But what particular
authority or particular skill do bioethicists
possess that allow them to add much in the way of
unique scholarship, practical wisdom, or ethical
reflection that is not already being applied today,
for better or worse, by experts in international
development, global health economics, and political
theory? Fox and Swazey do not answer this question.
They simply assume that bioethicists bring a needed
perspective.
This is not to deny a productive role for applied
ethics in modern life. Bioethicists can be great
educators of students and physicians and
policy-makers. When an expert in bioethics
approaches a problem, such as an end-of-life
decision, he brings a deep knowledge of the cultural
history of that controversy and the relevant legal
decisions. This allows him to draw analogies to
current situations. He is skilled at delineating
conflicts, laying out the assumptions behind
different positions, evaluating the soundness of
arguments, and reflecting upon potential
consequences.
Granted, many bioethicists endorse this as the
proper role for bioethics. But they must compete to
be heard in a field with widely divergent
understandings of itself. Are we a field of
scholarly inquiry, bioethicists ask themselves, or a
learned profession, a consultancy, a form of
policymaking or activism, an oversight apparatus
that monitors researchers and physicians, a
discourse, a project, or a collection of questions
or issues? What training should a bioethicist
receive? Should our field take stands on mainstream
political issues, such as the war in Iraq or the
crisis in Darfur? Are we excessively beholden to the
institutions we serve?
Fox and Swazey portray bioethics as a field in
turmoil. It suffers, the authors observe, from being
"overly impressed with its importance" and steeped
in a culture of "self-congratulation." But at the
heart of such self-conscious ceremony, they astutely
speculate, lies professional insecurity. Fox's and
Swazey's own prescription-to expand the bioethics'
franchise into global justice and activism-will not
help. Bioethics would become politicized, thereby
undermining the already shaky credibility of the
field.