Submission to the Alberta College of Pharmacists
Re: Draft Code of Ethics
Full Text
XVIII. The problem of
complicity
XVIII.1 Most people seem
willing to grant that a
health care worker who has
serious moral objections to
a procedure should not be
compelled to perform it or
assist directly with it.
However, many people find it
more difficult to understand
why some health care workers
object to even indirect
forms of involvement: why
some would refuse to refer
patients for procedures they
believed to be wrong.
XVIII.2 For example, the
Canadian Pharmacists'
Association (CPhA) agrees
that objecting pharmacists
should not have to "take
part" or " participate" in
euthanasia or assisted
suicide, but claims that
they (and physicians and
nurses as well) are
ethically obliged to "refer"
for the services where they
are legal.89
In this respect the CPhA
seems to follow the
reasoning of the ACOG
Committee on Ethics. The
Committee claims that
refusing to refer is
illogical. "[T]he logic of
conscience," it states, "as
a form of self-reflection on
and judgement about whether
one's own acts are
obligatory or prohibited,
means that it would be odd
or absurd to say, "I would
have a guilty conscience if
she did X."90
XVIII.3 It thus appears
that the Canadian Pharmacy
Association and ACOG
Committee are working from
what might be called the
'Absolutionist Premise:'
that someone who merely
arranges for an act is
absolved of moral
responsibility because only
someone who actually does an
act is morally responsible
for it.
XVIII.4 Alternatively,
the CPhA and ACOG may admit
that some moral
responsibility is incurred
by referral or by otherwise
facilitating a procedure,
but that the degree of
responsibility is
sufficiently diminished in
such cases that it is of no
real significance. Call this
the 'Dismissive Premise.'
XVIII.5 In passing, it
should be noted that, on
either account, the position
of the CPhA raises the
issues discussed in Parts
IX and
X. Whether it asserts
that referral or
facilitation do not incur
moral responsibility, or
that the degree of moral
responsibility incurred is
so minimal as to be
inconsequential, it is
making a moral judgement and
demanding that others adhere
to it.
Complicity in torture
XVIII.6 The Absolutionist
Premise is illustrated by
the opinion of Newsweek
columnist Jonathan Alter. In
the weeks following the
terrorist attacks on the
United States in September,
2001, Alter argued that it
was time to think about
torturing terrorist suspects
who might have information
about plans for such
horrendous crimes. He
acknowledged that physical
torture was "contrary to
American values," but argued
that torture is appropriate
in some circumstances, and
proposed a novel
'compromise:' that the
United States turn terrorist
suspects who won't talk over
to "less squeamish allies,"91
a practice known as
"extraordinary rendition."
The allies would then do
what Americans would not,
without compromising
American values.
XVIII.7
Less than a year later,
Canadian citizen Maher Arar,
returning home from Zurich
through New York, was
detained, interrogated and
"rendered" to Syria by U.S.
authorities.92
In Syria he was imprisoned
for almost a year,
"interrogated, tortured and
held in degrading and
inhumane conditions."93
XVIII.8 A subsequent
"comprehensive and thorough"
investigation "did not turn
up any evidence that he had
committed any criminal
offence" and disclosed "no
evidence" that he was a
threat to Canadian
security."94
A commission of inquiry was
appointed to investigate
"the actions of Canadian
officials" in the case.95
XVIII.9 What was of
concern to Mr. Arar, the
public and the government
was whether or not Canadian
officials had caused or
contributed to what happened
to Mr. Arar, even though his
deportation to Syria was
effected by the United
States, and Syrian officials
imprisoned and tortured him.
The key issue was whether or
not Canada was complicit in
torture.
XVIII.10 Concern about
Canadian complicity surfaces
repeatedly in the report of
the commission of inquiry:
in briefing notes to the
Commissioner of the RCMP,96
in the testimony of the
Canadian Ambassador to
Syria,97
in references to the
possibility of RCMP
complicity in his
deportation,98
about the perception of
complicity if CSIS agents
met Mr. Arar in Syria,99
in the suggestion that
evidence of complicity could
show "a pattern of
misconduct,"100
and in the conclusions and
recommendations of the
report itself.101
XVIII.11 The issue of
complicity arose again in
2007 when a report in
Toronto's Globe and Mail
alleged that prisoners taken
in Afghanistan by Canadian
troops and turned over to
Afghan authorities were
being mistreated and
tortured.102
"Canada is hardly in a
position to claim it did not
know what was going on,"
said the Globe. "At
best, it tried not to know;
at worst, it knew and said
nothing."103
On this view, one can be
complicit in wrongdoing not
only by acting, but by
failing to act, and even by
silence. The Globe editorial
brings to mind the words of
Martin Luther King and
Mahatma Gandhi.104
XVIII.12 Thus far,
government officials. But
the problem of complicity
does not relate only to
government officials. The
Lancet, among others, has
asked, "How complicit are
doctors in the abuse of
detainees?"105
and other journal articles
have explored the answer
with some anxiety.106
XVIII.13 The Arar
Inquiry, the concerns raised
by the Globe and Mail story about Afghan detainees
and the alarm raised about
physician complicity in
torture make sense only on
the presumption that one can
be morally responsible for
acts actually committed by
another person. The
Absolutionist Premise does
not provide a plausible
starting point for moral
reasoning.
