To Market, To Market
Responding to Vischer, Robert,
The Pharmacist Wars
The American Enterprise Online
14 February, 2006
Full Text
"Have you used this product before?" a clerk in a green coat asks a
garden centre customer with a bottle of herbicide. The sale is accompanied
by a brief lesson about the "do's and don'ts" of using herbicide."
"Have you used this product before?" a pharmacist in a white coat asks a
customer with an antihistamine at the pharmacy counter across the store. The
customer gets a brief lesson about using antihistamine as the pharmacist
processes the sale.
Such encounters occur hundreds of thousands of times daily, often in
stores where the pharmacy counter is found behind aisle after aisle of a
cornucopia of consumer goods - especially in large chain stores and in
department stores. In these circumstances, it is not difficult to see why
people tend to think that a pharmacy is to a patient what a garden centre is
to a gardener: a 'point of sale' for specialized products.
"I'm looking for that new German beer I heard about on the radio," says
the customer to the cold beer and wine store employee. "Have you got any?"
The employee directs the customer to the appropriate shelf, or, if the new
beer isn't in stock, suggests a similar brand or something he thinks is even
better.
"I'm looking for that new flu medicine I heard about on TV," says the
customer to the pharmacist across the street. "Have you got any?" The
pharmacist obliges the customer if the product is in stock, or, perhaps,
suggests an alternative.
Again, these common occurrences illustrate the fact that interactions
between pharmacists and patients more often resemble what takes place in
garden centres and cold beer and wine stores than in physician consulting
rooms and hospitals. Pharmacists are frequently identified, in the public
eye, as employees who further their employers' business interests (or
businessmen who further their own) by getting a product into the hands of
paying customers. Such opinions are sometimes reinforced by pharmacists
themselves.1 Thus, the ground has
been well-prepared for arguments advanced by Professor Robert Vischer of the
University of St. Thomas Law School in Minneapolis.2
These are all the more interesting because they appear to come from a
politically and economically conservative perspective.
Professor Vischer makes some valid points. Among them, he comments that
even if one believes that "full access" to approved drugs is important, it
does not follow that all approved drugs must be carried by all pharmacies.
He also explains that one must distinguish "between inconvenience and lack
of access." Only the latter situation, he argues, should trigger state
intervention. This leads to a most curious result, given the subsequent
development of the argument: that if the state intervenes at all, it should
be to ensure consumer access to approved drugs, not be to ensure freedom of
conscience for health care workers.
How, then, is freedom of conscience to be ensured?
Expressing a degree of frustration at the "headline-grabbing" activism of
the "interest group armies," Professor Vischer suggests that the solution to
the problem has been overlooked because of a false premise shared by the
opposing sides: the erroneous notion that society consists of only two
entities, "the individual, and the state."
In reality, he asserts, American tradition (for he is speaking of the
American situation) respects not only individual freedom, but builds upon
the "principle of association." Individual citizens associate with one
another to pursue common interests, beliefs and outlooks. Thus, he proposes
that pharmacies institute their own polices - for or against conscientious
objection - and that employees and customers "utilize market power to
contest or embrace the morals of their choosing."
The result, he prophesies, will be "webs of morality-driven associations
and allegiances" within which individuals with different conscientious
convictions can thrive, a "marketplace where multiple conceptions of
morality can coexist." He argues that the kind of "ongoing conversation"
that must occur in such an environment is more effective in fostering social
ties than legislation imposed from above. In brief, his solution to
conflicts about freedom of conscience is to be found in a "vibrant
marketplace" energized by principles of laissez-faire capitalism.
It is at this point that the contradiction involved in Professor
Vischer's suggested criteria for state intervention comes into clearer
focus. For if it is merely a question of ensuring access to an approved
product, surely access is better guaranteed and more efficiently provided by
the rules of supply and demand in a free market than by state intervention.
On the other hand, the pressures exerted by supply and demand do not
necessarily or consistently produce and preserve fundamental human freedoms:
witness the institution of slavery in the United States.
It is remarkable that a free-market advocate should assign the state the
function of ensuring access to a product - an economic function admirably
achieved by free markets - while denying the state a role in the
preservation of fundamental freedoms - a political function for which it
exists. Happily, it is possible to resolve this contradiction, restoring to
the market and to the state the functions proper to each, and to do so in a
way that may prove congenial to Professor Vischer.
