The Clash of Universalisms: Religious and Secular in Human Rights1
The Hedgehog Review, Fall, 2007
Reproduced with permission
Abdulaziz Sachedina*
The Moral Foundations of Human Rights
In the last three decades, especially since the early
1970s-when the social and political upheavals in the Muslim world occurred and the rise of
militant religiosity among some Muslim groups began-there has been sustained interest
in the foundations of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and its compatibility
with Islam. A number of books and articles in Arabic and Persian, written by some
prominent traditionalist interpreters of the Islamic revealed texts-like Muhammad al-Ghazali among
Egyptians and Ayatollah Ja'far Subhani Tabrizi among Iranians, to mention
only a few-underscore the attention and interest the international document has
attracted among champions of Islamic tradition. The major thrust of Islamic critique
of the Declaration, however, is its secularism and its implied hostility to divergent
philosophical or religious ideas. The secular foundation of the Declaration is deemed
epistemologically insufficient to account for the derivation of inherent and inalienable human
rights. Perhaps the sore point in the secular human rights discourse, as far as Muslim
theoreticians of rights language are concerned, is the total dismissal of anything
religious as being an impediment to the modern development of human rights.2
It is a mistake to think that Muslim thinkers, even the most
traditionalist among them, are against the need for universal human rights to
protect human dignity and human agency in the context of a nation-state today.
Even the staunchest opponents of the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, who
regard the document as being morally imperialistic and culturally ethnocentric,
concede the fact that human beings have rights that accrue to them as humans.
3Human rights language is modern, firmly rooted in a secular
liberalism that safeguards and promotes citizens' rights and that demands
privatization of religion from the public sphere to allow the development of a
politics independent of religion. This secularization of the public sphere is
absent in Islamic juridical and theological anthropology. Human beings are
not conceived in terms of compartmentalized individuals who can separate the
spiritual from the temporal in their persons and keep the former from
interfering with their everyday lives. Consequently, the secularism that
undergirds the Declaration does not translate into an Islamic idiom without
raising serious questions about the relationship of religion to the state. More
importantly, the overriding emphasis on the autonomy of the individual, with an
independent moral standard that transcends religious and cultural differences,
to claim rights without considering the bonds of reciprocity runs contrary to
the Islamic tradition's emphasis on the community and relational aspects of
human existence.
Ongoing Muslim criticisms of the Declaration as being
prejudicially anti-religious and politically hegemonic are founded upon a
rejection of the universal claim of secular morality. These criticisms can be
best tackled by looking at the philosophical and metaphysical issues
undergirding the international document that can find resonance in Islamic
philosophical theology. However controversial, I believe that a frank exchange
about the universal moral foundation of human rights will provide a corrective
to Muslim perceptions about the intended secularist bias of the Declaration.
Engaging traditional Muslim scholars in rethinking their anti-Declaration stance
and challenging them on their own terms to recognize that Islamic revelation and
the Declaration share a common moral terrain to protect individuals from
oppression will aid the overall goal of the universality of the secular document
in garnering support for its implementation in the Muslim world.
Without engaging those who disagree with these universal
principles and their cross-cultural application, universal human rights will
lack the necessary legitimacy and enforcement in the Muslim world. As long as
the moral and metaphysical foundations of human rights norms remain
unarticulated, they will be easily dismissed as yet another ploy to dominate
Muslim societies by undermining their religiously based culture and value
system. Moreover, since the rise of Islamic political consciousness in the
post-colonial age, Muslim authorities, for various reasons, have found it
legitimate to dismiss compliance with some articles in the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights by labeling them as "imperialistic" or
"culturally Eurocentric." As it stands, the Declaration is viewed as being
insensitive to particular Muslim cultural values, especially when it comes to
speaking about individual rights in the context of collective and family values
in Muslim society.
Foundationless Human Rights?
