Bioethics and natural law: an interview with John Keown
BioEdge,
8 March, 2016
Reproduced under Creative Commons licence
Xavier Symons John Keown
*
Bioethics discourse is often divided into two broad
categories: utilitarian perspectives and so-called deontological
or Kantian approaches to ethics. An alternative viewpoint that
receives far less attention is a natural law perspective on
ethics and medicine. The natural law approach emphasizes
interests or ends common to all members of humanity, and offers
a teleological account of morality and human flourishing.
Professor John Keown of Georgetown University's Kennedy
Institute for Ethics recently co-authored a book on natural law
with the late Georgetown Professor Alfonso Gómez-Lobo. The book
is entitled
Bioethics and the Human Goods: An Introduction to Natural Law
Bioethics. The Deputy Editor of BioEdge, Xavier Symons,
interviewed Professor Keown about his latest work.
Xavier Symons: What led you to write
Bioethics and the Human Goods: An Introduction to Natural Law
Bioethics?
John Keown: The book was largely written by
my distinguished colleague and friend, the late Professor
Alfonso Gómez-Lobo, who held the Ryan Chair in Metaphysics and
Moral Philosophy at Georgetown. Before his untimely death at the
end of 2011, he had submitted a manuscript to Georgetown
University Press. With the kind permission of his widow, and
with the approval of the Press, I completed the project,
incorporating amendments that he had indicated, in his comments
on the referees' reports, that he wanted to make, and some
amendments that I thought appropriate. About a third of the book
is material I added to his original manuscript. I thought it
important, given the regrettable dearth of introductory books on
bioethics from a natural law perspective, that his manuscript
should be enlarged, updated and completed
What contribution do you think natural law can make to
the field of bioethics?
Natural law has made, and has the potential to make in
future, a signal contribution to the ethics of healthcare and to
bioethics more broadly conceptualised. Natural law theory could
be described as the most enduring and important moral tradition
in Western thought, and it has had a profound influence on
Western law, professional medical ethics, and culture.
Many laws and codes of ethics are grounded in the natural law
articulation of certain fundamental moral principles that should
always be respected, regardless of the consequences. For
example, in relation to euthanasia, the prohibition on
intentionally killing patients, which is still reflected in the
law of the vast majority of jurisdictions, and in the ethics of
the World Medical Association, is grounded on one such
principle: the principle that it is always wrong intentionally
to kill a person, even at that person's request.
Unlike other approaches to bioethics, most notably
utilitarianism, natural law theory can offer a coherent account
of the intrinsic wrongness of treating patients in certain ways,
such as intentionally killing them, lying to them, or exploiting
them, however beneficial it might be to others or to society to
do so.
Moreover, although utilitarianism and 'principlism', in their
various forms, are undoubtedly dominant in bioethics education
today, it is important for students to realise that there is an
alternative ethical tradition, one which makes sense of much of
contemporary law and professional ethics, and which offers a
radically different approach to bioethical reflection. Indeed,
it seems to me that no student can understand bioethics (or,
indeed, biomedical law) properly without at least a basic grasp
of natural law theory. Without such a grasp, they have at best a
partial understanding of the field. I fear that the many
students of bioethics who are unfamiliar with the natural law
tradition do not even know what they do not know.
Unfortunately, although the literature on bioethics is vast,
that literature largely either ignores natural law theory,
mentions it only in passing, or misunderstands it. There is,
therefore, an important and urgent need for this book, and more
books like it.
I have lost count of the number of times I have been asked
'Could your recommend a clear, introductory book on natural law
bioethics, suitable for the college student or the general
reader?' Now, I have a ready answer. Previously, I recommended
one or two books like Professor Gómez-Lobo's Morality and
the Human Goods (Georgetown University Press, 2002).
However, although that book does touch on a number of bioethical
issues (especially abortion and euthanasia), it is more an
introduction to natural law ethics rather than natural law
bioethics. Still, it would make an excellent companion
volume, and I think students would find it valuable to read it
before reading Bioethics and the Human Goods.
The book mentions 'basic goods' and their importance for
natural law theory. What are they and why are they so important?
The starting-point for natural law theory is to ask 'What is
the Good Life?' It rejects standard utilitarian answers, whether
in terms of pleasure or the satisfaction of desires, both of
which could be used to justify obviously immoral acts. The
answer given by natural law theory is that the Good Life is a
life which involves true human fulfilment or flourishing. And
what is a truly flourishing life? One in which one participates
in the goods of life, health, friendship, knowledge,
appreciation of art and beauty, work, play and practical
reasonableness. (The precise formulation of basic goods may vary
depending on which theorist one reads, but the theorists share
the same, basic idea.) These goods are 'basic' in the sense that
they are not merely instrumental goods, but are ends in
themselves, worth pursuing for their own sake, and
self-evidently so. (Of course, basic goods like health and
knowledge can also be instrumentally valuable, but that does not
reduce their worth to mere instrumentality. It is, for example,
good for us to know about bioethics, or the history of the
American Revolution, or one's own personal history, even if one
never uses that knowledge instrumentally.)
The basic goods form an objective basis for natural law
ethics, but they need to be supplemented by intermediate moral
principles, intermediate between the basic goods and our
judgment about the ethics of particular conduct ('Is it right
for me to tell the patient he is fine when I know he is dying?'