Complicity in capital
punishment, euthanasia and
assisted suicide
XVIII.14 The Dismissive
Premise is more promising.
Granted that one can be
morally responsible for acts
actually committed by
another, there may be
differences of opinion about
what kind of action or
omission incurs such
responsibility. These
differences need not be
thoroughly canvassed in this
paper. It is sufficient to
ask if the kind of action
involved in referral can
have that effect. That is:
if a pharmacist refers or
otherwise helps a patient to
obtain what he believes to
be an immoral procedure, is
he a culpable participant in
the provision it?
XVIII.15
The issue of culpable
participation in a morally
controversial procedure has
been considered by the
American Medical Association
in its policy on capital
punishment. It forbids
physician "participation" in
executions.107
This is particularly
relevant here because of the
Canadian Pharmacy
Association's position that
referral for euthanasia or
assisted suicide does not
constitute participation in
the procedures.
XVIII.16 The AMA defines
"participation" as
(1) an action which
would directly cause the
death of the condemned;
(2) an action which
would assist, supervise,
or contribute to the
ability of another
individual to directly
cause the death of the
condemned;
(3) an action which
could automatically
cause an execution to be
carried out on a
condemned prisoner.
XVIII.17 Among the
actions identified by the
AMA as "participation" in
executions are the
prescription or
administration of
tranquillizers or other
drugs as part of the
procedure, directly or
indirectly monitoring vital
signs, rendering technical
advice or consulting with
the executioners, and even
(except at the request of
the condemned, or in a
non-professional capacity)
attending or observing an
execution.
XVIII.18 The attention
paid to what others might
consider insignificant
detail is exemplified in the
provision that permits
physicians to certify death,
providing that death has
been pronounced by someone
else, and by restrictions on
the donation of organs by
the deceased.
XVIII.19 The AMA also
prohibits physician
participation in torture.
Participation is defined to
include, but is not limited
to, "providing or
withholding any services,
substances, or knowledge to
facilitate the practice of
torture."108
The Canadian Medical
Association, while not faced
with the problem of capital
punishment, has voiced its
opposition to physician
involvement in the
punishment or torture of
prisoners. The CMA states
that physicians "should
refuse to allow their
professional or research
skills to be used in any
way" for such purposes.109
Complicity and referral
XVIII.20 While referral is
not mentioned in the AMA
policy on capital
punishment, nor in the
Canadian or American
policies on torture, one
cannot imagine that either
the AMA or CMA would agree
that physicians who refuse
to participate in torture or
executions have the duty to
refer the state "in a timely
manner" to other
practitioners.110In
fact, it is likely that both
the CMA and AMA would
censure a physician who did
so voluntarily, on the
grounds that such conduct
would make him complicit in
a gravely immoral act.
XVIII.21 It is reasonable
to hold that the kind of
action involved in referral
is the same kind of action
that is defined as
"participation" in the AMA
policies on capital
punishment and torture. The
model provided by the AMA
policy indicates that, in
principle, at least, it is
not unreasonable for
pharmacists to refuse to
refer patients for
procedures to which they
object for reasons of
conscience, on the grounds
that referral would make
them complicit in a wrongful
act.
XVIII.22 The point here,
of course, is not that
capital punishment or
torture are morally
equivalent to euthanasia,
assisted suicide,
post-coital interception,
etc. The point is that, when
professional associations
are convinced that an act is
seriously wrong - even if it
is legal - one finds them
willing to refuse all forms
of direct and indirect
participation in order to
avoid moral complicity in
the act. This is precisely
the position taken by
conscientious objectors in
health care.
CMPA: referrals and
complicity
XVIII.23 In 2002 the College
notified practitioners that
it was the opinion of the
Canadian Medical Protective
Association (CMPA) that
referral to non-regulated
health care providers
exposed physicians to civil
liability "if medical
problems arise during, or as
a result of services
provided by a non-regulated
health care provider."
XVIII.24 The CMPA
recommended that physicians
"avoid all actions that
could be construed as a
patient referral to a
non-regulated health care
provider" - especially
written referrals - and that
physicians make clear to
patients that it is their
responsibility "to make all
arrangements with the
non-regulated health care
provider." Further:
If the patient
requires something in
writing. . . the note
should clearly indicate
. . . that the
physician, though not
objecting, is neither
referring nor
recommending the patient
for the treatment.111
XVIII.25 The opinion of
the CMPA was clearly based
upon the premise that
referral makes a physician
complicit in what follows.