There is a context to every text. Human rights declarations
provide a good example of this observation. The language that was constructed at
the height of European colonialism over the ruins of the two World Wars and
atrocities committed by humans against humans (under various pretexts of racial
or religious claims of superiority of one people over another) could not have
evolved without some kind of soul-searching into the moral and spiritual
heritage of the colonizers (the power wielders and political brokers of the
1940s). The historical backdrop of the period should make it possible for
researchers of the human rights debates and deliberations to indicate the moral
and philosophical foundations that ultimately provided a language of
international justice across cultures and peoples of the world. However modern
the human rights idiom might be, it could not have emerged in a
philosophical-theological vacuum without serious search into the ideas that lent
themselves to the universal language that was needed to bind the peoples of the
world together in their commitment to redress the wrongs that were committed
against civilians and innocent bystanders. The drafters of the Declaration were
fully aware of the traditional communities and their ability to live together
with some kind of overlapping consensus that dictated the pragmatic need to
avoid endless conflicts and destruction of human life and environment. The
post-World War II nations were in search of even more exact universal language
to propose ways of protecting humans from indiscriminate violence and oppression
resembling the anti-Semitism that led to the horrors of the Holocaust.
I will examine two studies in order to make a case for an
urgently needed dialogue between secularist and religious claimants of universal
norms that attach to humans solely as humans. The first is Johannes Morsink's
TheUniversal Declaration of Human
Rights: Origins, Drafting, and Intent (1999), and the second is Michael
Ignatieff's Human Rights as
Politics and Idolatry (2001), both written around the fiftieth anniversary of the Declaration.
They have raised the most intriguing question that continues to be debated even
today, namely, whether there is a single moral foundation for human rights that
spans many cultures, many culturally specific moral foundations, or no moral
foundation at all.
My working assumption is that without a universal morality that
speaks to each and every person on this earth, the Declaration will
lack moral enforcement in the world community. To ensure that the
Declaration will continue to protect an individual's inalienable human
rights, its advocates need to state time and again the unshakeable universal
moral foundation of the Declaration and its ability to speak to peoples
of different traditions and cultures, without denying them an opportunity to
affirm or deny that universalism in the name of some comprehensive religious
doctrine. The ultimate support for the Declaration cannot simply come
from its pragmatic purpose of protecting human agency; rather, it must come from
the reasons as to why that personhood deserves to be protected from the unjust
conduct of those in power.
In The Universal
Declaration of Human Rights, Morsink meticulously and sensitively
traces the drafting of the Declaration, stage by stage, showing in
clear contours the thought process and the universal language that emerged to
capture and express international concern for the oppressed, the poor, and the
politically powerless of the world. Religious and humanitarian traditions had
already established a vocabulary that could be appropriated for the
Declaration. Morsink responds to the charge of ethnocentrism levelled
against the Declaration by tracing the complex and complicated negotiations that
took place to avoid any ethnocentric or particularistic language that would have
defeated the very purpose of the Declaration. He examines the language
of the Declaration to investigate the presumption that there was a
connection between the Declaration and Enlightenment ways of thinking about
morality that was universal and at the same time secular. But this secularism
was not totally non-religious in the sense that nature and reason-"the two
secular components of the triad-were still kept in close proximity to the God
from which they flowed."4 The
Enlightenment view of humanity was derived from natural rights philosophies,
which located human equality and inalienable rights in human beings simply by
virtue of their own humanity and not because of some extraneous reason. However,
in pursuit of a universal morality to support human rights across traditions,
the drafters pursued thorough-going secularism and kept the language of the
Declaration free from any religious idiom. Most strikingly they severed God from
nature and reason. Paradoxically, while the search for universality through the
secularization of human rights norms paved the way for pluralistic sources of
morality, it also led to their inevitable relativity.