'Should I allow the patient's refusal of consent to prevent me
from carrying out harmless and potentially ground-breaking
research on her while she is anaethetised?') Much of
Professor Gómez-Lobo's book Morality focused on the key
principles of 'care' and 'respect'. In Bioethics he
reformulates them in terms of 'beneficence' and
'non-maleficence'. In doing so, he recognises the influential
'four principles' approach advocated by Professors Tom Beauchamp
and Jim Childress, but he explains how those principles are
conceived and applied from a natural law, rather than from a
principlist, perspective. He rejected the 'four principles'
approach on the ground that it failed to give a substantive
account of the Good. Without such an account, he argued, it is
impossible to judge what truly benefits or harms another.
In your book you suggest that, although natural law
theory is compatible with major religious traditions, it is not
grounded in religion. Can you explain?
Adherents of the great religions will find much in natural
law that resonates with their teachings, such as its insistence
that all human beings share a fundamental equality-in-dignity,
including the most vulnerable, whether babies, people with
profound intellectual disabilities, the comatose, the demented,
the suffering and the dying.
For example, natural law theory's opposition to infanticide
(in contrast to its endorsement by leading utilitarians)
resonates with the long-standing opposition to infanticide in
the Judaeo-Christian tradition (in contrast to its endorsement
by the ancient Greeks and Romans). Natural law thinkers
reject the 'dualist' notion of personhood, in which only some
human beings, with certain mental abilities, count as 'persons'
and others, like babies or elderly folk with severe dementia, do
not. Moreover, natural law theory is the philosophical
tradition of the Catholic church. Further, my brother
Professor Damien Keown has, in his many publications, noted
similarities between natural law ethics and Buddhist ethics.
Despite these resonances between natural law theory and
teachings of the great religions, however, natural law theory
remains a philosophy, not a theology. It traces its origins to
pre-Christian Greek thinkers like Aristotle, and is reflected in
contemporary human rights documents in what many would describe
as our post-Christian world. Anyone can, and many do,
adopt natural law's absolute prohibitions on, say, torture or
euthanasia, without having any religious belief whatsoever. In
short, natural law is grounded on reason, not faith.
Is there not some distance between natural law theory and
a detailed practical ethics? How can a medical practitioner use
it to address thorny ethical issues in clinical practice?
There is always a distance between theory and practice,
whichever ethical theory one adopts. But, partly because of the
centuries-long history of the natural law tradition, much of the
intellectual heavy lifting about its application to practical
situations has already been done. That rich storehouse of
reflection has shaped our laws and codes of professional ethics,
whether in relation to carrying out research on patients, to
treating or withholding treatment, and to killing or not
killing.
That is not to say that natural law has figured out
definitive answers to all the bioethical questions clinicians
face in the contemporary world, but many of these questions are
largely old questions in a new form. For example, the question
of the moral status of the human embryo in vitro may
have seemed utterly novel to many, but natural law theorists
have been reflecting on the moral status of human embryos in
vivo for centuries. Again, the question whether to
withhold or withdraw tube-feeding from a patient in PVS may,
again, seem completely new and to require us to invent new
ethical principles, but to natural law thinkers the answer lies
in applying established ethical criteria which ask whether
tube-feeding is a medical treatment and, if so, whether it is
disproportionate as being either futile or too burdensome. This
is not to suggest that the answers to such questions are easy,
and will always attract consensus (even among natural law
theorists) but it is to say that even challenging, contemporary
bioethical questions can be resolved by the intelligent
application of well-established principles.
In any event, we should not forget that most clinicians, most
of the time, are not confronted with complex, thorny bioethical
issues. Most bioethical issues they face in everyday
practice are fairly easily resolved by the application of
established principles and codes of bioethics, such as those
requiring informed consent and respect for confidentiality. And
those principles and codes often reflect, to a greater or a
lesser extent, natural law thinking, which requires respect for
the basic rights and equality-in-dignity of each patient, not
least the vulnerable, and that patients never be used as a mere
means to the good of others.
What would you say to natural law critics of the 'new'
natural law theory which has been championed by philosophers
like Grisez and Finnis?
Professors Grisez and Finnis (and their collaborators, not
least Professor Boyle) have been largely responsible for the
exciting renaissance of natural law theory over the past 35
years or so. They would resist the label 'new' natural law on
the ground that their theory is but a modern restatement of
classical natural law theory. Not all natural lawyers would
agree with that, but it seems to me that many of the criticisms
are based on misunderstandings of the 'new' natural law project.
This is one reason I co-edited (with Professor Robert P George
of Princeton) a Festschrift in honour of John Finnis, (Reason,
Morality and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis) which was
published by Oxford University Press in 2013, to allow both
supporters and critics of his new classical theory to engage
with him, and him with them.
In any event, college students and health care professionals
interested in learning the basics of natural law bioethics may
well find disagreements about whether and if so how the new
classical theory of natural law differs from the old rather
abstract and abstruse, and I would encourage them to start with
some of the more introductory books and articles on natural law
bioethics, written by scholars including Christopher Kaczor,
Christopher Tollefsen, David Oderberg, Luke Gormally, David
Jones, Helen Watt and, of course, the late Alfonso Gómez-Lobo.
This article is published by John Keown and Xavier Symons and BioEdge
under a Creative Commons licence. You may republish it or translate it free
of charge with attribution for non-commercial purposes following
these
guidelines. If you teach at a university we ask that your department
make a donation to BioEdge. Commercial media must
contact BioEdge for
permission and fees. Some articles on this site are published under
different terms.