Freedom to Choose God
Catholic Dossier, Vol. 6, No. 2: Mar-April 2000
Reproduced with permission
The opening line of Dignitatis Humanae states, "A sense of the
dignity of the human person has been impressing itself more and more deeply
on the consciousness of contemporary man, and the demand is increasingly
made that men should act on their own judgment, enjoying and making use of a
responsible freedom, not driven by coercion but motivated by a sense of
duty." Dignitatis Humanae was written largely to defend man's right
to religious liberty. Religious freedom is the most important freedom, for
men need more than anything the freedom to get themselves right with God.
But as we know, in our age, few employ the abundant freedoms available to us
for advancing our relationship with God.
Dignitatis Humanae also states that "it is one of the major
tenets of Catholic doctrine that man's response to God in faith must be
free; no one therefore is to be forced to embrace the Christian faith
against his own will." This means that we must not force others to make
proclamations of faith. Yet freedom from such coercion, of course, does not
mean that individuals are free to worship in any way they choose; child
sacrifice, for instance, is not to be tolerated. We have the freedom to
believe whatever we want, but not the freedom to do whatever we want.
Religious freedom, then, is not absolute. It is a fundamental human right
but one subject to reasonable limitation. Let me comment on the current
state of bioethics as a means of illustrating what can go wrong when we
misunderstand the proper reach of human freedom and why the important
element in religious freedom is not so much freedom as it is religion.
The discipline of bioethics is currently nearly obsessed with autonomy,
or man's liberty to make his own choices. This liberty, however, has little
to do with human dignity or duty and much more to do with a reduction in
human dignity and a sense that one has few obligations other than making
one's own choices.
The students in my bioethics class were recently discussing a case of a
fifty-six year old man who was becoming increasingly demented. A simple
operation would halt his rapid slide into complete dementia (caused by water
on the brain) and perhaps enable him to regain many of his faculties. He,
for no apparent reason, was refusing the simple surgery. His submissive and
timid wife concurred with his wishes. Even when he was not demented he
refused surgery so his physicians were inclined to respect his autonomy and
not seek a court order mandating the surgery. In today's bioethical world it
seems the greatest wrong is being "paternalistic" and overturning a
patient's autonomous decision, even if that decision rejects simple ordinary
care and leads to severe disability, dementia, or even death.
A few of the students opined that since he was so old, dementia might not
be far away anyway. I put my head down on my desk and emitted a deep
existential groan. When I revived, I informed them that I am soon going to
turn fifty. I acknowledged that when I was their age, I thought that fifty
was old and now that I am nearly fifty I am sure that it is. I am
experiencing a reduction of all my powers; my hearing, sight, teeth, energy,
etc. are all diminishing and I have reason to believe that I discern signs
of impending dementia as well. Nonetheless, I told them that I belong to a
generation that largely has not yet done anything worthwhile with our lives
and that we, unlike previous generations, should not be put out to pasture
to admire the daisies however attractive an option that might seem. Rather,
we need time to redeem ourselves and see if we can help stall or even
reverse some of the terrible forces we have unleashed. (Though I do wonder
if the more pernicious of us might be better off reduced to ineffectuality.)
Such dismal moments aside, teaching at the University of Dallas is a
special privilege and teaching bioethics here is even a more special
privilege. By the time our students take the bioethics course, they have
already had three other philosophy course, ethics, philosophical
anthropology, and metaphysics. Such a background protects them somewhat from
the approach of bioethics texts that inform them that they can be a
utilitarian, one who seeks the "greatest happiness for the greatest number"
or a deontologist (roughly, one who believes in absolutes) and more recently
what is known as a "principlist" (to be described in a moment). The texts
give no reason why one would choose to be either a utilitarian or a
deontologist; one's choice seems a matter of preference. I point out to my
students that utilitarians have virtually no metaphysics and an anthropology
that seems to consist in the dubious claim that men have a natural sympathy
for each other and deontologists think virtually nothing is known about the
outside world and that man is a rational being who should ignore all of his
natural inclinations. They are, therefore, not much drawn to either system.