The CMPA recommendations
exactly parallel the
position taken by
pharmacists who refuse to
refer patients for
procedures or services the
pharmacists believe to be
wrong.
Complicity and dirty hands
XVIII.26 Having considered
the problem of complicity,
it is now worth asking why
the subject of complicity in
wrongful acts is not only of
grave concern to ethical
physicians, pharmacists,
medical journals, and
professional associations,
but why it can so thoroughly
arouse the public, the
media, and politicians: why
commissions of inquiry will
so meticulously investigate
the possibility of
complicity, producing
hundreds upon hundreds of
pages of detailed analysis
of the evidence taken, at no
little cost to the public
purse.
XVIII.27 A jaded
few will respond that
reports of scandal will
always sell newspapers, that
scandal always energizes the
self-righteous (both the
religious and the
politically motivated
varieties) and that scandal
is one of the traditional
weapons used against
opponents by politicians of
all stripes. There is some
truth to this, but, going
deeper into it, why is
complicity in wrongdoing
scandalous?
XVIII.28 The answer must
be that there is something
about complicity in
wrongdoing that triggers an
almost instinctive reaction
in people, something about
it that touches some
peculiar, deep and almost
universal sense of
abhorrence. One says
"almost" instinctive and
"almost" universal because,
of course, there have always
been exceptions: Eichmanns,
Pol Pots, Rwandan machete
men, for example. And the
degree of sensitivity varies
from person to person, from
subject to subject, and from
one culture to another.
Nonetheless, complicity in
wrongdoing can be a source
of scandal, a political
weapon and the subject for
public inquiries, only
because it has some real and
profound significance.
XVIII.29 The nature of
that significance is
suggested by a number of
expressions: "poisoned"
fruit doctrine,
"tainted"evidence, money
that has to be "laundered,"
and "dirty" hands.112
A senior Iraqi surgeon,
commenting on the complicity
of physicians in torture
under Saddam Hussein, said
that "the state wanted them
to have 'dirty hands'." In
contrast, some writers refer
approvingly to a "dirty
hands principle":
Philosopher Sidney
Axinn tells us the Dirty
Hands principle "holds
that in order to govern
an institution one must
sometimes do things that
are immoral." He goes on
to say that advocates
would claim that "we do
not want leaders who are
so concerned with their
own personal morality
that they will not do
`what is necessary' to
... win the battle....
We have an inept leader
if we have a person who
is so morally fastidious
that he or she will not
break the law when that
is the only way to
success" (Axinn, 1989:
138).113
But whichever view one
takes of "dirty hands," all
of these expressions convey
an uncomfortable sense that
something is felt to be
soiled by complicity in
wrongdoing. What is that
something? And what is the
nature of that cloying
grime?
XVIII.30 The answer
suggested by the Project is
that the "something" is not
a "thing" at all, but the
human person, and that the
sense of uncleanness or
taint associated with
complicity in wrongdoing is
the natural response of the
human person to something
fundamentally opposed to his
nature and dignity.
XIX. The needs of the
patient: anthropology counts
XIX.1 What is conducive to
human well-being is
determined by the nature of
the human person. There can
be no agreement upon what is
good for the patient without
first agreeing upon that.
One's understanding of the
nature of the human person
determines not only how one
defines the needs of the
patient, but how one
approaches every moral or
ethical problem in pharmacy
or medicine.
XIX.2 Reasoning from
different beliefs about what
man is and what is good for
him leads to different
definitions of "need,"
different understandings of
"harm," different concepts
of right and wrong, and,
ultimately, to different
ethical conclusions.114
XIX.3 Consider two
different statements: (a)
man is a creature whose
purpose for existence
depends upon his ability to
think, choose and
communicate; b) man is a
creature for whom intellect,
choice and communication are
attributes of existence, but
do not establish his purpose
for existence. Statements
(a) and (b) express
non-religious belief, not
empirically verified fact.
Such beliefs - usually
implicit rather than
explicit - direct the course
of subsequent discussion.
XIX.4 Bioethicists
working from (a) would have
little objection to the
substitution of persistently
unconscious human subjects
for animals in experimental
research.115
Those who accept (b) would
be more inclined to object.116
Finally, bioethicists
who do not believe in
'purpose' beyond filling an
ecological niche would
dismiss the whole discussion
as wrong-headed.
XIX.5 What must be
emphasized is that when
people cannot achieve a
consensus about the morality
of a procedure, it is
frequently because they are
operating from different
beliefs about the nature of
the human person.
Disagreement is seldom about
facts - the province of
science - but about what to
believe in light of them -
the province of philosophy
and religion.
XIX.6 The same thing is
true of disagreements about
freedom of conscience for
health care workers.
