Six questions about
physician-assisted death, from a conscientious
objector
Forcing doctors to knowingly
send their patient to another doctor willing to
cause the patient's death will seriously
compromise the moral integrity of
conscientiously objecting doctors.
National Post, 14 April, 2016
Reproduced with permission
Ewan C. Goligher*
Canadian policy makers have recently proposed
to require all doctors to provide an effective
referral for physician-assisted death (PAD) upon
the patient's request. Forcing doctors to
knowingly send their patient to another doctor
willing to cause the patient's death will
seriously compromise the moral integrity of
conscientiously objecting doctors and risks
undermining the quality of patient care. To
understand the position of conscientiously
objecting doctors, consider the following
questions.
1. Should doctors provide
physician-assisted death merely because it is
legal?
Doctors should provide PAD only if it is both
legal and ethical. The Supreme Court has ruled
that PAD ought not to be legally prohibited, but
it cannot define whether it is ethical for
doctors to intentionally cause death. In their
decision on the legality of PAD, the Supreme
Court Justices stated that "nothing in this
decision would compel physicians to provide
assistance in dying." The Justices recognize
that we need not automatically accept that PAD
is ethical in the wake of this sweeping change
in law.
2. Must all doctors accept the
assumptions underpinning the claim that
physician-assisted death is good medical care?
Advocates for PAD contend that death should
be used to treat suffering because for some
patients, death is better than life. This
assumes some notion of what it is like to be
dead. Yet the medical profession has no idea
what it is like to be dead. All beliefs about
the afterlife (including the belief that there
is no afterlife) are metaphysical
(quasi-religious) beliefs which cannot be
confirmed or refuted by scientific medical
evidence. Thus PAD is innately experimental and
its outcomes are hidden from us. Though there is
always a measure of uncertainty in medicine,
medical care must be based on evidence and
observation and sound reasoning, and doctors
should not be forced to practice medicine based
on untestable quasi-religious assumptions.
The case for PAD also assumes that respect
for the patient's wishes, rather than respect
for the patient as a whole, is the foundational
value of medical ethics. Respect for the
patient's wishes is unquestionably part of
respecting the patient, but valuing these wishes
above the patient herself would prevent doctors
from ever refusing any patient request, even if
it would clearly harm her health. The
long-accepted firm foundation for medical ethics
(including the duty to respect the patient's
wishes) is the incalculable intrinsic objective
worth of the patient. Intentionally causing
death would require us to render valueless that
which is of essential value: the patient.
In sum, given the tenuous assumptions
underpinning the case for PAD, doctors need not
accept that PAD is good medical care.
3. If physician-assisted death
remained illegal, would doctors be legally
liable for making an effective referral?
If a father were to request that his daughter
undergo circumcision (i.e. genital mutilation),
and I deliberately provided an effective
referral to a willing physician, I would be
complicit in an extremely grievous breach of
medical ethics. This scenario is not ethically
identical to PAD but it effectively illustrates
the moral and ethical responsibility attached to
an effective referral. This moral responsibility
is recognized in law: doctors are legally liable
for referring a patient for a procedure that is
forbidden by law, even if requested by the
patient (as was the case for PAD until now).
Knowingly referring a patient to a physician
willing to cause the patient's death makes
doctors complicit in that death. Therefore, if
upon considered moral reflection we find that
PAD is unethical, we ought not to provide
referrals for PAD.
4. Does the Charter right of Freedom
of Conscience apply to doctors?
Some argue that doctors cannot claim the
Charter right of Freedom of Conscience because
we willingly accept responsibilities and duties
that limit our freedom when we commit to care
for the patient. Accordingly, doctors are
duty-bound to deliberately cause death upon the
patient's voluntary request. This argument is
successful only if PAD is ethical: the
commitment to care does not extend to providing
unethical care. Doctors are duty-bound to ensure
that their patient's suffering is relieved by
all effective means available. Whether this
commitment entails a duty to cause death is a
controversial moral question contingent upon
certain philosophical assumptions. Those who
insist upon a duty to refer for PAD impose their
personal ethical beliefs and assumptions upon
others. The freedom of individuals to decide
this issue and to act in accordance with one's
deeply held moral beliefs is precisely what the
Charter right of Freedom of Conscience protects.
5. How does respect for conscientious
objection affect patient care?
Even given the assumption that PAD is
ethical, robust respect for conscientious
objection is still ultimately good for patients.
Patients entrust themselves to their doctors,
and doctors must be worthy of this trust. The
doctor's moral integrity—a commitment to acting
in accordance with moral norms—is foundational
to his/her trustworthiness. Suppressing
conscientious objection prizes moral conformity
over moral integrity and systematically teaches
physicians to suppress their basic moral
intuitions in favour of constantly evolving
social conventions. It also teaches the
profession to be less sympathetic of and
tolerant toward patients' diverse moral beliefs.
Thus, robust respect for conscientious objection
should be viewed as an important public good
that upholds the quality of medical care.
6. Will respect for conscientious
objection obstruct access to physician-assisted
death?
Upholding respect for conscientious objection
to PAD need not present a significant obstacle
to obtaining PAD. Making referrals mandatory
does not immediately guarantee access as PAD
will not be routinely provided by any particular
medical specialty and many in the medical
community do not know physicians willing to
accept such referrals. Conscientious objectors
have proposed simple solutions allowing patients
to refer themselves for PAD, and this may in
fact be the most reliable means of facilitating
access. Yet policy makers have disregarded such
proposals to this point. Carefully considered
policy frameworks for providing PAD can show
robust respect for conscientious objection while
enabling universal patient access.
Dr. Ewan Goligher practises intensive
care medicine in Toronto. The views expressed
here are his own and do not necessarily reflect
the views of any institutions with which he is
affiliated. Visit
http://www.canadiansforconscience.ca to
learn more.