The problem of relativism in the context of human rights
standards and values is an old one. Practical experience of life in societies
with very different cultures has been at the root of relativism in international
debates about standards of justice across state boundaries. It is accurate to
say that despite all of the intellectual efforts at a thorough secularization of
universal morality, it has been difficult, if not impossible, to build consensus
over the common standards for the entire human race in international
conventions. Moreover, detaching universal morality from any foundational
consideration in order to accommodate diverse cultures and national communities
has, unfortunately, served as a pretext for ignoring the universal thrust of the
human rights document across different Muslim countries where, time and again,
political authorities have used cultural relativity to justify their lack of
commitment to promote certain freedoms for their Muslim, as well as non-Muslim,
citizens.
An immediate corrective to this persisting problem depends upon
articulating the link between the secular values expressed in the document and
the philosophies of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment. These philosophies
influenced the conceptualization of the inherent attributes of the human person.
It is significant to note that such topics are also the focus of Muslim
theological ethics (and not necessarily juridical studies) and acceptable to the
traditionalist Muslim authorities. To be sure, those who participated in the
drafting of the Declaration were looking at the issue of protecting human rights
from their particular historical experience and cultural context. They were
responding to the carnage inflicted upon the victims of World War II and the
Holocaust in the early 1940s. As Morsink shows in admirable detail, each article
of the Declaration was responding to the urgent need to protect human personhood
in all its manifestations in the social and political contexts of nation-states.
It is quite revealing that there was minimal Muslim
participation in the process. There was no real effort to expound comprehensive
Islamic doctrines to get the sense of the tradition's stance on different
articles. Further, as the profiles of the different representatives from
participant Muslim countries like Saudi Arabia, Pakistan, and Syria reveal, the
representatives from Muslim countries were secularly educated individuals, who
had little or no human rights training in the foundational sources of Islamic
tradition and could not adequately articulate the universal impulse of Islamic
comprehensive doctrines that would have enriched the debates. In fact, Jamil
Baroody, the Saudi representative in the drafting committee, was a Lebanese
Christian and lacked even the basic Islamic credentials to speak on any
theological aspects of Islam authoritatively.
The deliberations were not inclusive of all the diverse trends
in traditionalist interpretations of religious notions, including even those of
Western Christian theology. The exclusion of Muslim traditionalist
representation in the human rights deliberations at this early stage could have
been a political decision since most of the Muslim countries were dominated by
Western colonial authorities who had a negative view of the Muslim seminarians,
whose opposition to the colonial political and cultural domination could have
derailed the secular and anti-tradition tone of the human rights deliberations.
This lack of serious Muslim participation, however, has continued to cast a long
shadow of doubt over the cultural and political contours of the Declaration
that reveal an indubitable secular-Western bias.5
This bias is evident in the second study that deals with Islamic
encounters with Western human rights. In Ignatieff's treatment of the Islamic
challenge in Human Rights as
Politics and Idolatry, he
argues for a pragmatic approach to human rights. His liberal secular stance
relies on a presupposition that there is a common denominator of rationality
that remains when the particularities of one's religious convictions are
bracketed or suppressed. He treats human rights as "pragmatic political
instruments" that should aspire to be effective before they aspire to be more
comprehensive in their pronouncements. Religious reasons, in Ignatieff's secular
evaluation, do not count as properly contributing to a human rights discourse.
Protections against cruel, inhuman, and degrading treatment should constitute
the purpose of human rights. Moreover, according to Ignatieff, to believe in
human rights does not entail believing that they exist independently of
human purpose. All we need to believe is that human rights are important
instruments for protecting human beings against cruelty, oppression, and
degradation. Hence, there is no need to believe and insist on a divine or
natural source for human rights. Ignatieff understandably denies human rights
any creedal status, lest they become the source of a new humanist idolatry.