Returning to the point made
in XIX.1 TO XIX.4, beliefs
about the nature of the
human person lie at the root
of any attempt to set limits
to this freedom. In fact,
failure to engage at this
level will probably
frustrate more superficial
efforts to resolve the
conflict.
XIX.7 What follows is a
plausible description of an
aspect of the human person
that is relevant to the
present discussion. The
threshold of plausibility
ought to be sufficient,
since the context for this
discussion is a liberal
democracy, in which there is
an expectation that a
plurality of more or less
comprehensive world-views
will be accommodated.
XX. The human person
The integrity of the human
person
XX.1 The pharmacist, a
unique someone who
identifies himself as "I"
and "me,"117
has only one
identity, served by a single
conscience that governs his
conduct in private and
professional life. This
moral unity of the human
person is identified as
integrity, a virtue highly
prized by Martin Luther
King, who described it at as
essential for "a complete
life."118
[W]e must remember
that it's possible to
affirm the existence of
God with your lips and
deny his existence with
your life. . . . We say
with our mouths that we
believe in him, but we
live with our lives like
he never existed . . .
That's a dangerous type
of atheism.119
XX.2 Against this, some
writers have invoked the
venerable concept of
self-sacrifice.
"Professionalism," Professor
R. Alta Charo suggests
rhetorically, ought to
include "the rather
old-fashioned notion of
putting others before
oneself."120
XX.3 But self-sacrifice,
in the tradition of King,
Gandhi and Lewis, while it
might mean going to jail or
even the loss of one's life,
has never been understood to
include the sacrifice of
one's integrity. To abandon
one's moral or ethical
convictions in order to
serve others is
prostitution, not
professionalism. "He who
surrenders himself without
reservation," warned C.S.
Lewis, "to the temporal
claims of a nation, or a
party, or a class" - one
could here add 'profession'
- "is rendering to Caesar
that which, of all things,
emphatically belongs to God:
himself."121
XX.4 The integrity or
wholeness of the human
person was also a key
element in the thought of
French philosopher Jacques
Maritain. He emphasized that
the human person is a
"whole, an open and generous
whole" that to be a human
person "involves totality."
122
The notion of
personality thus
involves that of
totality and
independence; no matter
how poor and crushed a
person may be, as such
he is a whole, and as a
person subsists in an
independent manner. To
say that a man is a
person is to say that in
the depth of his being
he is more a whole than
a part and more
independent than
servile.123
XX.5 This concept is not
foreign to the practice of
modern medicine. Canadian
ethicist Margaret
Somerville, for example,
asserts that one cannot
overemphasize the importance
of the notion of
'patient-as-person' and
acknowledges a "totality of
the person" that goes beyond
the purely physical.124
The dignity and
inviolability of the human
person
XX.6 "Man," wrote Maritain,
"is an individual who holds
himself in hand by his
intelligence and his will."
He exists not merely
physically; there is in
him a richer and nobler
existence; he has
spiritual superexistence
through knowledge and
through love.125
XX.7 Applying this
principle, Maritain asserted
that, even as a member of
society or the state, a man
"has secrets that escape the
group and a vocation which
the group does not
encompass."126
His whole person is engaged
in society through his
social and political
activities and his work, but
"not by reason of his entire
self and all that is in
him."127
For in the person
there are some things -
and they are the most
important and sacred
ones - which transcend
political society and
draw man in his entirety
above political society
- the very same whole
man who, by reason of
another category of
things, is a part of
political society.128
XX.8 Even as part of
society, Maritain insisted,
"the human person is
something more than a part;"129
he remains a whole, and must
be treated as a whole.130
A part exists only to
comprise or sustain a whole;
it is a means to that end.
But the human person is an
end in himself, not a means
to an end.131
Thus, according to Maritain,
the nature of the human
person is such that it
"would have no man exploited
by another man, as a tool to
serve the latter's own
particular good."132
XX.9 British philosopher
Cyril Joad applied this to
the philosophy of democratic
government:
To the right of the
individual to be treated
as an end, which entails
his right to the full
development and
expression of his
personality, all other
rights and claims must,
the democrat holds, be
subordinated. I do not
know how this principle
is to be defended any
more than I can frame a
defence for the
principles of democracy
and liberty.133
In company with Maritain,
Professor Joad insisted that
it is an essential tenet of
democratic government that
the state is made for man,
but man is not made for the
state.134
XX.10 To reduce human
persons to the status of
tools or things to be used
for ends chosen by others is
reprehensible: "very
wicked," wrote C.S. Lewis.135
Likewise, Martin Luther King
condemned segregation as
"morally wrong and awful"
precisely because it
relegated persons "to the
status of things."136
XX.11 Similarly, Polish
philosopher Karol Wojtyla
(later Pope John Paul II):
. . . we must never
treat a person as a
means to an end. This
principle has a
universal validity.
