Are "Values" the Same as Virtues?
Centrepoints, Vol. 2, No. 2, Article #1, Fall, 1996
Reproduced with permission
Iain T. Benson, B.A. (Hons.), M.A. (Cantab.), LL.B.
*
"Search for values brings boomers back to church;" so ran the heading of
a recent Vancouver Sun article. The journalist interviewed various people
who had left the church while young, but later brought their own children
back. A church leader said the reason some young families are returning to
church is that "they want some help in fostering values for their children."
A mother of young children stated that it is at church that children can
learn "what's right, what's wrong" so as to get a "moral education...." Are
these two people speaking about the same kind of things? Are "values" and
"right and wrong" the same thing? It will surprise some people to realize
that "values" is a term that obscures moral discourse rather than furthers
it and that the term entered our language very recently. We all know, after
all, that in contemporary usage, "you have your values and I have mine." A
difference in "values" is virtually expected and no cause for concern.
So what does it mean when people speak of "Women's values" or "Christian
values" or "Family values" as if the capitalized word in each phrase implies
something that is objectively true? Precious little. In a values framework,
those who think they are standing up for something like "family values" are
actually squatting. The hopeful person at a school board meeting who thinks
he or she is communicating something true when they speak of "Christian
values" is mistaken. In the current climate, such an expression of view ends
up sounding like this: "I speak of the values that a Christian like me
holds." Yawn. Next speaker please.
When the woman in the above article said she hoped that her children
would learn about "right and wrong" when they got a "moral education," she
was not speaking the same language at all as those who speak about values
clarification in the schools. Attaching such terms as "Christian," "social,"
"Charter," or "women's" to the term "values" does not overcome the essential
relativism of a values framework, and so, completely undercuts the objective
good which the speaker thinks he or she is expressing. Each one is, after
all, merely a personal (or group) value - if I am not of that group, there
is no reason objectively why I ought to support the "value." And the content
of values is, by definition, merely personal. The fragmenting tendency of
such an approach to society is obvious.
What has not yet been sufficiently noted is that this "values" language
has gradually overtaken the place previously occupied by the more robust
framework of virtue and character education. "Values" are valid in relation
to such things as aesthetic choices or what type food we prefer but we must
be careful not to reduce the moral order to a question of merely personal
preference. "Virtues", on the other hand, have specific application to an
individual person in terms of that person's nature (Sally may be more
courageous than Robert, thereby exhibiting more fully the moral virtue of
courage). The virtue of courage would be discussed as something, in a sense,
beyond each. All properly informed people would recognize the common and
particular aspects of the virtues because they had been taught to recognize
and describe them. Now educational materials in the public school (and most
private schools) assist children in the task of "clarifying their own
values" instead of teaching them. As such, it conforms them to chaos instead
of informing them about meaning.
Now we make our own "values" rather than conform ourselves to "virtues"
as the categorical aspects of an overall (and therefore shared) goodness. In
such a situation, where reasoned debate itself is considered unnecessary in
the face of power politics, we all have reason to fear a "values" approach
that appears moral but is essentially relativistic. Yet, due to the
lamentable watering-down of education over the past century, what was once
basic to education and culture itself, is now largely lost. Since politics
depends on culture and culture depends on the character of a people, a
recovery of the tradition of the virtues is essential. A suspicion of reason
goes hand in hand with a deeply ambiguous use of "values."
Perhaps a reasoned explanation of virtue will go some way to restoring
confidence in both.
The writers of the classical period had various lists of virtues and
divided them in different ways. Aristotle, for example, divided all the
virtues into those that were moral (having to do with character) and those
that were intellectual (having to do with the mind). Though others mentioned
these virtues as important, it was a Christian thinker, Thomas Aquinas, who
grouped four key virtues together as the cardinal virtues: justice, wisdom
(prudence), courage (fortitude), and moderation (temperance or
self-control). The term cardinal comes from the Latin word cardo (a hinge)
because all the other virtues pivoted on these four. Wisdom was called the
"charioteer of the virtues" because it guided all the other virtues.
Finally, "Grace perfects nature" and the theological virtues of faith, hope,
and charity came to be seen as the supreme virtues, with the greatest of
these being charity.
The concept of the mean (or "golden mean") recognizes that the virtues
are the mean (or middle) between two extremes. Thus, courage is the mean (or
middle way) between rashness (too much) and cowardice (too little). All
errors with respect to the virtues involve either an excess or a deficiency
of the virtue in question. Depending on our natures, we might have to move
towards courage from either side of the mean. This is true for all the
virtues and presents the drama of each person's development of a virtuous
character. Aristotle observed that an understanding of particular virtues
was more helpful than simply being urged to "do good and avoid evil." The
same applies to holiness. It is helpful to examine and practice the specific
aspects that together make up a holy life.
That is the essence of the virtuous life - a dynamic rooted in the
reality of our natures and the moral life. Great stories (scriptural and
other) provide examples for reflection and education but need the "grammar"
that the teaching of the structure of the virtues can provide. The
difficulty is in getting access to such teaching nowadays. True education,
as Augustine noted, is to learn what to desire. Since many obviously desire
to be better informed about "virtues" and have been more or less suspicious
of "values" language, it is hoped that the works listed below will provide
some assistance in beginning the essential task of recovery and development
of a robust understanding of virtue and character.
- Peter C. Emberley, Values Education and Technology: The Ideology of
Dispossession (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1995)
- Stanley Hauerwas, Vision and Virtue: Essays in Christian Ethical
Reflection (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974)
- Peter Kreeft, Back to Virtue (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1992) n
Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Press, 2nd. ed., 1984)
- Joseph F. Power, "[George]Grant's Critique of Values Language" in
Larry Schmidt ed. George Grant in Process (Toronto: Anansi, 1978), pp.
90-98
- "Virtue and Vice" and "Habit" (and Scriptural references for each)
in Mortimer Adler, ed. Syntopicon Vols. 2 & 3 of Great Books of The
Western World (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc., 1952)
- "The Virtues" and "The Moral Law" in the Catechism of the Catholic
Church (1993), para. #1803 - 1845 and #1950 ff
Centre for Cultural Renewal:
was an independent, not-for-profit, charitable organization that helped Canadians
and their leaders shape a vision of civil society. To this end, its focus was
on the important and often complex connections between public policy,
culture, moral discourse and religious belief, and production of discussion papers, forums and lectures on key issues affecting Canadian society, public policy and culture. Centrepoints was the newsletter of the Centre