However, this denial of a single moral foundation or multiple
moral foundations that span many cultures and traditions for human rights has
led to the prevailing suspicion in traditionalist Muslim circles that the
Declaration is nothing more than the continuation of a colonialist, hegemonic
discourse that imposes its will through a human rights regime.6
There is no doubt that human rights can serve a multitude of purposes,
and those purposes can be expressed in many ways, not only across different
societies and cultures, but within them as expressions of a plurality of moral
assessments of human agency. In order to defend human rights in traditional and
religious societies, it is imperative to establish the reason why human beings
have rights in the first place. In Muslim culture the emphasis is on
responsibilities, without any mention of rights. Although there is a purpose to
human life, the purposive agent simply fulfills his or her duties in society to
make sure that justice prevails in all human undertakings. Claims about human
dignity or respect owed to human beings are viewed strictly within the larger
social good and not independent of it. At the same time, Islamic doctrines speak
about the creation of human beings as equal, sharing parentage, and endowed with
honor and dignity as "children of Adam."
Ignatieff's prescription to forgo foundational arguments rooted
in human dignity, divine purposes, natural law, and related philosophical and
moral ideas would function as a conversation stopper in Muslim societies where
human rights can be more readily defended by claims about human dignity and the
equal creation of human beings by God. Human beings are created with intuitive
reason and an innate capacity to know right from wrong. Yet, they are in need of
constant guidance from God to fulfill their true roles in society. The
relationship between human agency and human dignity is the result of the
purposive creation of humanity, with a goal to guide it to create a just public
order. By avoiding such foundational arguments because they are unimportant to
"pragmatic political instruments" to further human rights, the Declaration
exposes itself to an unintended relativism that suggests that ultimately each
culture and people will determine the valuation of human agency and protect what
they believe to be in
accord with their moral
judgment.
The drafting of the Declaration clearly shows that there were
several key sources for the writing of the articles that are now enshrined in
the document. What made it possible for this
lingua franca of human
rights to emerge was their convergence, rather than the upholding of a single
cultural or philosophical tradition, even though, as some Muslims have argued,
modern, secular values formed the core of the norms that informed human rights.
It is common to assume that arguments about human agency, dignity, and natural
law tend to be quite philosophical and abstract, and it may therefore be
tempting to assume that not much of practical importance is at stake. But such
an assumption would be rash. What is at stake in determining the foundations of
human rights is often the very legitimacy of human rights talk among Muslim
religious scholars. A human rights regime that takes into consideration and
promotes an overlapping consensus is more compatible with respect for many
cultural and philosophical traditions that converge in support of a similar set
of human rights. This convergence between, for instance, Islamic and secular
humanist traditions is not complete or perfect, but neither is the convergence
on human rights from within a modern, secular cultural or philosophical
tradition.
Ignatieff 's doubts about the need for a metaphysical foundation
for human rights arise in response to abstract claims about human beings having
an innate or natural dignity, or having been endowed with natural and intrinsic
self-worth, and hence, being inviolable. These abstract claims, Ignatieff
argues, are controversial and detrimental to advancing human rights. In his
words, such propositions may weaken the reinforcement of human rights. "Far
better," he argues, "to forgo these kinds of foundational arguments altogether
and seek to build support for human rights on the basis of what such rights
actually do for human
beings."7
This is a fundamentally flawed argument at the international
level when attempts must be made to resolve the controversial aspects of the
Declaration's moral foundations in order to build an overlapping consensus among
different cultures and metaphysical positions to enlist the full cooperation of
various peoples and governments to do something more than just paying lip
service to human rights. Moreover, one of the major problems confronting the
secular document from an Islamic point of view is the charge of relativity
against the Eurocentric sources of the Declaration. This charge of relativism
cannot be taken lightly, and the only way it can be overcome is by recognizing
the need for dialogue with other claimants of comprehensive doctrines, whether
religious or secular. The ultimate goal of this conversation is to reach a
consensus about human agency linked to human dignity as a special mark of
humanness that is entitled to inalienable human rights.
Ignatieff fails to understand that different cultures and a wide
variety of civilizations, despite their fundamental disagreements about such
matters as what constitutes a good human life, have never denied the existence
of injustices that are committed by the powerful against fellow humans. More
importantly, as Jeffrey Stout has shown in his
Democracy and Tradition,
conflicting religious conceptions of the good in the public sphere, however
problematic, do not in any way diminish the role of public reason in building
overlapping consensus in pluralistic societies.8 An appeal to a metaphysical
foundation for human nature that leads to recognizing common moral terrain among
divergent cultural groups may actually enhance the validity of a minimum dignity
to which all humans are entitled by the simple fact of being created equal.