Nobody can use a person
as a means towards an
end, no human being, nor
yet God the Creator.137
XX.12 Maritain, Joad,
Lewis, King and Wojtyla
reaffirmed in the twentieth
century what Immanuel Kant
had written in the
eighteenth: "Act so that you
treat humanity, whether in
your own person or in that
of another, always as an end
and never as a means only."138
Human dignity and freedom of
conscience
XX.13 Perhaps ironically,
this was the approach taken
when Madame Justice Bertha
Wilson of the Supreme Court
of Canada addressed the
issue of freedom of
conscience in the landmark
1988 case R v.
Morgentaler. Madame
Justice Wilson argued that
"an emphasis on individual
conscience and individual
judgment . . . lies at the
heart of our democratic
political tradition."139
Wilson held that it was
indisputable that the
decision to have an abortion
"is essentially a moral
decision, a matter of
conscience."
The question is:
whose conscience? Is the
conscience of the woman
to be paramount or the
conscience of the state?
I believe. . . that in a
free and democratic
society it must be the
conscience of the
individual. Indeed, s.
2(a) makes it clear that
this freedom belongs to
"everyone", i.e., to
each of us individually.140
XX.14 "Everyone" includes
every pharmacist. But, at
this point in the judgement,
Wilson was not discussing
whether or not the
conscience of a woman should
prevail over that of an
objecting physician, but how
the conscientious judgement
of an individual should
stand against that of the
state. Her answer was that,
in a free and democratic
society, "the state will
respect choices made by
individuals and, to the
greatest extent possible,
will avoid subordinating
these choices to any one
conception of the good
life."141
XX.15 Quoting the above
passage from Professor
Joad's book, Wilson approved
the principle than a human
person must never be treated
as a means to an end -
especially an end chosen by
someone else, or by the
state. Wilson rejected the
idea that, in questions of
morality, the state should
endorse and enforce "one
conscientiously-held view at
the expense of another," for
that is "to deny freedom of
conscience to some, to treat
them as means to an end, to
deprive them . . .of their
'essential humanity'."142
XXI. Summing up: mandatory
referral or assistance
XXI.1 Issue No. 1 reprise:
The primary issue raised by
the Draft Code of Ethics
is whether or not the
College of Pharmacists of
Alberta demand that a
pharmacist actively
facilitate a service or
procedure he believes to be
wrong, such as euthanasia,
assisted suicide or
post-coital interception.
Put another way, should a
pharmacist's conscientious
refusal to refer to refer
patients or assist them in
obtaining euthanasia,
assisted suicide,
post-coital interception,
etc. constitute professional
misconduct?
XXI.2 Parts
VIII to
XVII
demonstrate that
arguments commonly advanced
to support the notion that
pharmacists should be forced
to refer services to which
they object for reasons of
conscience are faulty or
inadequate. Part
XVIII and
XIX suggest that any
attempt to propose ethical
guidelines for referral must
fully address the issue of
complicity in wrongdoing and
the nature of the human
person.
XXI.3 Part
XX argues that a long
philosophical tradition,
stretching from at least
Immanuel Kant to R. vs.
Morgentaler and beyond,
insists that the nature of
the human person is such no
one should be exploited by
another by being reduced to
the status of a tool or
thing: that it is
reprehensible to use a human
person for ends chosen by
others. Within this
tradition, self-sacrifice,
has never been understood to
include the sacrifice of
one's integrity. To abandon
one's moral or ethical
convictions in order to
serve others is
prostitution, not
professionalism: once more,
servitude, not service.
XXI.3 In the tradition of
Kant, C.S. Lewis, Martin
Luther King, Cyril Joad and
Karol Wojtyla, and following
Madame Justice Wilson in R. vs. Morgentaler, to
demand that pharmacists
provide or assist in the
provision of procedures or
services that they believe
to be wrong is to treat them
as means to an end and
deprive them of their
"essential humanity."
XXI.4 Issue No. 1:
conclusion A pharmacist's
conscientious refusal to
refer to refer patients or
assist them in obtaining
euthanasia, assisted
suicide, post-coital
interception, etc. should
not constitute professional
misconduct. The College of
Pharmacists of Alberta
should not demand that a
pharmacist actively
facilitate a service or
procedure he believes to be
wrong. The Draft Code of
Ethics should be revised
to ensure that the document
cannot be used for this
purpose.
XXII. The need to explicitly
address freedom of
conscience
XXII.1 Of the 39 English
language pharmacy
associations or regulatory
entities noted in Appendices
"A" to "C," 29 have formally
addressed the issue of
freedom of conscience,
either in codes of ethics or
in practice guidelines, or
both. In Canada, the subject
has been considered by all
of the English language
pharmacy regulatory
authorities, as well as
NAPRA and the Canadian
Pharmacists Association.