It is true, as he maintains, that there is more to society than
individuals and the state: that the "principle of association" must be taken
fully into account, along with (as he implies) the principle of
subsidiarity; that is, the state should not usurp or interfere unnecessarily
in the functions of lesser communities and associations. What is wanting is
recognition of the fact that the individuals who comprise the body politic,
including its associations and the state, are not merely individuals, but
individual human persons. That a human being is simultaneously a human
individual and a human person is emphasized by French philosopher Jacques
Maritain as the key to a correct understanding of the relationship between
the human person and society and the origin of human rights.3
Maritain's elaboration of this theme leads to a different conclusion than
that proposed by Professor Vischer, but, rather than nullifying his
observations, brings to them new and profound dimensions.
Maritain insists that the essential characteristic of a civilized society
is "respect and feeling for the dignity of the human person," for which, he
adds, "we must be ready to give our lives."4
The solemnity and force of this assertion becomes more evident when we
recall that it was written in the middle of the Second World War, when
Maritain's birthplace was in Nazi hands.
"What worth deserving of such sacrifice," he asks, "is then contained in
man's personality? What, precisely, do we mean when we speak of the human
person?"5
Man is an animal and an individual, but unlike other
animals or individuals. Man is an individual who holds himself in hand by
his intelligence and his will. He exists not merely physically; there is in
him a richer and nobler existence; he has a spiritual superexistence through
knowledge and through love. . . and through love he can give himself freely
to beings who are, as it were, other selves to him. For this relationship no
equivalent is to be found in the physical world.6
One finds in the physical world communities of sorts, like ant colonies,
comprised of individuals who contribute to a common work that preserves the
community (and, thus, the individuals that comprise it) by ensuring access
to necessary goods. The individual exists as part of a whole, like a cell
that has a function, surely, but no purpose or meaning apart from the
organism in which it subsists, and upon which it relies. T.H. White's King
Arthur, turned into an ant by Merlyn to learn something about political
philosophy, emerges from an ant colony in a rage:
It was not only that their language was destitute of
the words in which he was interested, so that it was impossible to ask them
whether they believed in Life, Liberty and the Pursuit of Happiness, but
also that it was dangerous to ask them questions at all. A question was a
sign of insanity to them because their life was not questionable: it was
dictated.7
Free market forces might efficiently dictate some of the functional
aspects of social and economic life, like the division of responsibilities
in labour and production; the market is competent to pass judgement on
function. But the nature of the human person and of human society is
transcendent,8 not merely functional, and it is
not appropriate to treat human persons as the merely functional parts of a
greater whole. This, Merlyn explains to the Badger, "is the totalitarian
theory: that men or ants exist for the sake of the state or world, not vice
versa."9
Maritain not only rejects this totalitarian view, but condemns it as
"political perversion."10 And if
one agrees that the human person does not exist for the sake of the state or
the world, one should also be chary of the notion that a pharmacist exists
for the sake of the pharmacy, or for the sake of a "vibrant marketplace."
Thus, Maritain also warns that if human persons are conceptually reduced to
the status of mere individuals pursuing individual goods or private
interests, the result will be a materialist culture in which the main duty
of the state will be to guarantee the freedom of each to follow these
pursuits without interference, "thereby enabling the strong freely to
oppress the weak."11 This outcome is
all the more likely if society is ordered, not according to principles of
justice, but in obedience to the blind forces of economic and social
Darwinism administered by Adam Smith's "invisible hand."12
The business of the market is the distribution of goods and services.
Food, for example, is an essential commodity that can be efficiently
produced and distributed in a free market; the state need not assume primary
responsibility for it, nor is it likely that the state could successfully
mandate and regulate "equal access" to all kinds, quantities and qualities
of food. But, in some circumstances - natural disasters, for instance - the
state ought to intervene to ensure that minimum human needs are met. This
principle can also be applied to drug distribution, though it is more
difficult to decide what constitutes a "minimum human need" for that
purpose: insulin? Plan B? AIDS drugs? oral contraceptives? cancer drugs?
mifepristone?
That difficulty notwithstanding, it is reasonable to acknowledge that the
state may intervene in the marketplace in order to ensure that minimum human
needs are met,13 because that is a
matter of justice, and the business of the state is justice.14State
intervention in the practice of pharmacy to ensure access to drugs is thus
authorized as an exception to the norms of a free market. But state
intervention in the practice of pharmacy to ensure freedom of conscience is
required as the rule according to the norms of a free country, which insist
upon minimum standards for the preservation of human dignity.
