Is Bioethics Ethical?
The Weekly Standard,
28 May, 2000.
Reproduced with the permission. For more information on subscribing
to The Weekly Standard, please call 1-800-283-2014 or visit the website.
Decision making has been
quietly co-opted by bioethics, a genre of
philosophical discourse practiced by an elite group
of academics, philosophers, lawyers, and physicians,
many of whom are openly hostile to the sanctity of
life and the Hippocratic traditions that most people
still take for granted.
The case of James H. Armstrong, M.D. v. The State
of Montana should have been merely a skirmish in the
never-ending national struggle over abortion.
Instead, relying on the reasoning of certain experts
in the moral choices surrounding health care, the
Montana Supreme Court issued in October 1999 a
sweeping decision that could make huge changes in
the way Montanans live and the way they die.
What happened in Montana is happening across the
country, usually less dramatically but nonetheless
steadily. The United States has a bad case of
expertitis, and for many years we have been ceding
to experts control over our public decisions. Now
the most important questions about health care have
been added to the list. Decision making has been
quietly co-opted by bioethics, a genre of
philosophical discourse practiced by an elite group
of academics, philosophers, lawyers, and physicians,
many of whom are openly hostile to the sanctity of
life and the Hippocratic traditions that most people
still take for granted.
Bioethicists spend much of their time arguing
with one another, beneath or, more accurately, above
the public radar, in arcane academic journals,
books, university symposia, and government-appointed
commissions. This is no empty intellectual
enterprise, but a project aimed at changing America.
In the course of their arguments, bioethicists are
arriving at a consensus about the course of our
medical future, and they are slowly succeeding at
transforming the laws of public health and the
ethics of clinical medicine in their own image.
At issue in the Montana case was a state law
requiring that doctors (as opposed to
physician-assistants) perform all abortions. This
the court unanimously overturned; but it didn't stop
there. Writing for a 6-2 majority, Justice James C.
Nelson went on to impose a radical philosophical
imperative on the people of Montana, unwarranted by
the facts of the case and
unnecessary to its prudent adjudication. Indeed,
Nelson's audacious opinion will be grist for
litigation in Montana for many years to come.
Its essential holding is this: The Montana
Constitution broadly guarantees each individual the
right to make medical judgments affecting her or his
bodily integrity and health in partnership with a
chosen health care provider free from government
interference. As the two justices who objected to
the scope of the ruling, Karla M. Gray and Chief
Justice J.A. Turnage, warned, the Court's opinion
sweeps so broadly as to encompass and decide such
issues as the right to physician-assisted suicide
and other important health and medical-related
issues which simply were not litigated in this case.
Gray and Turnage's trepidation is abundantly
warranted. If the ruling means that virtually
anything goes medically in Montana so long as a
patient requests it and a health care professional
is willing to provide it, then patients can ask
doctors to kill them for organ-donation purposes,
parents or guardians can secure the killing of
disabled infants, and people can volunteer to be
experimented on in dangerous ways that are currently
illegal, all this as a result not of a considered
decision by the people of Montana but of a
little-noticed ruling by the state supreme court.
As it happens, the Montana constitutional
convention that created the state right to privacy
in 1972 explicitly refused to include abortion and
other medical issues in the privacy guarantee. So,
to justify its ruling, the court looked to
precedents like Roe v. Wade, the 1973 U.S. Supreme
Court decision that legalized abortion nationwide.
Even more than on case law, however, the Montana
court relied on philosophical treatises. In
particular, the authority it cited most frequently
is the book Life's Dominion: An Argument About
Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (1993),
by the attorney and bioethicist Ronald Dworkin.
Dworkin's thesis is that true adherence to a
modern understanding of the sanctity-of-life ethic
requires that all of us be permitted to decide for
ourselves about abortion and euthanasia and that our
decisions be accepted by society and tolerated by
those who disagree. Otherwise society is
totalitarian. The majority opinion in Armstrong
cites Life's Dominion so many times and applies its
reasoning so enthusiastically that Ronald Dworkin's
philosophy may now be considered the court-mandated
health care creed of the state of Montana.
Dworkin's triumph in Armstrong v. Montana
illustrates the growing influence of bioethics. To
become a bioethicist isn't hard. No tests have to be
passed; practitioners are not licensed, like
attorneys, physicians, real estate agents, and
hairdressers; and, while more than 30 universities
offer degrees in bioethics, there are no standards
of excellence that generally apply. A Catholic
priest may be a bioethicist, as may an atheist
college professor. Health care professionals such as
nurses and community ombudsmen may get appointed to
hospital ethics committees, take a few training
courses, and call themselves bioethicists. Indeed, I
could say that I am a bioethicist, having written
and lectured extensively on the ethics of assisted
suicide and the withholding of medical treatment
from dying and disabled people.