Hence, diverse and sometimes divisive religious validation of what is good is
not detrimental or obstructive to the search for a shared belief in what it is
to be a human being and what norms can be identified in different faith
communities that are compatible with the protection of human dignity and agency.
However, Ignatieff maintains that the universal commitments implied in human
rights can be compatible with other comprehensive doctrines only if the
universalism implied in the Declaration is self-consciously "minimalist."
This is problematic in the international communities where there
is no agreement about the "thin" and "minimalist" commitments, which are
dependent upon "thick" and "maximalist" descriptions of the comprehensive
doctrines held by different communities. As a world community with much to
converse about its achievements (and failures), Muslims have a lot to contribute
to the Eurocentric discussions of human rights. They can become full
participants in the development of human rights and put their forces behind the
"minimalist" universalism if they can demonstrate both to their faith
communities around the world and the international community that it is
unhelpful to dismiss Islamic or any other comprehensive religious doctrine as
parochial or relativist with no impact whatsoever in the development of human
rights.
The foundational sources of Islamic doctrines in the Qur'an and
the tradition share the universal language of morality and human agency,
including human dignity. In the Muslim world, the legitimacy of the Declaration
is being challenged as an affront to the God-centered worldview about the ends
of human agency and dignity. Even if the bias of human rights advocacy can be
directed toward the victim, and the test of legitimacy-and hence universality-is
what might be termed the "victim's consent," the West's selective advocacy of
human rights in certain regions of the world to the exclusion of others, and the
endless, institutionalized violence against certain groups, has ended up
devouring the minimal legitimacy that human rights had among Muslims and has not
resulted in furthering the rights of minorities or women in the Muslim world.
People cannot help themselves or protect their agency without the support of the
traditional authorities that provide legitimacy to the state authorities who
have constantly trampled upon the rights of their own people, while dismissing
the universal claim of the international conventions. If it can be shown
that Islamic doctrines share the universalism of human rights, however
minimalist, then we will have opened a door for real conversation about
secularist and Islamic notions of human agency and human dignity for the
protection of abused individuals. Without this fundamental theoretical
breakthrough in the foundational aspects of human rights, the credibility gap
between the international document and the Muslim world will continue to widen,
making it farfetched to believe that individuals in traditional societies with
strong communitarian ties could ever exercise the minimum understanding of their
capacity to protect their rights against autocratic states and their agencies.
I agree with Ignatieff's statement that human rights matter
because they help people to help themselves. Nevertheless, this statement is
based on Western liberal confidence in the empowered individual who, having been
brought up in a liberal political system, understands and undertakes to protect
him- or herself. Without a constitutional democratic system in place, no
individual has the minimalist understanding of what it means to fight for one's
civil rights. While it is true that human rights is a language of individual
empowerment, an empowerment by means of which individuals can protect themselves
against injustices, Ignatieff is speaking in the context of the political
development of individuals in a liberal democratic society, where injustice is
understood relative to one's experience in a democratic system that guarantees
certain basic rights to its citizens. How can people in Darfur, for instance,
protect themselves with this kind of empowerment when they have had no
experience of seeing their agency or their rational capacity as important
instruments to assert their human rights and defend themselves?
Ignatieff's prescriptive avoidance of any foundational
consideration at the international level, in my opinion, leads to an imposition
of a Western conception of individualism, even if one were to take it in the
sense of a "moral individualism" that protects cultural diversity. Moral
individualism claims to respect the diverse ways individuals choose to live
their lives. According to Ignatieff, in this way of thinking, human rights is
only a systematic agenda of "negative liberty," a toolkit against oppression, a
toolkit that individual agents must be free to use as they see fit within the
broader frame of cultural and religious beliefs by which they live. But in
Muslim societies where people have traditionally conceived their individuality
within the context of their communal and collective life, human rights will have
to protect individuals as members of collective groups and require collective
groups to work towards a just balance between individual and collective
concerns.