This suggests that there is
a need to include specific,
unambiguous and ethically
sound guidelines on the
issue in the proposed Code of Ethics.
XXII.2
A second reason for
including specific,
unambiguous and ethically
sound guidelines that
protect freedom of
conscience in the profession
is provided by the continual
efforts of powerful or
influential individuals or
groups to suppress freedom
of conscience in health
care. In the absence of such
guidelines, they are likely
to encourage harassment of
objecting pharmacists, with
a view to forcing them to
participate in what they
consider to be morally
objectionable services, or
forcing them out of the
profession.
XXII.3 Ethically sound
guidelines will balance
respect for the personal
integrity of the pharmacist
and for his fundamental
freedoms against the
provision of pharmacy
services to the patient,
giving to each what is due
in justice.
XXIII. In search of
consensus
XXIII.1 Not one of the 29
English language pharmacy
associations or authorities
noted in Appendices "A" to
"C" that have addressed the
issue of freedom of
conscience prohibits
conscientious objection.
Only one - the College of
Pharmacists of British
Columbia - would require an
objecting pharmacist to
supply drugs for euthanasia,
assisted suicide,
post-coital interception,
etc.. Only two (Arkansas and
Georgia State Pharmacy
Boards) impose no duties on
an objector, perhaps
reflecting state laws.
XXIII.2 Given the
professional and regulatory
responses summarized in
Appendices
"A",
"B"and
"C", it is impossible to
argue that there is a
genuine ethical consensus
that objecting pharmacists
should be forced to provide
drugs for euthanasia,
assisted suicide, or
post-coital interception.
Nor is it possible to argue
that such a consensus exists
on the issue of referral. In
this respect, it is
noteworthy that regulators
have sometimes see-sawed
back and forth: Ontario is
one case in point; the
present Draft Code of
Ethics for pharmacists
in Alberta is another.
XXIII.3 Instead, the
majority of responses
surveyed repeatedly attempt
to articulate what may be
reasonably required of a
conscientious objector,
short of referral or some
other kind of positive act.
The range of responses is
set out in
Appendix "A." 20 of 29
entities with policies
concerning freedom of
conscience fall within one
of two categories:
-
Systemic Cooperation
(13)
The objecting pharmacist
is not required to
directly assist in the
delivery of a drug or
service, but is to work
cooperatively within a
system that allows
patients to access
controversial drugs and
services through other
sources.
-
Personal Action or
Systemic Cooperation (7)
An objecting pharmacist
may directly assist in
the delivery of a drug
or service by referral
to a specific person or
entity, or by some other
act, OR work
cooperatively within a
system that allows
patients to access
controversial drugs and
services through other
sources.
Personal action or systemic
cooperation
XXIII.4 Referral requires a
positive action by an
objector to facilitate
euthanasia, assisted
suicide, post-coital
interception, etc. So, too,
does a policy like NAPRA's,
which demands that an
objector "pre-arrange access
to an alternate source."
Five Australian and two
Canadian pharmacy
authorities are described as
requiring either personal
action or systemic
cooperation. A closer look
at their responses is
warranted.
XXIII.5 The
1998 Code of Ethics
of the Pharmaceutical
Society of Australia states
that objecting pharmacists
have a duty to ensure
continuity of care, and,
"when required, assist and
refer clients to another
pharmacist" for that
purpose. Under what
circumstances assistance and
referral might be required
is not considered.
XXIII.6
However, the issue of
conscientious objection is
discussed at length in a
2003 Society policy
statement, Ethical Issues
in Declining to Supply.
At least four of Australia's
state pharmacy boards adhere
to standards set by the
Pharmaceutical Society of
Australia. It is reasonable
to assume that they are also
guided by this statement. It
does not insist upon
referral or assistance, but
advises that someone
(unspecified) may have to
"identify another reasonably
available source for the
required medicine or
service" if conscientious
objection results in
"nonsupply of a product or
service." It suggests that,
"where a pharmacist's moral
belief is likely to impact
on the pharmacy services
available to patients,"
pharmacists and their
employers should agree upon
strategies to accommodate
objectors and patients, and
steps should be taken by the
owner or manager to inform
patients of service
limitations and alternative
sources of pharmacy service.
The statement makes clear
that this kind of systemic
cooperation would be
consistent with the
Society's Code of Ethics,
although it cautions that
there might be other legal
ramifications for an
objector.
XXIII.7 The current
position of two Canadian
authorities, including the
Alberta College of
Pharmacists, is quite
similar to that of the five
Australian entities.
XXIII.8 The Alberta
College of Pharmacists
currently asserts that
objecting pharmacists "must
make reasonable efforts to
ensure that clients are able
to obtain these services
from another authorized
provider." More
specifically, it states that
objectors must "arrange the
condition of their practice"
to ensure continuity of
care, and advises them to
give timely notice of their
views to their employers,
presumably to enable their
employers to accommodate
both objectors and patients.