Actually, one wonders who outside of professional ethicists is drawn to
either system. In fact, few of them seem willing to identify themselves with
either system; in reading bioethics commentaries one is hard put to find any
ethicist who identifies him or her self as a utilitarian or a deontologist.
Reigning today are is the "system" coming to be known as "principlism." Two
bioethicists, Tom Beauchamp and James Childress, seem to have devised this
"system" as a compromise (one claims to lean towards rule utilitarianism,
the other towards deontology); it evaluates bioethical issues in terms of
the principles of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. These
"principles" are loosely grounded in whatever grounds rule utilitarianism
and deontology but mostly are meant to stand alone, as rather obvious
principles for those in the health care profession.
Because physicians have historically and one might say naturally been
thought to have the function of healing their patients or reducing their
pain, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and even justice seem natural principles
for bioethics. But the truly reigning principle is the principle of
autonomy. We must be free to make our own decisions - and such freedom is
much more important than the rightness or wrongness of any choice that we
make. We value our right to be wrong much more than our responsibility to be
right. Physicians are frequently forced in our culture to abandon
beneficence, nonmaleficence and even justice to protect the autonomy of
their patients (we need look no further than the legalization of abortion
and the growing support for assisted suicide).
One might hope that the dominance of autonomy as a value is rooted in the
notion of human dignity, of man being made in the "image and likeness" of
God. Natural law ethics and personalism justify a strong interest in helping
patients be self-determining for these reasons, but bioethics texts rarely
mention natural law and have no awareness of personalism (though feminist
and environmentalist ethics occasionally merit a mention.) Rather, the
commitment to autonomy seems based primarily on the fact that we are living
in an age of moral pluralism; we have so little if any means of coming to
any agreement on moral issues. When we are so confused that we cannot agree
that partial birth abortions are wrong, what can we agree upon? So, we slide
more and more into a culture that permits almost anything - even the "right"
to kill others and certainly the "right" to kill one's self.
Although bioethics is dominated by the advocates of the principle of
autonomy, more and more it has its critics if only because it is so
difficult to honor it in clinical situations. Patients want to trust their
doctors; patients often don't know what they think is right, and some of
them who do make choices that will cause them great harm and threaten to
compromise the moral commitments of the physicians. Physicians are generally
at a loss of what to do, besides hoping that their patient will fail the too
frequently requested psychiatric consult when their patients make what they
think are harmful, foolish, and sometimes immoral choices. They do not want
to operate as simple technicians who are there strictly to do the patient's
bidding. So sometimes it seems that the battle in bioethics is not between
utilitarians and deontologists but between wannabe paternalists and
autonomists.
The real opponents, however, are those who think that man is just a more
highly developed animal particularly attached to his freedom of choice and
who will face no eternal consequences for those choices, and those who think
man is made in the image and likeness of God. In this view, since man is
rational, free, and relational, he must use his reason and freedom to
fulfill his obligations to himself, others, and his God.
Studies show that most Americans are religious and at the bedside priests
and ministers are generally very welcome, but from reading bioethics text
books one would rarely get the idea that patients are to be urged to draw
upon their religious beliefs to help them make their decisions. The Kantian
view that one should not let others influence one, that one has to make
one's own decisions for them to be fully respectable, lingers in bioethics.
Catholic physicians must take the lead in helping other physicians and
bioethicists as well realize that autonomy or freedom is not the greatest
good; it is a good only if used to perform one's duties. They may be aided
by a close reading of Dignitatis Humanae with its understanding of the
balanced interplay between freedom and responsibilities, and rights and
duties. We must realize the source of man's freedom: it is a gift from God
and the reason for man's freedom: so that we can love and obey God because
we ourselves recognize His sovereignty. If so, we must certainly want
patients (and seekers after truth) to make their own decisions, but we will
also want to help them make the right decisions. If by no other means,
physicians can do so by refusing to perform operations and provide treatment
they know to be immoral and by being willing to attempt to get patients and
their fellow physicians to take into account the possible eternal
consequences of their choices. To refuse to do so is to let ignorance rather
than truth guide one's decisions and there is no point to freedom unless it
is used to grasp and live by the truth.