Conclusion
In the post-colonial age, and more particularly, in the age of
economic and cultural globalization, it is important to dispel doubts about the
universality of human rights by seriously engaging metaphysical and epistemic
foundations of human rights norms to demonstrate that these norms can be
essentially grounded in religious notions about human dignity and divinely
ordained human freedom of will. Religious doctrines have the potential of
working towards an overlapping consensus on important articles in the
Declaration-a consensus that secular human rights theoreticians can ill-afford
to ignore. The Declaration's normative discourse must be critically
reinvestigated for its universal presumptions about human inherency in light of
the theological discourse whose universal language continues to guide ethical
and jurisprudential values of the common life.
Whereas I do not share Alasdair MacIntyre's rejection of
universal rights as fictitious, I agree with him in insisting that traditional
societies had universal notions of justice and had worked towards principles of
coexistence among themselves and others long before the secular modernist spoke
about the contractarian theory of corporate life that shaped modern politics.9 The founder of Islam, for instance, not only recognized the temporal
existence as part and parcel of one's faith commitment; he also created stable
and universal institutional structures to further the vision of a just public
order under God's guidance. Islam's experience with the temporal world was
sociologically and linguistically inclusive and universalistic. As a
world-embracing tradition, Islam's ethical and jurisprudential guidance set out
to provide fixed norms for building a multi-faith, multi-ethnic, and
multi-cultural society that spoke to the vision of a universal community founded
upon justice. Since this moral context was potentially inclusive, the need to
compromise its faith-based vision of the public order to accommodate other
communities actually never arose. As a matter of fact, it had no problem in
endorsing a common moral stance that was founded upon a universally recognizable
account of individual autonomy, the common good, and a divinely endowed
self-subsisting moral standard that transcends religious and cultural
differences.10
Having argued for the inclusion of conversation about the
foundations that undergird the Declaration, let me also hasten to add that in
principle I agree with the secularist theoreticians of human rights who actively
advocate avoiding entanglement with metaphysical and religious notions like
human dignity, natural law, and divine purposes for humanity so that the true
purpose of the international document, namely, protection of human beings from
abuse, oppression, and cruelty, is not in any way diminished. It is a truism to
reiterate the secularist concern that when human dignity itself is in danger,
academic controversy about the foundations of universal morality intensifies
moral complacency rather than protecting individual human rights. Nonetheless,
ignoring Muslim criticisms about the ethnocentric and hegemonic goals of the
Declaration, however unfounded, has the danger of further marginalizing human
rights in the Muslim world.
The problem that faces Muslim supporters of the Declaration is
that without due consideration of religious or philosophical sources, it will be
difficult to garner the support of Muslim communities to work towards improving
human rights instruments to effect the necessary implementation of the
Declaration. Evidently, emphasis on the secular-religious dichotomy will
necessarily lead to a foundationless model, which actually stifles critical
dialogue between the secular and traditionalist theorists. In addition,
Western-Islamic polarization in terms of liberal-non-liberal societies is also
detrimental to the need for international consensus on protecting a number of
basic freedoms, including freedom of conscience and religion. The Islamic model
for democratic pluralism is not inherently antithetical to a central concept of
human dignity and the individual's inalienable right to determine her spiritual
destiny without interference. In Muslim societies enforcement of human rights
will be taken even more seriously if, using the foundational model, one can
derive the inherent worth of the individual and argue for freedom of religion.
Human rights is in origin a Western concept that needs to become Islamic in all
its ramifications.
The secular liberal thesis that liberty can survive only outside
religion and through secularization of a religious tradition was founded upon
the historical experience of Christianity, and, hence, had little resonance in
Islam. The liberal solution was clearly to separate the public and the private
in order to guarantee that the public square would remain inclusive and tolerant
of differences. The value of freedom had to be raised over and against Christian
religious exclusivity. In other words, privatization through the secularization
of Christianity helped in reducing the hold of religious law and the church over
society, thus making pluralism in the public square possible.