The mere designation, however, does not give one
influence within the bioethics movement. That is to
say, there is a very big difference between being a
bioethicist and subscribing to the ideology of
mainstream bioethics. It is the adherents of the
ideology who matter and who hold a steadily
increasing sway over the laws of public health, the
application of medical ethics, and the protocols
that govern hospital care.
This phenomenon is relatively new. It began about
30 years ago as an intellectual exchange among
medical ethicists, philosophers, and theologians
with widely varying views about how to resolve the
dilemmas presented by the growth of technological
medicine. In the early years, there was a robust
contest for the heart and soul of the movement.
Adherents of human equality and the sanctity of
life, such as the late Paul Ramsey, were pitted
against utilitarians who emphasize the quality of
life, such as the late Joseph Fletcher, the
patriarch of modern bioethics. Over the years, the
Ramsey school made crucial contributions, most
notably, helping promote the right to refuse
unwanted medical treatment, but steadily lost
influence. Today, mainstream bioethics is
substantially homogeneous in outlook, and the
primary differences among bioethicists concern the
proper ways to apply generally agreed-upon values to
health care policy and individual medical decisions.
It is in this sense that bioethics has become an
ideology, albeit one that not every bioethicist
shares.
In order to have clout within the bioethics
movement and seriously affect the discourse that is
its hallmark, one must subscribe to its intellectual
underpinnings. Pro-lifers have no influence, by
definition, and those whose advocacy is rooted in
religion are usually ignored. Mainstream bioethics
reached a consensus long ago that religious values
are divisive in a pluralistic society and thus have
little place in the formulation of public policy.
Those who believe in abortion rights but also hold
that all born humans are equally endowed with moral
worth, along with those who subscribe to the do no
harm ethos of the Hippocratic oath, have little
impact, since mainstream bioethics rejects
Hippocratic medicine as paternalistic and shrugs off
equal human moral worth as a relic of the West's
religious past.
In mainstream bioethics, human beings per se have
no special rights or moral value. The movement as a
whole no longer thinks in that idiom. Instead, it
overwhelmingly embraces a quality-of-life ethic that
requires individual humans to earn their moral and
legal rights by displaying certain cognitive
capacities. This is usually described as achieving
the status of a person. As we shall see, the
criteria for personhood are still a matter of debate
among bioethicists. But the notion that personhood
rather than humanness is what counts in determining
moral worth and legal rights is nearly universally
accepted within the mainstream movement and has been
taught in American universities and colleges to a
whole generation of students. Bioethics ideology
rejects person status for newborns, people with
severe brain damage, and those with dementia, all of
whom it regards as beings of lesser worth than those
with more developed frontal lobes. There is serious
debate within bioethics, however, whether to extend
personhood to some animals (nonhuman animals, in
bioethics parlance), even as it is being stripped
from some humans.
Part of what makes this alarming is that the
values and presumptions of bioethics ideology are
not shared generally throughout society. Unlike
adherents to this ideology, most people believe that
being human in and of itself confers a special moral
status. Most people view a newborn infant as having
the same moral worth as all other humans and want
their doctors to subscribe to the Hippocratic oath.
This means that, as the government, the law, and
organized medicine rely increasingly on expert
bioethicists to supply the answers to public policy
dilemmas in areas such as cloning, stem cell
research, health care rationing, and organ
procurement for transplantation, those answers are
likely to be based on beliefs not generally shared
by the people affected. More and more, public
policies and medical protocols are likely to
conflict with, rather than reflect, the values of
the citizenry.
If bioethics ideology is out of step with
mainstream American thinking, however, it is
entirely consistent with the mindset of the elite.
As Daniel Callahan, one of the movement's pioneers,
wrote in the Hastings Center Report in 1993, the
final factor of great importance in bioethics'
success was the emergence ideologically of a form of
bioethics that dovetailed nicely with the reigning
political liberalism of the educated classes in
America.
It is not surprising, then, that movement
bioethicists have become among society's most
powerful members or that their work affects American
culture from top to bottom: They serve on federal
and state public policy commissions. They write
health legislation. They teach the next generation
of doctors, lawyers, business executives, and
government policy makers in our institutions of
higher learning. They are paid by HMOs to consult on
issues such as when desired medical treatment can be
withheld or withdrawn unilaterally. They direct
hospital and nursing-home ethics committees that
make or influence decisions ranging from whether to
withhold treatment from premature infants to whether
to pull feeding tubes from stroke patients who are
not dying. They testify as expert witnesses in court
cases and submit friend of the court briefs in legal
cases of major significance, thereby affecting the
evolution of law. They serve on institutional review
boards that oversee the ethics of medical
experiments using human subjects. They help write
protocols governing organ procurement. Occasionally,
their work leads to startling lurches in the law, as
in Montana. More typically, their advocacy erodes
ethical standards and values slowly, as waves
transform shorelines, through a succession of subtle
changes in public policy and medical ethics, a
process known within the movement as policy creep.