This does not mean, as Professor Vischer suggests, that pharmacies must
"honour the wishes" of every customer and every pharmacist. In the first
place, the goal of "wish fulfilment" does not recommend itself as an ethical
principle that ought to govern the practice of medicine or pharmacy. Beyond
that, state intervention to safeguard freedom of conscience typically takes
the form, not of limitless compulsion, but of limited prohibitions.
Employers and others are obliged only to abstain from certain kinds of
wrongful conduct, not compelled to do all that legislators or "interest
group armies" think desirable. In this respect, protection of conscience
legislation is actually less onerous than legislated medical or
pharmaceutical mandates. Like laws prohibiting racial discrimination in
employment and education, such legislation may be seen as an unwelcome
constraint in a free market, but it is a bulwark of liberty in a free
country.
Professor Vischer is correct to insist that problems of access to drugs
should be left to the marketplace (which is competent to manage the
distribution of goods and services), while acknowledging the duty of the
state to intervene when and to the extent necessary to ensure that minimal
human needs are met. However, deprivation of freedom of conscience is a
fundamental injustice, and justice is the primary concern of the state.
Thus, the state acts completely within its proper sphere of competence when
it intervenes to the extent necessary to protect the dignity of the human
person by enacting protection of conscience legislation.
This approach fully respects the different roles of market and state and
is not inconsistent with Professor Vischer's insistence that a solution to
the current controversy must be in accord with the principles of association
and subsidiarity.
Notes:
1. In May, 2000, Canadian pharmacist Gordon Stueck argued
against freedom of conscience on the grounds that it would endanger the
monopoly enjoyed by pharmacists in dispensing drugs. (Stueck, Gordon, "Here
we go again..." Pharmacy Practice, May 2000;Project
response ). Three years later, the Nevada legislative assembly rejected
a freedom of conscience measure because it "interfered with business
management" (Pearson, Ryan, "Nevada
panel: Drugs must be dispensed regardless of beliefs." Las Vegas Sun,
29 Apri, 2003. (Accessed 2006-03-22). In October, 2004, it was reported that
the British Columbia (Canada) Pharmacy Association supported the withdrawal
by pharmacists in remote areas from the Non-Insured Health Benefits (NIHB)
programme. A representative of BC Pharmacists for Conscience expressed
surprise at the "overwhelming support being given to pharmacists who
threaten to withhold services for economic reasons," in contrast to the lack
of support for pharmacists who decline to dispense certain drugs for reasons
of conscience. BC Pharmacists for Conscience News Release,Economics
Outweighs Ethical Principles in the Pharmacy Profession, 18 October,
2004.
2. Vischer, Robert,
The Pharmacist Wars. The American Enterprise Online, 14 February,
2006. (Accessed 2006-03-22)
3. Maritain, Jacques, (Doris C. Anson, Trans.) The
Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1943.
Reprinted New York: Gordian Press, 1971. One need not insist that Maritain's
is the only philosophy that can provide an adequate response to Professor
Vischer. It is sufficient, for present purposes, that it offers a plausible
alternative.
4. Ibid., p. 2
5. Ibid.
6. Ibid., p. 2-3
7. White, T.H., The Book of Merlyn: The unpublished
conclusion to the Once and Future King. Boston, Massachusetts: G.K. Hall
& Co., 1978, p. 96-97
8. Maritain, Jacques, (Doris C. Anson, Trans.) The
Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1943.
Reprinted New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 73-74
9. White, T.H., The Book of Merlyn: The unpublished
conclusion to the Once and Future King. Boston, Massachusetts: G.K. Hall
& Co., 1978, p. 111
10. Maritain, Jacques, (Doris C. Anson, Trans.) The
Rights of Man and Natural Law. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1943.
Reprinted New York: Gordian Press, 1971, p. 13- 17; Maritain, Jacques, Man
and the State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951 (Phoenix Edition,
1966) p. 13
11. Ibid. p. 8, 42
12. Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments
(Ed. D.D.Raphael and A.L. Macfie). Oxford University Press, 1976 (Liberty
Fund Edition, 1982), IV.I.10, p. 184
Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of he Wealth of
Nations (Ed. R.H. Campbell, A.S. Skinner). The Glasgow Edition of the
Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith, Oxford University Press, 1976
(Liberty Fund Edition, 1981), Vol. 1, IV.ii.9, p. 456
13. Given his subsequent arguments, this is probably
Professor Vischer's meaning.
14. Maritain, Jacques, Man and the State.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951. Phoenix Books, 12th Impression,
1966, p. 19-20