The religious experience of those who argue for foundationless
theories of human rights is worth keeping in mind, particularly when such a
negative evaluation of religion is extended to the different historical
experience of Muslim societies. Foundationless theories are concerned with
guaranteeing basic human rights and reconciling basic freedoms with the moral
worth of all humans as humans. To be sure, in light of the tragic unfolding of
exclusive religiosity and moral absolutism, that concern was and remains real
even today.
Was Muslim historical experience any different? Evidently it
was, and this is what seems to be the source of an alternative human rights
paradigm presented by Muslim apologists. What is missing in this
alternative paradigm is the discussion of any foundational capacity in Islamic
tradition to sit in dialogue with the secular human rights theorists to make a
case for inclusive notions of human entitlements, tampered with human
responsibilities in maintaining the overall well-being of humanity in all its
areas and spheres of existence. What is needed is a substantial theoretical
discussion of an inclusive foundational conception of human rights that would
appeal to the suspicious traditional authorities in the Muslim world, apparently
threatened by secular ideologies that they believe are determined to destroy the
spiritual and moral foundations of a global community to make room for liberal
secular ideas of inalienable human rights.
A foundational theory of human rights could be articulated based
on some of the pluralistic features of Islam and its culture that are totally
ignored by Muslim traditionalist and fundamentalist discourse. True to its
internal juridical plurality, the Islamic tradition was concerned with the
preservation of freedom against any kind of legal or political authoritarianism,
especially in view of its refusal to afford any human institution like the
"church" the right to represent divine interests on earth. Moreover, this
default plurality was instrumental in preserving relatively peaceful coexistence
among peoples of diverse faiths and cultures under Muslim political domination.
Functional recognition of separate jurisdictions for spiritual and temporal was
also instrumental in affording fundamental agreement on public values and in
meeting the demands of multi-faith and multi-cultural societies of the Islamic
world to regulate human relationships among peoples of different faiths and
culture. Hence, the Western experience of separation of religion and politics by
default remains alien to Muslim political experience.
It is this difference in the historical experience of the West
and Islam that calls into question whether the foundationless secular model can
on its own provide universal standards that can be applied across cultures. It
needs to look at the foundational religious model with its own universal claim
to offer a more comprehensive understanding of what it means to be a defender of
human rights today. Religion cannot and will not confine itself to the private
domain where it will eventually lose its influence in nurturing human
conscience. It needs a public space in the development of an international sense
of a world community with a vision for creating an ideal society that cares and
shares.
Notes
1.
Research for this essay and for the forthcoming book, Islam and Human Rights,
from which this essay was adapted, was conducted under the Carnegie Scholar
of Islam program.
2.
It is worth reminding
ourselves that Christian assessment of the Declaration is founded upon
an entirely different set of concerns that arose from its reaction to
the liberal paradigm, which was based on radical individualism and was
derived from the historically situated political and social discourse of
seventeenth century philosophical thought. In his introduction to Human Rights and the Image
of God (London:
SCM, 2004), Roger Ruston traces the development of Christian-Catholic
criticism of the liberal paradigm of human rights since the Universal
Declaration in 1948. While there are some common themes that unite
Muslim critics with their Christian counterparts, for Muslims the major
problem with the liberal paradigm has been its hostile attitude to
religion per se and its enormous confidence in secularism, which has
failed time and again to deliver justice in Muslim countries that
adopted its presuppositions for their reconstruction of modern Muslim
societies. It is not only Turkey that institutionalized secularism
through constitutional politics and is now faced with internal
challenges posed by Islamic cultural revival; Algeria also stands out as
another unmistakable example of secularism enforced from the top by a
colonial power that failed to
3.