What makes this especially worrisome is that once
a policy is formally adopted or embedded in law, it
has the power to modify the beliefs of the people it
affects. Thus, the patriarch, Joseph Fletcher,
viewed the field expansively, as determining how we
are to live and act, a wisdom he deemed specially
appropriate to the medical sciences and medical
arts. Some bioethicists see themselves as the
creators of a new moral paradigm that will replace
the archaic Judeo-Christian order as the
philosophical underpinning of society.
To appreciate fully the mindset of bioethics and
the consequences that will flow from its growing
influence on public policy, one need only look to
the journals in which its leading thinkers
communicate with one another and with their
colleagues in the trenches of American medicine in
physicians' offices, on hospital ethics committees,
at consultancies advising nursing homes where
bioethics values affect everyday decisions. Two of
the most prominent journals devoted exclusively to
bioethics are the Hastings Center Report, a
bimonthly published by the bioethics think tank the
Hastings Center, of Garrison, New York, and the
Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, a quarterly
published by Georgetown University. Although not
every article in these publications embraces
bioethics ideology, the vast majority do. These
journals channel the discussion in a definite
direction.
The December 1999 issue of the Kennedy Institute
of Ethics Journal is a case in point. It
concentrates on the continuing debate over
personhood. A person, the journal's introduction
says, is someone morally considerable who is the
subject of moral rights and merits moral protection.
Most people would say that all human beings qualify.
The authors of several articles disagree.
The lead author, John Harris, the Sir David
Alliance professor of bioethics at the University of
Manchester, in England, claims that it is necessary
to establish the criteria for personhood so as to
identify those sorts of individuals who have the
ëhighest' moral value or importance. It is not life
per se that is dispositive, but life of such quality
as to bring [individuals] into the same moral
categories as ourselves. Being human alone does not
do the trick: Personhood theory creates castes of us
and them, in an explicit hierarchy of human worth.
Harris makes a rather astonishing assertion,
considering the brouhaha over abortion. He baldly
states that human life begins at conception. This,
of course, does not mean he opposes abortion to the
contrary. Remember, it is not human life that
matters in personhood theory; human beings do not
deserve special status merely because of their
species. Harris blandly denigrates unborn human
life: The human embryo and fetus, he writes, in all
stages of its development from conception to birth
is no more interesting or complex than the embryos
of other creatures and indeed no more interesting
than the adult forms of other creatures, for example
cats and canaries.
Harris next opines that the exploration of who is
a person must include animals, because the exclusion
of fauna from personhood deliberations would be
arbitrary and an act of speciesism, a claim of
superiority based on species, which Harris considers
as disreputable as an assertion of superiority based
on race, gender, nationality, religion, or any other
nonmoral characteristic.
So, who (or what) should duly be deemed a person?
To Harris, a person is a being that can value
existence. This means persons might, in principle,
be members of any species, or indeed machines. He
explicitly states that fetuses and newborn infants
are not persons, nor are people with significant
cognitive disability or dementia.
The ultimate purpose of personhood analysis is to
determine whom we can kill and still get a good
night's sleep. Harris writes, "Persons who want to
live are wronged by being killed. Nonpersons or
potential persons cannot be wronged in this way
because death does not deprive them of something
they value. If they cannot wish to live, they cannot
have that wish frustrated by being killed." So much
for the moral wrongness of murdering newborns and
throwing them into trash dumpsters.
In the same issue of the Kennedy Institute of
Ethics Journal, Georgetown's Tom L. Beauchamp,
co-author with James F. Childress of one of the most
influential bioethics textbooks, Principles of
Biomedical Ethics, also writes about personhood,
taking a different route to essentially the same
destination as Harris. Beauchamp asserts that the
key to determining personhood is analyzing whether a
being enjoys moral personhood, which he calls both a
cognitive and moral-capacity criterion for
possession of moral rights. He writes, "It is safe
to assume that a creature is a moral person if (1)
it is capable of making moral judgments about the
rightness and wrongness of actions and (2) it has
motives that can be judged morally."