Thus, the "reasonable
efforts" envisioned could
include making the kind of
arrangements described in
XXIII.6,
and need not involve active
facilitation of euthanasia,
assisted suicide,
post-coital interception,
etc..
XXIII.9 The policy of the
Saskatchewan College of
Pharmacists on conscientious
objection is less precise.
It states that the
objector's duty of care
"might" require referral or
pre-arrangement of "access
to an alternate source,"
thus falling short of a
demand for referral. It is
reasonable to believe that
the arrangements described
in XXIII.6 would be
acceptable in Saskatchewan.
Systemic cooperation
XXIII.10 The majority of
responses indicate a
preference for what is here
described as "systemic
cooperation." A glance at a
few of the policies will
suffice to explain what this
means.
XXIII.11 The
Manitoba Pharmaceutical
Society requires objectors
"to participate in a system
designed to respect a
patient's right to receive
pharmacy products and
services," without further
specifying the nature of the
participation. The same
expectation is found in the
Codes of Ethics of pharmacy
colleges in New Brunswick
and Newfoundland, which add
that the system "must be
pre-arranged." They do not,
however, identify the party
responsible for the
pre-arrangement. Consistent
with these statements,
pharmacy authorities in Nova
Scotia and New Zealand
require objectors to notify
their managers, who are
charged with the duty of
arranging the practice to
accommodate objecting
pharmacists and patients.
Similarly, the American
Pharmacists Association
"supports the ability of the
pharmacist to step away, not
in the way, and supports the
establishment of an
alternative system for
delivery of patient care."
XXIII.12 The common
element in these policies is
that the responsibility to
arrange access to assisted
suicide, euthanasia or
post-coital interception is
not imposed on those who
object to these services,
but lies with those who do
not. What is required of
objecting pharmacists is
that they notify their
supervisors and colleagues
of their views and cooperate
with them as they
accommodate their
conscientious convictions
and the desires of patients.
They may not interfere with
arrangements being made by
others for assisted suicide,
euthanasia , post-coital
interception, etc., but they
are not expected to help
with them.
The key distinction
XXIII.13 The preceding
discussion highlights the
key distinction. Policies
that demand that objectors
make arrangements for
alternative delivery or
refer a patient require a
positive act, while those
that call for systemic
cooperation do not. The
result is same in both cases
(the patient accesses
euthanasia, assisted
suicide, post-coital
interceptives, etc.), but
the former demand active
participation by an objector
in conduct he believes to be
wrong.
XXIII.14 This explains
why objectors often
vehemently refuse demands
that they refer or otherwise
help a patient obtain
controversial services, but
may well be willing to work
cooperatively within a
system in which
controversial services are
provided by others.
XXIV. The way forward
XXIV.1 The furor that
resulted last year when it
was suggested that Ontario
physicians should be forced
to refer for abortion and
other controversial
procedures demonstrates that
a demand for referral is far
more likely to generate
significant and heated
resistance from objectors
than accommodation through a
policy of systemic
cooperation. Further, the
fact that the majority of
the pharmacy entities noted
in Appendices "A" to "C"
have already adopted this
approach suggests that
accommodation of
pharmacists' freedom of
conscience and patients'
desire for service can be
achieved in this way.
Modifying the approach
XXIV.2 Under a policy of
systemic cooperation, the
obligation to arrange access
to euthanasia, assisted
suicide, post-coital
interception, etc. lies with
pharmacy management, the
pharmacy owner or others,
not the objecting
pharmacist. The obvious
drawback to this is that it
effectively bars objecting
pharmacists from management
positions and ownership of
pharmacies. It is reasonable
to ask if a policy of
systemic cooperation can be
modified to reduce this
adverse effect.
XXIV.3
Such a modification is
suggested by the opening of
a pharmacy operating as an
entity of Divine Mercy Care,
a Catholic health care
organization, in Chantilly,
Virginia. DMC Pharmacy will
not dispense, recommend or
counsel for contraceptives
and will adhere to other
aspects of Catholic
teaching. The pharmacy
manager has expressed
gratitude for the
opportunity to work in an
environment that respects
his conscientious
convictions. The pharmacy is
intended to cater to "a
special niche" of people who
have similar views. Unlike
some other states that have
made ownership or management
of pharmacies impossible for
citizens who share such
convictions, Virginia does
not require pharmacies to
carry or refer for
contraceptives. NARAL
Pro-Choice America
recommends that the pharmacy
be boycotted because it
"doesn't respect [patient]
choices."
143
XXIV.4 The operation of
the pharmacy, on the one
hand, and the call for a
boycott, on the other,
demonstrates an appropriate
balance in the exercise of
freedom of conscience by
parties with different
views.