In his book on human rights,
the prominent traditionalist scholar of Egypt, Muhammad al-Ghazali lends
qualified support to the international document as something that must
be respected by Muslims because some of its "foundations" are also
enunciated in the Qur'an. For Ghazali, like other traditionalist
scholars in the Muslim world, Islam provides the norms that are
culturally legitimate and applicable within the Islamic world. As such,
an alternative declaration of Islamic human rights is appended to the
translation and discussion of the international document. See Huquq al-insan: Bayn
ta'alim al-islam wa i'lan al-umam al-muttahida (Human
Rights: Between the Teachings of Islam and the Declaration of the United
Nations)
(Alexandria, Egypt: Dar al-Da'wa, 1422/2002). This trend in traditional
human rights scholarship has undermined the legitimacy of the universal
declaration in Muslim eyes. The only way to lessen the negative
influence of this trend is to engage traditional scholars in exploring
the metaphysical foundations of the human rights declaration and
demonstrate the common moral ground that is shared by world religions in
upholding the norms that undergird the international document. By
denying any normative foundations for the human rights declaration and
insisting upon its secular thrust, the opportunity to stimulate
conversation with the actual representatives of Islamic tradition is
lost.
4.
Johannes Morsink, The Universal Declaration
of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting, and Intent (Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1999) 282.
5.
Khaled Abu El Fadl and
Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na'im are among the few serious discussants of human
rights in the context of Islamic tradition.
6.
Muhammad 'Amara, al-Islam wa huquq al-insan:
Darurat…la huquq (Islam
and Human Rights: Necessities…not Rights)
(Kuwait: 'Alam al-Ma'rifa, 1405/1985) criticizes both Muslim
fundamentalist and Muslim secular scholarship for having failed to
demonstrate human rights within the parameters of Islamic comprehensive
doctrines. The secularist scholarship that was produced under the
Orientalist masters and that followed Western cultural and
civilizational domination of Muslim minds was guilty of not examining
Islamic sources carefully before agreeing with the Western thesis about
the inadequacy of Islam and its juridical tradition to issue anything
similar to the international declaration of human rights. The Muslim
secularists' prescription that one must derive human rights from Western
civilization instead of searching for these in Islamic sources,
according to 'Amara, must be totally rejected because it smacks of new
Western hegemony over Muslim societies (9-10).
7.
Michael Ignatieff, Human Rights as Politics
and Idolatry (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001) 54.
8.
Jeffrey Stout, Democracy and Tradition
(Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2004) 2. Stout points to two prominent American
thinkers on American democracy, namely, John Rawls and Richard Rorty,
who want to severely restrict the use of religious reasons in public
discussions about politics. Stout takes seriously the concerns of these
thinkers and the claims of their opponents. In response to their
prescription that leads to the virtual hiding of one's religious reasons
lest they are rendered unreasonable by not accepting a free-standing
notion of justice as a universal point of reference in political
discussion in pluralistic societies, Stout defends the "reasonableness"
of religious reasons by focusing on the sharing and hearing of
particular reasons in public discourse and by pointing out that "a
person can be a reasonable (socially cooperative) citizen without
believing in or appealing to a free-standing conception of justice"
(68). He notes that Rawls's definition of reasonable as being willing to
govern their conduct according to a universally applicable principle
"implicitly imputes
unreasonableness to everyone who opts out of the contractarian project, regardless of the
reasons they might have for doing so" (67).
9.
For his rejection of humans
rights as fictitious, see Alasdair MacIntyre, "Community, Law, and the
Idiom and Rhetoric of Rights," Listening: Journal of
Religion and Culture 26 (1991): 96-110. For his
argument concerning traditional universal notions of justice, see
Alasdair MacIntyre,
After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (London: Duckworth, 1981)
64-7.
10.
I have examined Islamic
ethical and theological notions to demonstrate the Qur'anic principles
of social coexistence and civil cooperation founded on a common morality
that touches all humans, independent of one's faith affiliation, in
The Islamic Roots of
Democratic Pluralism (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2000).