Beauchamp, like Harris, asserts that under his
theory, unprotected persons would presumably include
fetuses, newborns, psychopaths, severely
brain-damaged patients, and various demented
patients. Beauchamp does not believe that moral
personhood should be the sole basis for moral rights
or that animals can be moral persons, but he does
assert that humans who are not moral persons may be
treated with the same levels of respect or
exploitation as animals are now; some humans are
equal or inferior in moral standing to some
nonhumans. If this conclusion is defensible, he
writes, we will need to rethink our traditional view
that these unlucky humans cannot be treated in the
ways we treat relevantly similar nonhumans. For
example, they might be aggressively used as human
research subjects and sources of organs. In other
words, Beauchamp holds out the prospect that we may
someday exploit living infants and cognitively
disabled human beings as if they were mere natural
resources.
The November-December 1999 Hastings Center Report
focuses on the ethics of expanding organ procurement
from non-heart-beating cadaver donors, that is,
people who have died from cardiac arrest instead of
brain death. Much of the discussion has to do with
how long doctors should have to wait after a heart
stops beating before judging the donor dead for
purposes of organ procurement and still be in
compliance with the dead donor rule, which requires
that donors of vital and non-paired organs be dead
before having their organs procured. (Many
bioethicists want to discard the dead donor rule, to
increase organ availability, but that argument is
not made here.) Some organ centers currently wait
only two minutes after the cessation of the
heartbeat to procure organs; a recent bioethics
panel recommended five minutes. The arguments are
important, but arcane, and would take too long to
explain here.
That said, the ultimately utilitarian approach of
mainstream bioethics is much in evidence. John A.
Robertson, holder of the Vinson Elkins chair at the
University of Texas Law School, where he teaches
criminal law, constitutional law, and bioethics,
makes an audacious proposal. He notes that until and
unless law and medical ethics discard the dead donor
rule, as many bioethicists urge, it will be
impossible to use such people as anencephalic
infants (babies born with most of their brains
missing) or unconscious people as vital-organ
donors. Even with the dead donor rule in place,
however, Robertson suggests that single kidneys and
some other body tissues could be harvested from such
people, who would not be directly harmed by such
use.
Again, the proposal is to use cognitively
disabled people as mere natural resources. One
wonders whether the New Mexico woman who recently
woke up after being unconscious for 16 years would
have objected had she awakened to learn that one of
her kidneys and her corneas had been taken from her
on the theory that the loss of them could not harm
her.
Like ruminating cows, bioethicists earnestly chew
and rechew their ideas until they have explored
every nuance, considered every implication, and the
movers and shakers of the movement have achieved
consensus about a particular approach. When that
point comes, public policy often changes fast:
Notice the speed with which removing feeding tubes
from unconscious, cognitively disabled people became
ethical and legal throughout the country once
bioethicists agreed it was no different morally from
withdrawing antibiotics.
If mainstream bioethicists tread gingerly in
pushing their agenda into policy, it is for fear of
a public backlash, provoked by what bioethicists
jokingly call the yuck factor. For those of us who
believe that bioethics is directing us down immoral
and dangerous paths, this fear of the light offers
the best hope of an antidote. Since it is almost
surely too late to transform the movement's
utilitarian assumptions from within, keeping the
movement contained inside the academy appears to be
the most promising strategy to prevent our society
from being remade in bioethics' image. To do this
will require heightened media scrutiny and public
awareness of what ideological bioethics is, what it
stands for, why it matters, and what consequences
will befall us all if the new medicine becomes our
future.
That is easier said than done, of course. But
there are ways. The ideology could be engaged
vigorously, from the grass roots to the academy to
the halls of Congress. Philanthropists could be
persuaded to endow academic chairs dedicated to
exploring human equality as the basis for health
care law and policy, much as bioethics chairs are
used to promote the quality-of-life agenda.
Politicians, devoted to their constituents' welfare,
could resist the bioethics tide. Nonprofit groups
could be formed to follow the bioethics movement,
publish journals, engage the proponents in public
debate, and alert the media to particularly noxious
developments. The popular media, especially
television and radio talk shows, could recognize the
urgency of covering bioethics as seriously as they
cover politics. After all, are not issues like
personhood and the harvesting of organs from living
people as compelling as tax policy and welfare
reform?
Beyond the media, a counter-bioethics movement
could be created by those who believe that the only
truly moral way to resolve the dilemmas with which
bioethics grapples is by strict adherence to
universal human equality.
Perhaps this new, ethical bioethics could be
called human-rights bioethics. It would boldly
promote the proposition that there is no them and
us; only us. Surely, an abundance of academics,
physicians, lawyers, disability rights activists,
patient advocates, theologians, and just plain
people would be willing to stand up proudly for the
equal moral worth of all living people. For now,
their rallying cry could be: No more Montanas.