XXIV.5 Other suggestions
might be proposed, but it is
obvious that a policy of
systemic cooperation can be
modified so that it does not
require any positive act on
the part of pharmacists who
own pharmacies, or who
manage or are employed in
pharmacies that publicly
identify the scope of their
practice to exclude certain
services.
XXV. Summing up:
accommodating pharmacists
and patients
XXV.1 Issue No. 2: reprise.
Should the College of
Pharmacists of Alberta
include in its Code of
Ethics provisions that
honour and fully accommodate
the exercise of freedom of
conscience by pharmacists?
If so, how can this be done?
XXV.2 Part
XXII explains why the
Code of Ethics should
include specific provisions
to honour and fully
accommodate the exercise of
freedom of conscience by
pharmacists. Parts
XXIII and
XXIV suggest, in general
terms, the kind of policy
that would accommodate
objecting pharmacists and
the desire of patients for
pharmacy service.
XXV.3 Issue No. 2:
conclusion. The College of
Pharmacists of Alberta
should include in its Code of Ethics a
unambiguous policy of
accommodating freedom of
conscience through systemic
cooperation that does not
require active participation
by an objecting pharmacist
in conduct he believes to be
wrong. The policy should not
apply to pharmacists who
own, manage or are employed
in pharmacies that clearly
and publicly identify the
scope of their practice to
exclude certain services.
XXVI. Recapitulation
XXVI.1 The Draft Code of
Ethics does not address
the situation of a
pharmacist who, for reasons
of conscience, refuses to
fill a prescription for
assisted suicide, euthanasia
or post-coital interception.
Further, it fails to define
key terms, thus complicating
its application in such a
case.
XXVI.2 The failure
to define or limit key terms
strongly suggests that
pharmacists will be expected
to enhance access to
assisted suicide or
euthanasia, even if they
object to the procedures for
reasons of conscience. At
the least, a limitless
obligation to "enhance
access" provides limitless
opportunities to prosecute
objectors for professional
misconduct.
XXVI.3 This is
particularly troubling
because references to
accommodation of freedom of
conscience in the current Code have been removed
from the Draft Code.
It is not unreasonable to
believe that deletion of
reference to accommodation
of freedom of conscience and
the construction of the Draft Code are intended
to force objecting
pharmacists to enhance
access to euthanasia,
assisted suicide,
post-coital interception,
etc. (Part VIII, Draft
Code), and to compel
them to assist the patient
to obtain such services in a
timeframe acceptable to the
patient (Part V Draft
Code).
XXVI.4 To impose this
requirement would
effectively close the
profession of pharmacy to
anyone who finds such
conduct morally
unacceptable. It would
present current members who
would refuse to facilitate
assisted suicide, euthanasia
or post-coital interception
with the choice of
compromising their personal
integrity or leaving the
profession.
XXVI.5 Arguments commonly
advanced to support the
notion that pharmacists
should be forced to refer
services to which they
object for reasons of
conscience are faulty or
inadequate, in that they
fail to fully address the
issue of complicity in
wrongdoing and the nature of
the human person.
XXVI.6 A long
philosophical tradition,
stretching from at least
Immanuel Kant to R. vs.
Morgentaler and beyond,
insists that the nature of
the human person is such
that no one should be
exploited by another by
being reduced to the status
of a tool or thing: that it
is reprehensible to use a
human person for ends chosen
by others. Within this
tradition, self-sacrifice
has never been understood to
include the sacrifice of
one's integrity. To abandon
one's moral or ethical
convictions in order to
serve others is
prostitution, not
professionalism: servitude,
not service.
XXVI.7 In the tradition
of Kant, C.S. Lewis, Martin
Luther King, Cyril Joad and
Karol Wojtyla, and following
Madame Justice Wilson in
R. vs. Morgentaler, to
demand that pharmacists
provide or assist in the
provision of procedures or
services that they believe
to be wrong is to treat them
as means to an end and
deprive them of their
"essential humanity."
XXVI.8 A pharmacist's
conscientious refusal to
refer to refer patients or
assist them in obtaining
euthanasia, assisted
suicide, post-coital
interception, etc. should
not constitute professional
misconduct. The College of
Pharmacists of Alberta
should not demand that
pharmacists actively
facilitate a service or
procedure they believe to be
wrong. The Draft Code of
Ethics should be revised
to ensure that the document
cannot be used for this
purpose.
XXVI.9 The College of
Pharmacists of Alberta
should include in its Code of Ethics a
unambiguous policy of
accommodating freedom of
conscience through systemic
cooperation that does not
require active participation
by an objecting pharmacist
in conduct he believes to be
wrong. The policy should not
apply to pharmacists who
own, manage or are employed
in pharmacies that clearly
and publicly identify the
scope of their practice to
exclude certain services.
Prev | Next